Skip to main content

Full text of "Marx & Engles The German Ideology"

See other formats


KARL 

MARX 

FREDERICK 

ENGELS 



Collected 

Works 

°§§° 

Wume 5 

Marx and Engds 
1845-1847 



Contents 

Preface XIII 

KARL MARX AND FREDERICK ENGELS 
WORKS 

April 1845-April 1847 

Karl Marx. Theses on Feuerbach [Original version] 3 

Karl Marx. Theses on Feuerbach [Edited by Engels] 6 

Frederick Engels. Feuerbach j i 

Karl Marx and Frederick Engels. A Reply to Bruno Bauer’s Anti- 

Critique 15 

Karl Marx and Frederick Engels. The German Ideology. Critique of 
Modern German Philosophy According to Its Representatives Feuerbach, 

B. Bauer and Stimer, and of German Socialism According to Its Various 
Prophets . 19 

Volume I. Critique of Modern German Philosophy According to Its 
Representatives Feuerbach, B. Bauer and Stimer 21 

Preface ... 23 

I. Feuerbach. Opposition of the Materialist and Idealist Outlooks 27 

[1] 27 

[l.J Ideology in General, German Ideology in Particular 28 

[2. Premises of the Materialist Conception of History] .. 31 

[3. Production and Intercourse. Division of Labour and Forms of 

Property — Tribal, Ancient, Feudal] 32 

[4. The Essence of the Materialist Conception of History. Social Being 

and Social Consciousness] , 35 

[II] 38 

[ 1 . Preconditions of the Real Liberation of Man] 38 

[2. Feuerbach’s Contemplative and Inconsistent Materialism] 38 




VI 



Contents 



[3. Primary Historical Relations, or the Basic Aspects of Social Activity: 
Production of the Means of Subsistence, Production of New Needs, 
Reproduction of Men (the Family), Social Intercourse, Conscious- 
ness] 41 

[4. Social Division of Labour and Its Consequences: Private Property, the 

State, “Estrangement” of Social Activity] 46 

[5. Development of the Productive Forces as a Material Premise of 

Communism] 48 

[6. Conclusions from the Materialist Conception of History: History as a 
Continuous Process, History as Becoming World History, the Necessi- 
ty of Communist Revolution] 50 

[7. Summary of the Materialist Conception of History] 53 

[8. The Inconsistency of the Idealist Conception of History in General 

and of German post-Hegelian Philosophy in Particular] 55 

[9. Idealist Conception of History and Feuerbach’s Quasi- 

Communism] 57 

[III] 59 

[1. The Ruling Class and the Ruling Ideas. How the Hegelian Conception 

of the Domination of the Spirit in History Arose] 59 

[IV] 63 

[ 1 . Instruments of Production and Forms of Property] 63 

[2. The Division of Material and Mental Labour. Separation of Town and 

Country. The Guild-System] 64 

[3. Further Division of Labour. Separation of Commerce and Industry. 

Division of Labour between the Various Towns. Manufacture] 66 

[4. Most Extensive Division of Labour. Large-Scale Industry] 72 

[5. The Contradiction between the Productive Forces and the Form of 

Intercourse as the Basis of Social Revolution] 74 

[6. Competition of Individuals and the Formation of Classes. Contradic- 
tion between Individuals and Their Conditions of Life. The Illusory 
Community of Individuals in Bourgeois Society and the Real Union of 
Individuals under Communism. Subordination of the Social Condi- 
tions of Life to the Power of the United Individuals] 75 

[7. Contradiction between Individuals and Their Conditions of Life as 
Contradiction between the Productive Forces and the Form of 
Intercourse. Development of the Productive Forces and the Changing 

Forms of Intercourse] 81 

[8. The Role of Violence (Conquest) in History] 84 

[9. Contradiction between the Productive Forces and the Form of 
Intercourse under the Conditions of Large-Scale Industry and Free 

Competition. Contradiction between Labour and Capital] 85 

[10. The Necessity, Preconditions and Consequences of the Abolition of 

Private Property] 87 

[11.] The Relation of State and Law to Property 89 

[12. Forms of Social Consciousness] 92 




Contents VII 

The Leipzig Council ; 94 

II. Saint Bruno 97 

1. “Campaign” against Feuerbach 97 

2. Saint Bruno’s Views on the Struggle between Feuerbach and Stirner 105 

3. Saint Bruno versus the Authors of Die Heilige Familie 107 

4. Obituary for “M. Hess” 114 

III. Saint Max 117 

1. The Unique and His Property 119 

The Old Testament: Man 121 

1. The Book of Genesis, i.e., A Man’s Life 121 

2. The Economy of the Old Testament 130 

3. The Ancients 136 

4. The Moderns 144 

A. The Spirit (Pure History of Spirits) 148 

B. The Possessed (Impure History of Spirits) 152 

a) The Apparition 157 

b) Whimsy 160 

C. The Impurely Impure History of Spirits 103 

a) Negroes and Mongols 163 

b) Catholicism and Protestantism 170 

D. Hierarchy 172 

5. “Stirner” Delighted in His Construction 185 

6. The Free Ones 193 

A. Political Liberalism 193 

B. Communism 205 

C. Humane Liberalism 232 

The New Testament: “Ego” 240 

1. The Economy of the New Testament 240 

2. The Phenomenology of the Egoist in Agreement with 

Himself, or the Theory of Justification 242 

3. The Revelation of John the Divine, or “The Logic of the New 

Wisdom” 272 

4. Peculiarity 301 

5. The Owner 315 

A. My Power 315 

I. Right 315 

A. Canonisation in General 315 

B. Appropriation by Simple Antithesis 319 

C. Appropriation by Compound Antithesis 321 

II. Law 327 

III. Crime 336 




VIII 



Contents 



A. Simple Canonisation of Crime and Punishment 337 

a. Crime ; 337 

b. Punishment . 339 

B. Appropriation of Crime and Punishment Through Antithesis 340 

C. Crime in the Ordinary and Extraordinary Sense 343 

[B. My Intercourse] 346 

[I. Society] 346 

5. Society as Bourgeois Society 348 

II. Rebellion 377 

III. Union 389 

1. Landed Property 389 

2. Organisation of Labour 391 

3. Money 395 

4. State 399 

5. Rebellion 402 

6. Religion and Philosophy of the Union 403 

A. Property 403 

B. Wealth 407 

C. Morality, Intercourse, Theory of Exploitation 408 

D. Religion 414 

E. Supplement to the Union 415 

C. My Self-Enjoyment 417 

6. Solomon’s Song of Songs or the Unique 427 

2. Apologetical Commentary -444 

Close of the Leipzig Council 451 

Volume II. Critique of German Socialism According to Its Various 
Prophets 453 

True Socialism 455 

I. Die Rheinischen Jahrbucher or the Philosophy of True Socialism 458 

A. “Communismus, Socialismus, Humanismus” 458 

B. “Socialisdsche Bausteine” 470 

First Cornerstone 474 

Second Cornerstone 477 

Third Cornerstone 480 

IV. Karl Griin: Die Soziale Bewegung in Frankreich und Belgien (Darmstadt, 

1845) or the Historiography of True Socialism 484 

Saint-Simonism 493 

1 . Lettres d'un habitant de Geneve d ses Contemporains 498 

2. Catechisme politique des Industriels 500 




Contents 



IX 



S. Nouveau christianisme 503 

4. The School of Saint-Simon 504 

Fourierism . 510 

•The “Limitations of Papa Cabet” and Herr Grun 519 

Proudhon 529 

V. “Doctor Georg Kuhlmann of Holstein” or the Prophecies of True 

Socialism 531 

Frederick Engels. The T rue Socialists 540 

NOTES AND INDEXES 

Notes 585 

Name Index 609 

Index of Quoted and Mentioned Literature . 627 

Index of Periodicals 64 1 

Subject Index .... 645 



ILLUSTRATIONS 



Facsimile of Thesis 1 1 on Feuerbach. From Marx’s notebook 9 

First page of the Preface to The German Ideology in Marx’s handwriting 25 

A page of the manuscript of The German Ideology. From the chapter 

“Feuerbach” ( Discovered in the early 1 960s) 34-35 

A page of the manuscript of The German Ideology. From the chapter 

“Feuerbach” 34“ 35 

A page of the manuscript of The German Ideology. From the chapter 

“Saint Max” ...226-227 

Max Stimer. Drawing by Engels 267 

First page of Chapter IV (Volume II) of The German Ideology as published 
in the Westpholische Dampfboot No. 8, 1847 487 




translators: 

CLEMENS DUTT: The German Ideology (Volume I, 
“The Leipzig Council”) and “The True So- 
cialists” 

W. LOUGH: The German Ideology (Volume I, Chapter I, 
“Feuerbach”) 

C. P. MAGILL: The German Ideology (Volume II) 




Preface 



The fifth volume of the Collected Works of Karl Marx and 
Frederick Engels contains a major joint work of the founders of 
Marxism, The German Ideology, together with the writings immediate- 
ly connected with it. 

They were all written between the spring of 1845 and the spring of 
1847, during Marx’s stay in Brussels, where he moved in February 
1845 following his deportation from France by the Guizot govern- 
ment. Engels came to Brussels from Barmen in April 1845 and 
remained till August 1846. This was the period when Marxism 
was finally evolved as the scientific world outlook of the revolu- 
tionary proletariat. Marx and Engels had arrived at the decisive 
stage in working out the philosophical principles of scientific com- 
munism. 

It was in The German Ideology that the materialist conception of 
history, historical materialism, was first formulated as an integral 
theory. Engels said later that this theory, which uncovered the gen- 
uine laws of social development and revolutionised the science of 
society, embodied the first of Marx’s great discoveries (the second 
being the theory of surplus value) which played the main role in 
transforming socialism from a utopia into a science. The German 
Ideology is in effect the first mature work of Marxism. It immediately 
preceded the first published mature Marxist writings — The Poverty of 
Philosophy and the Manifesto of the Communist Party. 

During the period when The German Ideology and the works closely 
connected with it were being written, Marx and Engels devoted their 
main efforts to joint theoretical and practical work aimed at setting 
out the revolutionary communist teaching and rallying around it the 
progressive elements of the proletariat and the revolutionary 
intelligentsia. Summing up the tasks they set themselves at that time, 




XIV 



Preface 



Engels wrote later, in his work “On the History of the Communist 
League”: “We were both already deeply involved in the political 
movement, and possessed a certain following in the educated world, 
especially of Western Germany, and abundant contact with the 
organised proletariat. It was our duty to provide a scientific 
foundation for our view, but it was equally important for us to win 
over the European and in the first place the German proletariat to 
our conviction.” 

Early in 1846, Marx and Engels founded the Brussels Communist 
Correspondence Committee, which took steps to establish interna- 
tional contacts between the participants in the working-class 
movement, to spread the new communist ideas and to prepare the 
ground for the creation of a revolutionary proletarian party. In 
August 1846, Engels, on the Committee’s instructions, moved to 
Paris to develop revolutionary propaganda among the German and 
French workers. 

The new revolutionary outlook of Marx and Engels was ham- 
mered out in struggle with bourgeois and petty-bourgeois ideology. 
They directed their criticism in the first place against the idealist 
conception of history inherent in German post-Hegelian philosophy, 
including that of Ludwig Feuerbach, whose materialist views were 
inconsistent and essentially metaphysical. 

The volume opens with Marx’s “Theses on Feuerbach”, of which 
Engels wrote in 1888 that they are “invaluable as the first document 
in which is deposited the brilliant germ of the new world outlook” 
(Foreword to Ludwig Feuerbach and the End of Classical German 
Philosophy). 

The “Theses on Feuerbach” were written in connection with the 
project of The German Ideology and represent the initial draft of a 
number of general ideas for the first chapter of this work. Nearly all 
the basic propositions of the “Theses” were further developed in 
The German Ideology. Essentially, they counterpose against contem- 
plative and passive pre-Marxian materialism the dialectical materialist 
conception of the decisive role of material practice in human 
cognition. Practice, Marx stressed, is the starting point, the basis, the 
criterion and the purpose of all cognition, including philosophical 
theory. And in order to become an effective and active factor of 
social development, theory must be embodied in living revolutionary 
practical activity. 

In the “Theses on Feuerbach” Marx put forward the materialist 
conception of “the essence of man”. In opposition to Feuerbach, 
who had only an abstract conception of “man” in isolation from 
social relations and historical reality, Marx emphasised that real 




Preface 



XV 



men could only be understood as products of social relations. Marx 
then went much further than Feuerbach in the critical comprehen- 
sion of religion and the ways of overcoming it. He pointed out that it 
was not enough to understand the earthly basis of religion. The 
condition for eliminating religion, the “Theses” underline, is the 
revolutionary elimination of the social contradictions which give rise 
to it. 

Particularly important is the eleventh thesis, which says: “The 
philosophers have only interpreted the world in various ways; the 
point is to change it” (see this volume, p. 5). Marx himself separated 
this thesis from the preceding ten, as though underlining its 
summarising character. We must understand the world in order to 
change it, instead of interpreting it one way or another in order to 
reconcile ourselves with what exists. Such in substance is the true 
meaning of this thesis. Organically connected with it is another 
thought. The world cannot be changed by merely changing our 
notions of it, by theoretically criticising what exists; it must be 
understood, and then, proceeding from this, transformed by 
effective action, material revolutionary practice. This thesis 
concisely formulates the fundamental difference of Marxist 
philosophy from all earlier philosophy, including pre-Marxian 
materialism. It concentrates into a single sentence the effective, 
transforming character of the revolutionary theory created by 
Marx and Engels, its inseparable connection with revolutionary 
practice. 

The basic principles of the new scientific world outlook, which 
Marx had formulated in the “Theses on Feuerbach”, were 
developed in The German Ideology. This work comprises two volumes. 
Volume I is devoted to criticism of the views of Ludwig Feuerbach, 
Bruno Bauer and Max Stirner, and Volume II to criticism of “true 
socialism”. Despite all the efforts of Marx and Engels to have The 
German Ideology published, it did not appear in print during their 
lifetime, except for one chapter of Volume II. This circumstance 
does not, however, diminish its significance. In working on The 
German Ideology , Marx and Engels first and foremost clarified to 
themselves the basic aspects of the new world outlook. “We 
abandoned the manuscript to the gnawing criticism of the mice all 
the more willingly as we had achieved our main purpose — self- 
clarification,” Marx wrote in 1859 in the preface to A Contribution to 
the Critique of Political Economy. The conclusions Marx and Engels 
reached constituted the theoretical basis for all their further 
scientific and political activity. They were able to impart them to 
their closest associates — future prominent proletarian revolu- 




XVI 



Preface 



tionaries. And they soon found an opportunity of making their 
conclusions public after giving them a more finished and perfect 
form. This was done in The Poverty of Philosophy, by Marx, and the 
Manifesto of the Communist Party, by Marx and Engels. 

The German Ideology is remarkable for the great wealth and variety 
of its content, since the ideas developed in it relate to many aspects of 
the revolutionary teaching which was taking shape. Thus profound 
thoughts were expressed on questions pertaining to the theory and 
history of the state and of law, to linguistics, aesthetics and literary 
criticism. Not only were post-Hegelian philosophy and “true 
socialism” subjected to a detailed critical analysis, but digressions 
were also made into the history of philosophy and of socialist 
theories. And the new materialist interpretation of the history of 
social thought was in particular reflected in the positive treatment of 
the great social thinkers of the past. 

The German Ideology is the continuation of previous works by Marx 
and Engels, mainly of the Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts 
of 1844 and The Holy Family, and in a sense synthesises the ideas 
contained in them. At the same time, an immense step forward was 
made to a qualitatively new stage in the development of the 
philosophical foundations of the revolutionary proletarian outlook. 
It was in this work that for the first time the materialist way of under- 
standing history became an integral conception of the structure of 
society and of historical periodisation. By virtue of the general 
dialectical law of the transformation of theory into method and of 
the unity of world oudook and method, organically inherent in the 
new revolutionary teaching, this conception appears in The German 
Ideology not only as the theory of society, but also as the method of 
understanding social and historical phenomena. Marx and Engels 
gave science a powerful weapon for the knowledge of social life, a 
means of elucidating both the general course of social development 
and the existing social relations. Thus they made possible the 
comprehension of social processes which is necessary for active and 
revolutionary interference in them. Marx himself saw in this work 
the methodological prerequisite for a new political economy. In a 
letter to the German publisher Leske on August 1, 1846, he pointed 
out that the publication of a polemical work against the German 
philosophers was necessary in order to prepare readers for his point 
of view in the field of economic science. 

The German Ideology is a polemical work. Criticism of views 
hostile to the proletarian world oudook occupies a predominant 
place in it, often couched in a biting satirical form which gives it 
particular force and expressiveness. In the course of their attacks, 




Preface 



XVII 



Marx and Engels continually counterposed their own point of view 
to the views they were criticising. 

Chapter I of Volume I of The German Ideology occupies a special 
place in the work as a whole. Unlike the other chapters, which are 
mainly polemical, it was conceived as a general introduction 
expounding the materialist conception of history. The basic 
theoretical content of the whole work is indeed concentrated in this 
chapter. 

First of all Marx and Engels formulate the “premises” of the 
materialist conception of history. These premises are the real living 
people, their activity and the material conditions under which they 
live, both the conditions which they find already existing and those 
produced by their activity. Thus, what is underlined here is the 
historical character of the material conditions themselves, which are 
increasingly influenced by people’s activity. And there are two sides 
to it. First, production (people’s active relation to nature, their 
influence on it), and, secondly, intercourse (people’s relations to one 
another in their activity). Production and intercourse determine each 
other, but the decisive side of this mutual action is production. 
Subsequently, Marx and Engels introduced the term “relations of 
production” to distinguish the social relations people enter into in 
production, which are the basic relations underlying everything 
included under the term “intercourse”. 

In The German Ideology Marx and Engels not only developed in all 
its aspects the thesis of the decisive role of material production in the 
life of society, which they had already formulated in their previous 
works, they also revealed for the first time the dialectics of the 
development of the productive forces and the relations of produc- 
tion. This most important discovery was formulated here as the 
dialectics of the productive forces and the form of intercourse. It 
illuminated the whole conceptual system of historical materialism 
and made it possible to expound the substance of the materialist way 
of understanding history as an integral scientific conception. 

This discovery' can be reduced to the following propositions. The 
productive forces determine the form of intercourse (social rela- 
tions). At a certain stage of their development, the productive forces 
come into contradiction with the existing form of intercourse. This 
contradiction is resolved by social revolutions. In the place of the 
previous form of intercourse, which has become a fetter, a new one is 
evolved which corresponds to the more developed productive forces. 
Subsequently, this new form of intercourse in its turn ceases to 
correspond to £he developing productive forces, turns into their 
fetter and is replaced by an ensuing, historically more progressive 



2—2086 




XVIII 



Preface 



form of intercourse. Thus, in the course of the entire historical 
development a link of continuity is established between successive 
stages. In disclosing the laws of social development, Marx and Engels 
arrived at a conclusion of immense significance: “... All collisions in 
history have their origin, according to our view, in the contradiction 
between the productive forces and the form of intercourse” (see this 
volume, p. 74). 

The discovery of the laws of social development provided the key to 
the scientific understanding of the entire historical process. It served 
as the point of departure for the scientific periodisation of history. 
Thus, as Lenin commented: “His [Marx’s] historical materialism was 
a great achievement in scientific thinking. The chaos and arbitrari- 
ness that had previously reigned in views on history and politics were 
replaced by a strikingly integral and harmonious scientific theory, 
which shows how, in consequence of the growth of the productive 
forces, out of one system of social life another and higher system 
develops — how capitalism, for instance, grows out of feudalism” 
( Collected Works, Vol. 19, p. 25). 

In The German Ideology Marx and Engels investigated the basic 
determinants of the sequence of phases in the historical development 
of social production. They showed that the outward expression of 
the level of development of the productive forces is always to be 
found in that of the division of labour. Each stage in the division of 
labour determines a corresponding form of property and, as Marx 
subsequently pointed out, the property relations are but “the legal 
expression” of the relations of production. The transition from 
primary historical relations to the ensuing stage in social develop- 
ment was determined by the development of the productive forces, 
resulting in the transition from an initial, natural division of labour 
to the social division of labour in the form which is expressed in the 
division of society into classes. This was the transition from pre-class 
to class society. 

Along with the social division of labour there develop such 
derivative historical phenomena as private property, the state and 
the “estrangement” of social activity. Just as the natural division of 
labour in primitive society determines the first, tribal (family) form 
of property so the increasing social division of labour determines the 
further development and change of the forms of property. The 
second form of property is the “ancient communal and state 
property”, the third form is “feudal or estate property” and the 
fourth is “bourgeois property”. The singling out and analysis of 
forms of property which successively replace one another and 
dominate at different stages of historical development provided the 




basis for the scientific Marxist theory of the social formations, the 
successive replacement of which is the principal feature of the whole 
historical process. 

Marx and Engels examined the last, the bourgeois, form of private 
property in greater detail than the other historical forms of 
property, tracing its transition from the guild-system to manufacture 
and large-scale industry. This was the first time that these two 
principal stages in the development of bourgeois society, the 
manufacture period and the period of large-scale industry, had been 
singled out and analysed. Marx had already demonstrated in the 
Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844 that the emer- 
gence of private property was historically conditioned, that it 
must necessarily come into being at a certain stage in the 
development of human society, and also that it must inevitably be 
subsequently abolished. It was proved in The German Ideology that it 
is only with the development of large-scale industry that the material 
conditions are created for the abolition of private property in the 
means of production. And it becomes evident that this abolition is 
necessary. 

Proceeding from production to the sphere of intercourse, i.e., of 
social relations, the social system, Marx and Engels gave a materialist 
interpretation of the class structure of society and demonstrated the 
role of classes and the class struggle in social life. In The German 
Ideology, as compared with the Economic and Philosophic Manu- 
scripts of 1844 and The Holy Family, the Marxist theory of classes 
and class struggle acquired mature features — those very features 
which, as Marx noted in his letter to Weydemeyer of March 5, 1852, 
distinguished this theory from the progressive bourgeois historians’ 
understanding of class struggle. It was demonstrated that the 
division of society into antagonistic classes and the existence of 
classes are connected with definite stages in the development of 
production, that the development of the class struggle must 
necessarily lead to a communist revolution carried out by the pro- 
letariat, and that this revolution will result in the abolition of classes 
and the creation of a classless society. 

In The German Ideology considerable attention is devoted to the 
political superstructure, and in particular to the relation of the state 
and law to property. For the first time the essence of the state in 
general and the bourgeois state in particular was revealed. “... The 
state is the form in which the individuals of a ruling class assert their 
common interests, and in which the whole civil society of an epoch is 
epitomised” (see this volume, p. 90). In analysing the class nature and 
the main functions of the state at the capitalist stage of development, 




XX 



Preface 



Marx and Engels pointed out that the bourgeois state “is nothing 
more than the form of organisation which the bourgeois are 
compelled to adopt, both for internal and external purposes, for the 
mutual guarantee of their property and interests” (see this volume, 
p. 90). 

In dealing with the various forms of social consciousness, the 
ideological superstructure, Marx and Engels made clear the general 
correlation between the material sphere and the sphere of conscious- 
ness. Of particular importance is the classical formulation of the 
materialist solution to this basic question of philosophy: “Conscious- 
ness [das Bewusstsein ] can never be anything else than conscious being 
[das bewusste Sein], and the being of men is their actual life-process.... 
It is not consciousness that determines life, but life that determines 
consciousness” (see this volume, pp. 36-37). The formation of 
consciousness is immensely influenced by the class structure of 
society. In their work Marx and Engels disclosed the class origins 
of the various forms of consciousness and showed that in a class 
society the dominating consciousness is the consciousness of the 
ruling class. 

Summing up the substance of the materialist conception of history, 
Marx and Engels wrote: “This conception of history thus relies on 
expounding the real process of production — starting from the 
material production of life itself — and comprehending the form of 
intercourse connected with and created by this mode of production, 
i.e., civil society in its various stages, as the basis of all history; 
describing it in its action as the state, and also explaining how all the 
different theoretical products and forms of consciousness, religion, 
philosophy, morality, etc., etc., arise from it, and tracing the process 
of their formation from that basis; thus the whole thing can, of 
course, be depicted in its totality (and therefore, too, the reciprocal 
action of these various sides on one another). It has not, like the 
idealist view of history, to look for a category in every period, but 
remains constantly on the real ground of history; it does not explain 
practice from the idea but explains the formation of ideas from 
material practice, and accordingly it comes to the conclusion that ... 
not criticism but revolution is the driving force of history, also of 
religion, of philosophy and all other kinds of theory” (see this 
volume, pp. 53-54). 

In their subsequent scientific work, Marx and Engels constantly 
developed and deepened their materialist conception of history and 
perfected the method of historical materialism by applying it in the 
various fields of the social sciences. The whole system of con- 
cepts — which in The German Ideology still bears the stamp of the 




Preface 



XXI 



formation process of the conception itself — was thus elaborated and 
made more precise, and the basic explanatory ideas of historical ma- 
terialism were expressed in a more adequate terminology. In later 
works of Marx and Engels the various aspects of the concept “mode 
of production”, a basic term in historical materialism, were 
expounded; the internal law of development of the modes of 
production began to be formulated in terms of the dialectical 
interaction of productive forces and relations of production, and the 
latter were shown to play the main, decisive role — as was made clear 
already in The German Ideology — in the system of social relations. The 
term “social formation” first appeared in Marx’s economic manu- 
script of 1857-58, Critique of Political Economy (the so-called Grund- 
risse), and the concept “social-economic formation” was first thor- 
oughly expounded in the preface to his A Contribution to the Critique 
of Political Economy ( 1 859), thus providing for the better understand- 
ing of the successive replacement of social formations, the general 
outline of which was given in The German Ideology. It should be 
noted, too, that in the light of the subsequent development of the 
theory of scientific communism it becomes evident that, in speaking 
in The German Ideology of the “abolition of the division of labour”, 
and even of the “abolition of labour”, in communist society, Marx 
and Engels had in mind only the division of labour in the conditions 
of class-divided society — with its antithesis between mental and 
physical labour and people being tied down to certain occupations 
and professions — and, in particular, the capitalist form of the 
exploitation of labour, not work and its organisation in general. 

The classical formulation of the basic propositions of the 
materialist conception of history was later set down by Marx in the 
already-mentioned preface to his book A Contribution to the Critique of 
Political Economy. 

This scientific materialist theory of social development served 
Marx and Engels as the theoretical foundation for their conclusions 
about the communist transformation of society. The principal 
conclusion from the materialist conception of history, already 
substantiated in The German Ideology, is the historical necessity of a 
proletarian, communist revolution. Marx and Engels stressed that 
“for the practical materialist, i.e., the communist, it is a question 
of revolutionising the existing world, of practically coming to 
grips with and changing the things found in existence” (see this 
volume, pp. 38-39). 

The development of the productive forces within bourgeois society, 
Marx and Engels pointed out, provides the two basic material 
premises of a communist revolution. These are: first, a high 




XXII 



Preface 



level of production, which is incompatible with private property and 
at the same time is necessary for the organisation of society on a 
communist basis; and, secondly, mass proletarianisation, the forma- 
tion of the proletariat, the most revolutionary class in modern 
society. This definition of the premises of a communist revolution 
is one of the fundamental conclusions of scientific communism 
contained in The German Ideology. 

It was in The German Ideology that Marx and Engels first spoke of 
the necessity for the proletariat to conquer political power as the only 
way of carrying out a communist revolution. They pointed out: 
“... Every class which is aiming at domination, even when its 
domination, as is the case with the proletariat, leads to the abolition of 
the old form of society in its entirety and of all domination, must first 
conquer political power” (see this volume, p. 47). Thus we find 
expressed for the first time the idea of the dictatorship of the 
proletariat, though as yet only in a most general form. 

Marx and Engels stressed that a communist revolution is a dual 
process: a change in people’s conditions of life, and at the same time 
a change in the people themselves who carry out the revolution. This 
thought, already contained in the ‘‘Theses on Feuerbach”, was given 
its classical formulation in The German Ideology : “... The revolution is 
necessary, therefore, not only because the ruling class cannot be 
overthrown in any other way, but also because the class overthrowing 
it can only in a revolution succeed in ridding itself of all the muck 
of ages and become fitted to found society anew” (see this vol- 
ume, p. 53). 

The German Ideology expounds the basic features of future 
communist society — the abolition of private property, of the class 
division of labour and of classes themselves, the transformation of 
production and all the social relations, and the disappearance of the 
state, the instrument of class domination. People’s own activity will 
cease to confront them as a power alien to them. The antagonism 
between town and country and between mental and physical labour 
will be eliminated. Labour will be transformed from activity people 
perform under compulsion into the genuine self-activity of free 
people. The real liberation and all-round development of every 
individual will be the highest aim of the communist organisation of 
society. 

This view of the future communist society is presented in The 
German Ideology for the first time as an integral theory, free from all 
the artificial, dogmatic construing of the future system which was 
typical of the utopian Socialists despite all the brilliant conjectures 
they made. The foresight of Marx and Engels was based on an 




Preface 



XXIII 



analysis of the real tendencies of social development and was the 
result of comprehension of its real laws. By expounding the specific 
features of future communism, Marx and Engels were laying the 
foundations of the scientific forecasting of social processes. 

Not only the positive aspect of The German Ideology, the exposition 
of the authors’ views, but also the critical content of this work was of 
great significance in shaping the new revolutionary world outlook. 
This criticism was mainly directed against the idealist conceptions of 
German post-Hegelian philosophy. And by subjecting the views of 
the German philosophers to a critical analysis, Marx and Engels in 
fact presented a radical and scientifically based criticism of previous 
philosophical thought as a whole. They demonstrated the untenabili- 
ty of the idealist interpretations of history inherent in all previous 
philosophy, sociology and historiography. The thinkers working in 
these fields could never understand the real social processes and 
their true character. At best they could grasp and more or less 
correctly describe only individual aspects of these processes without 
seeing the general connections determining them. The idealist 
interpretation of history, The German Ideology underlined, leads to 
only a superficial and illusory perception of the historical process, 
and explains it in an illusory way. The socialist theories based on a 
similar interpretation were likewise incapable of going beyond the 
bounds of fantastic notions and utopias. 

A large part of The German Ideology is occupied by criticism of the 
Young Hegelians Bruno Bauer and Max Stirner. The need for 
such criticism arose, as Engels pointed out, from the fact that 
Bauer and Stirner were “the representatives of the ultimate 
consequences of abstract German philosophy, and therefore the only 
important philosophical opponents of Socialism — or rather Com- 
munism ...” (see present edition, Vol. 4, p. 241). 

The German Ideology completes the criticism, begun in The Holy 
Family, of the subjective-idealist views of Bruno Bauer, with their 
mystification of the historical process and contraposition of the 
outstanding individuals, who were supposed to be the sole makers of 
history, to the “passive and inert” masses. By citations from the latest 
writings of Bruno Bauer and other Young Hegelians, Marx and 
Engels drove home their characterisation, given in The Holy Family, 
of Young Hegelian ideas as unscientific and anti-revolutionary. In 
this respect there is partial textual coincidence between the 
corresponding chapter in The German Ideology and the article “A 
Reply to Bruno Bauer’s Anti-Critique” written by Marx and Engels 
in refutation of the Young Hegelian leader’s attempt to dispute their 
criticism of his views in The Holy Family. 




XXIV 



Preface 



Most of the first volume of The German Ideology is taken up by a 
critical examination of the philosophical and sociological views of 
Max Stirner, formulated in his book Der Einzige und sein Eigenthum 
( The Unique and His Property). Stirner was a typical exponent of 
individualism and one of the first ideologists of anarchism. His views, 
reflecting a petty-bourgeois protest against the bourgeois system, 
enjoyed a considerable success among petty-bourgeois intellectuals 
and to some extent influenced the immature outlook of craftsmen 
who were becoming proletarians, while his failure to understand the 
role of the proletariat, whom he identified with paupers, and also his 
attacks on communism, made a resolute exposure of his views 
indispensable. 

Marx and Engels demonstrated the artificial and far-fetched 
character of Stirner’s philosophical and sociological constructions 
and the fallacy of his theory that the way to the liberation of the 
individual lay through the destruction of the state and the implemen- 
tation of every individual’s egoistic right to self-assertion. They 
pointed out that Stirner’s voluntaristic appeals to the rights of the 
individual did not in any way affect the existing social relations and 
their economic basis, and so, in effect, continued to sanction the 
preservation of the bourgeois social conditions which are the main 
source of inequality and oppression of the individual. Stirner’s 
seemingly revolutionary phrases were in fact a disguise for an 
apologia of the bourgeois system. 

The exposure of Stirner’s anarchist views in The German Ideology 
was essentially a criticism of all such individualistic theories which 
substitute fruitless rebellion by isolated individuals for participation 
in the real revolutionary movement and preach total negation and 
destruction instead of the positive communist aims of struggle. Marx 
and Engels pointed out that the path outlined by Stirner and his like 
could by no means lead to the liberation of the individual. Only a 
communist revolution, carried out by the working class in the 
interests of all the working people, can break the fetters with which 
the individual is shackled by the existing capitalist system, and can 
lead to the genuine freedom and free development of the individual, 
to harmonious unity of public and personal interests. 

The second volume of The German Ideology and Engels’ manuscript 
“The True Socialists”, which is its direct continuation, further 
show that, in substance, German “true socialism” was only a philistine 
variety of earlier petty-bourgeois social utopianism and that, under 
the pretence of “universal love for man”, the “true socialists” were 
spreading ideas of class peace, renouncing the struggle for 
democratic freedoms and revolutionary change. This was particular- 




Preface 



XXV 



ly dangerous at the time in Germany, where the struggle of all the 
democratic forces against absolutism and feudal relations was 
growing sharper while at the same time the contradictions between 
the proletariat and the bourgeoisie were becoming more and more 
acute. Marx and Engels likewise subjected to devastating criticism 
the German nationalism of the “true socialists” and their arrogant 
attitude to other nations. They criticised in detail the philosophical 
views of the “true socialists”, their aesthetic views, and the tendency 
of some of them to give socialism a religious tinge and to impart to 
it the character of a religious prophecy. 

Both by its positive ideas and by its criticism of ideological trends 
hostile to the proletarian world outlook, including those couched in 
pseudo-revolutionary and socialist phrases, The German Ideology 
represented an important landmark in the development of Marxism. 
This work signified a decisive stage in the philosophical and 
sociological grounding of the theory of scientific communism, in the 
scientific demonstration of the world-historic role of the working 
class as the social force whose historical mission is to overthrow the 
exploiting capitalist system and create the new communist society. 

* * * 



The works contained in this volume have been translated from the 
original German text. The German Ideology, which forms the greater 
part of this volume, was never published in the authors’ lifetimes, 
except for one chapter, nor arranged by them for publication, and 
has come down to us incomplete. The text of The German Ideology has 
been re-checked and re-arranged in accordance with the researches 
of the Institute of Marxism-Leninism of the Central Committee of 
the Communist Party of the Soviet Union, with a view to presenting 
it in a form corresponding as closely as possible to the layout and 
content of the manuscript. In particular, Chapter I, “Feuerbach”, 
which was not finished by the authors and has reached us only in the 
form of several separate manuscripts, is presented in accordance 
with the new arrangement and subdivision of the text prepared by 
Georgi Bagaturia and edited by Vladimir Brushlinsky (first pub- 
lished in English in Karl Marx and Frederick Engels, Selected Works , 
Progress Publishers, Moscow, 1969, Vol. 1, and also separately under 
the title Karl Marx and Frederick Engels, Feuerbach: Opposition of the 
Materialist and Idealist Outlooks, Lawrence & Wishart, London 1973). 

The whole work on this volume has been finalised by Lev 
Churbanov. He also prepared the Preface, the Notes and the Subject 




XXVI 



Preface 



Index, which have been edited by Lev Golman (both of the Institute 
of Marxism-Leninism). 

The Name Index, the Index of Quoted and Mentioned Literature 
and the Index of Periodicals were prepared by Nina Loiko, of the 
Institute of Marxism-Leninism. 

The English translation of the bulk of The German Ideology, i.e., 
“The Leipzig Council”, and also Engels’ essay “The True Socialists”, 
was made by Clemens Dutt. The translation of Chapter I, 
“Feuerbach”, Volume I, was made by W. Lough, and that of 
Volume II by C. P. Magill, these two sections having been edited by 
Roy Pascal for the English edition published by Lawrence 8c Wishart, 
London, in 1938. 

The English translations were edited for this volume by Maurice 
Cornforth, E. J. Hobsbawm and Margaret Mynatt for Lawrence & 
Wishart, and Salo Ryazanskaya, for Progress Publishers, and finally 
passed for the press by the editors Lydia Belyakova, Nadezhda 
Rudenko and Victor Schnittke, Progress Publishers. 

The scientific editing was done by Georgi Bagaturia and Norair 
Ter- Akopyan (Institute of Marxism-Leninism). 




KARL MARX 
and 

FREDERICK ENGELS 



WORKS 

April 1845-April 1847 




Karl Marx 



[THESES ON FEUERBACH 3 ] 



1) ad FEUERBACH 1 

1 

The chief defect of all previous materialism (that of Feuerbach 
included) is that things [Gegenstand], reality, sensuousness 
are conceived only in the form of the object, or of contemplation, but 
not as sensuous human activity, practice, not subjectively. Hence, in 
contradistinction to materialism, the active side was set forth 
abstractly by idealism — which, of course, does not know real, 
sensuous activity as such. Feuerbach wants sensuous objects, really 
distinct from conceptual objects, but he does not conceive human 
activity itself as objective activity. In Das Wesen des Christenthums, he 
therefore regards the theoretical attitude as the only genuinely 
human attitude, while practice is conceived and defined only in its 
dirty-Jewish form of appearance . 2 Hence he does not grasp the 
significance of “revolutionary”, of “practical-critical”, activity. 



2 



The question whether objective truth can be attributed to human 
thinking is not a question of theory but is a practical question. Man 
must prove the truth, i.e., the reality and power, the this-worldliness 
of his thinking in practice. The dispute over the reality or non-reality 
of thinking which is isolated from practice is a purely scholastic 
question. 



Original version. — Ed. 




4 



Karl Marx 



3 

The materialist doctrine concerning the changing of cir- 
cumstances and upbringing forgets that circumstances are changed 
by men and that the educator must himself be educated. This 
doctrine must, therefore, divide society into two parts, one of which 
is superior to society. 

The coincidence of the changing of circumstances and of human 
activity or self-change can be conceived and rationally understood 
only as revolutionary practice. 



4 

Feuerbach starts out from the fact of religious self-estrangement, 
of the duplication of the world into a religious world and a secular 
one. His work consists in resolving the religious world into its secular 
basis. But that the secular basis lifts off from itself and establishes 
itself as an independent realm in the clouds can only be explained by 
the inner strife and intrinsic contradictoriness of this secular basis. 
The latter must, therefore, itself be both understood in its contradi- 
ction and revolutionised in practice. Thus, for instance, once the 
earthly family is discovered to be the secret of the holy family, the 
former must then itself be destroyed in theory and in practice. 

5 

Feuerbach, not satisfied with abstract thinking, wants [sensuous] 
contemplation; but he does not conceive sensuousness as practical, 
human-sensuous activity. 



6 

Feuerbach resolves the essence of religion into the essence of man. 
But the essence of man is no abstraction inherent in each single 
individual. In its reality it is the ensemble of the social relations. 

Feuerbach, who does not enter upon a criticism of this real 
essence, is hence obliged: 

1. To abstract from the historical process and to define the 
religious sentiment [Gemiit] by itself, and to presuppose an 
abstract — isolated — human individual. 

2. Essence, therefore, can be regarded only as “species”, as an 
inner, mute, general character which unites the many individuals in 
a natural way. 




Theses on Feuerbach 



5 



7 

Feuerbach, consequently, does not see that the “religious senti- 
ment” is itself a social product, and that the abstract individual which 
he analyses belongs to a particular form of society. 

8 

All social life is essentially practical. All mysteries which lead theory 
to mysticism find their rational solution in human practice and in the 
comprehension of this practice. 



9 

The highest point reached by contemplative materialism, that is, 
materialism which does not comprehend sensuousness as practical 
activity, is the contemplation of single individuals and of civil society. 



10 

The standpoint of the old materialism is civil society; the 
standpoint of the new is human society, or social humanity. 



11 

The philosophers have only interpreted the world in various ways; 
the point is to change it. 

Written in the spring of 1845 

This version was first published in 
1 924 — in German and in Russian — by 
the Institute of Marxism-Leninism 
of the Central Committee of the C.P.S.U 
in Marx-Engels Archives, Book I, Moscow 



Printed according to the manu- 
script 




Karl Marx 



[THESES ON FEUERBACH 3 ] 



MARX ON FEUERBACH 
( Written in Brussels in the spring of 1845) 



The chief defect of all previous materialism — that of Feuerbach 
included — is that things [ Gegenstand ], reality, sensuousness are 
conceived only in the form of the object , or of contemplation, but not as 
human seTisuous activity, practice, not subjectively. Hence it happened 
that the active side t in contradistinction to materialism, was set forth by 
idealism — but only abstractly, since, of course, idealism does not know 
real, sensuous activity as such. Feuerbach wants sensuous objects, 
really distinct from conceptual objects, but he does not conceive 
human activity itself as objective activity. In Das Wesen des Christen- 
thums, he therefore regards the theoretical attitude as the only ge- 
nuinely human attitude, while practice is conceived and defined only 
in its dirty-Jewish form of appearance. Hence he does not grasp the 
significance of “revolutionary”, of practical-critical, activity. 



2 

The question whether objective truth can be attributed to human 
thinking is not a question of theory but is a practical question. Man 
must prove the truth, i.e., the reality and power, the this-worldliness 
of his thinking in practice. The dispute over the reality or non-reality 
of thinking which isolates itself from practice is a purely scholastic 
question. 



Edited by Engels. — Ed. 




Theses on Feuerbach 



7 



3 

The materialist doctrine that men are products of circumstances 
and upbringing, and that, therefore, changed men are products of 
other circumstances and changed upbringing, forgets that it is men 
who change circumstances and that the educator must himself be 
educated. Hence, this doctrine is bound to divide society into two 
parts, one of which is superior to society (in Robert Owen, for 
example). 

The coincidence of the changing of circumstances and of human 
activity can be conceived and rationally understood only as 
revolutionising practice. 



4 

Feuerbach starts out from the fact of religious self-estrangement, 
of the duplication of the world into a religious, imaginary world and 
a real one. His work consists in resolving the religious world into its 
secular basis. He overlooks the fact that after completing this work, 
the chief thing still remains to be done. For the fact that the secular 
basis lifts off from itself and establishes itself in the clouds as an 
independent realm can only be explained by the inner strife and 
intrinsic contradictoriness of this secular basis. The latter must itself, 
therefore, first be understood in its contradiction and then, by the 
removal of the contradiction, revolutionised in practice. Thus, for 
instance, once the earthly family is discovered to be the secret of the 
holy family, the former must then itself be criticised in theory and 
transformed in practice. 



5 

Feuerbach, not satisfied with abstract thinking , appeals to sensuous 
contemplation; but he does not conceive sensuousness as practical, 
human-sensuous activity. 



6 

Feuerbach resolves the essence of religion into the essence of man. 
But the essence of man is no abstraction inherent in each single 
individual. In its reality it is the ensemble of the social relations. 

Feuerbach, who does not enter upon a criticism of this real 
essence, is hence obliged: 




8 



Karl Marx 



1. To abstract from the historical process and to define the 
religious sentiment [ Gemiit ] regarded by itself, and to presuppose an 
abstract — isolated — human individual. 

2. The essence of man, therefore, can with him be regarded only 
as “species”, as an inner, mute, general character which unites the 
many individuals only in a natural way. 

7 

Feuerbach, consequently, does not see that the “religious senti- 
ment” is itself a social product , and that the abstract individual which 
he analyses belongs in reality to a particular form of society. 



Social life is essentially practical. All mysteries which mislead theory 
into mysticism find their rational solution in human practice and in 
the comprehension of this practice. 

9 

The highest point attained by contemplative materialism, that is, 
materialism which does not comprehend sensuousness as practical 
activity, is the contemplation of single individuals in “civil society”. 

10 

The standpoint of the old materialism is “civil” society; the 
standpoint of the new is human society, or associated humanity. 

n 

The philosophers have only interpreted the world in various ways; 
the point, however, is to change it. 



Written in the spring of 1845 



Printed according to the book 



First published by Engels 
in the Appendix to the separate 
edition of his Ludwig Feuerbach 
und der Ausgang der klassischen 
deutschen Philosophic, Stuttgart, 1888 







‘ t K"" . * - ‘Mr JL/ V 



>u Y“ r tV~* v -» 

■**■*$* °* 



5— 4— v -|^ w ^ : 






. -1 



fc- 



/p'-yi' V(yw*- 




Die Philosopher! haben die Welt nur verschieden interpretirt, 
es kommt drauf an sie zu verandem. 



Facsimile of Thesis 1 1 on Feuerbach. From Marx’s notebook 




Frederick Engels 

FEUERBACH 3 



a) The entire philosophy of Feuerbach amounts to 1. philosophy 
of nature — passive adoration of nature and enraptured kneeling 
down before its splendour and omnipotence. 2. Anthropology, 
namely «) physiology, where nothing new is added to what the 
materialists have already said about the unity of body and soul, but 
it is said less mechanically and with rather more exuberance, 
J5) psychology, which amounts to dithyrambs glorifying love, analo- 
gous to the cult of nature, apart from that nothing new. 3. Morality, 
the demand to live up to the concept of “man”, 3 impuissance mise en 
action . b Compare §54, p. 81: “The ethical and rational attitude of 
man to his stomach consists in treating it not as something bestial but 
as something human.” — §61: “Man ... as a moral being” and all the 
talk about morality in Das Wesen des Christenthums. 



b) The fact that at the present stage of development men can 
satisfy their needs only within society, that in general from the very 
start, as soon as they came into existence, men needed one another 
and could only develop their needs and abilities, etc., by entering 
into intercourse c with other men, this fact is expressed by Feuerbach 
in the following way: 



3 Cf. Ludwig Feuerbach, Grundsatze der Philosophic der Zukunft, § 52. — Ed. 
b Powerlessness set in motion. Charles Fourier, Theorie des quatre mouvements, et des 
destinees generates, deuxieme partie. Epilogue. — Ed. 
c See Note 11. — Ed. 




12 



Frederick Engels 



“Isolated man by himself has not the essenceof man in himself ’; “the essence of man is 
contained only in the community, in the unity of man and man, a unity, however, which 
depends only on the reality of the difference between I and you. — Man by himself is 
man (in the ordinary sense), man and man, the unity of I and you, is God" (i.e., man in 
the supraordinary sense) (§§ 61, 62, p. 83). 

Philosophy has reached a point when the trivial fact of the 
necessity of intercourse between human beings — a fact without a 
knowledge of which the second generation that ever existed would 
never have been produced, a fact already involved in the sexual 
difference — is presented by philosophy at the end of its entire 
development as the greatest result. And presented, moreover, in the 
mysterious form of “the unity of I and you”. This phrase would have 
been quite impossible had Feuerbach not xax’ e$opjv a thought of 
the sexual act, the conjugal act, the community of I and you.* And 
insofar as his community becomes real it is moreover limited to the 
sexual act and to arriving at an understanding about philosophical 
ideas and problems, to “true dialectics” (§ 64), to dialogue, to “the 
procreation of man, both spiritual and physical man” (p. 67). What 
this “ procreated ’ man does afterwards, apart from again “spiritually” 
and “physically” “procreating men”, is not mentioned. Feuerbach 
only knows intercourse between two beings, 



“the truth that no being on its own is a true, perfect, absolute being, that truth and 
perfection is only the association, the unity of two beings that are essentially alike’’ 
(pp. 83, 84). 



c) The beginning of the Philosophie der Zukunft immediately shows 
the difference between us and him: 

§ 1: “The task of modern times was the realisation and humanisation of God, the 
transformation and dissolution of theology into anthropology.” Cf. “The negation of 
theology is the essence of modern times” (Philosophie der Zukunft, p. 23). 



* For, since the human being = brain + heart, and two are necessary to represent 
the human being, one of them personifies the brain in their intercourse, the other the 
heart — man and woman. Otherwise it would be impossible to understand whv two 
persons are more human than one. b Saint-Simonist individual. 4 



a Mainly. — Ed. 

b Cf. Ludwig Feuerbach, Grundsatze der Philosophie der Zukunft, § 58. — Ed. 




Feuerbach 



13 



d) The distinction that Feuerbach makes between Catholicism and 
Protestantism in §2 — Catholicism: “theology” “is concerned with 
what God is in himself”, it has a “tendency towards speculation and 
contemplation”; Protestantism is merely Christology, it leaves God to 
himself and speculation and contemplation to philosophy — this 
distinction is nothing but a division of labour arisen from a need 
appropriate to immature science. Feuerbach explains Protestantism 
merely from this need within theology, whereupon an independent 
history of philosophy naturally follows. 



e) “Being is not a general concept which can be separated from things. It is 
identical with the things that exist.... Being is posited by essence. What my 
essence is, is my being. The fish is in the water, but its essence cannot be separated from 
this being. Even language identifies being and essence. It is only in human life that 
being is divorced from essence — but only in exceptional, unfortunate cases — only there 
is it possible that a person’s essence is not in the place where he is, but it is precisely 
because of this division that his spirit is not truly in the place where his body actually is. 
Only where your heart is, there you are. But all things — apart from abnormal cases — like 
to be in the place where they are, and like to be what they are” (p. 47). 

A fine panegyric upon the existing state of things! Apart from 
abnormal cases, a few exceptional cases, you like to work from your 
seventh year as a door-keeper in a coal-mine, remaining alone in the 
dark for fourteen hours a day, and because it is your being 
therefore it is also your essence. The same applies to a piecer 3 at a 
self-actor. 3 It is your “essence” to be subservient to a branch of 
labour. Cf. Das Wesen des Glaubens, p. 11, “unsatisfied hunger” [...] b 



f) § 48, p. 73. “ Time is the only means that makes it possible without contradiction to 
combine opposite or contradictory determinations in a single being. This applies at all 
events to living beings. Only thus does here— for example in man — the contradiction 
make its appearance that now this determination, this resolution, dominates and 
occupies me, and then a quite different and diametrically opposed determination.” 

Feuerbach describes this as 1) a contradiction, 2) a combination of 
contradictions, and 3) alleges that time brings this about. Indeed time 



3 This word is in English in the manuscript. — Ed. 

b Engels did not finish this sentence. A similar idea is expressed in Chapter I of The 
German Ideology (cf. p. 58 of this volume). — Ed. 




14 



Frederick Engels 



“filled” with events, but still time, and not that which takes place 
during this time. 3 The proposition amounts to the statement: it is only 
in time that change is possible. 

Written probably in the autumn Printed according to the manu- 

of 1 845 script 

First published in German in 1932 
in Marx/Engels, Gesamtansgabe, 

Erste Abteilung, Bd. 5 



Ludwig Feuerbach , Grundsatze der Philosophie der Zukunft, § 1 2. — Ed. 




Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 

[A REPLY TO BRUNO BAUER’S ANTI-CRITIQUE 5 ] 



Brussels, November 20. In Wigand’s Vierteljahrsschrift, Vol. Ill, 
p. 138 ff., Bruno Bauer stammers out a few words in answer to Die 
heilige Familie, oder Kritik der kritischen Kritik, 1845, by Engels and 
Marx . a At the outset Bruno Bauer declares that Engels and Marx have 
misunderstood him; with unaffected naivete he repeats his old 
pretentious phrases, which have long since been reduced to nothing, 
and regrets that these writers do not know his catchwords about “the 
constant struggle and victory, the destruction and creation of 
criticism”, which is the “only historical force”, his assertions that 
“the critic and only the critic has smashed religion in its entirety and 
the state in its various manifestations”, that “the critic has worked 
and still works”, and similar high-sounding protestations and lofty 
effusions. In his reply Bauer immediately provides new and striking 
proof of “ how the critic has worked and still works”. For the 
“hard-working” critic considers that it serves his purpose better not to 
make the book by Engels and Marx the object of his exclamations and 
quotations, but a mediocre and confused review of this book published 
in the Westphalische Dampfboot (May issue, p. 206 ff.) 6 — a conjuring 
trick, which, with critical prudence, he conceals from the reader. 

While Bauer is copying from the Dampfboot, he interrupts his 
“ arduous work” only with laconic, but highly ambiguous shrugging of 
his shoulders. Critical criticism has limited itself to shrugging its 
shoulders since it has no more to say. It finds salvation in the 
shoulder-blades despite its hatred of the sensuous world, which it can 



See present edition, Vol. 4, pp. 3-21 1. — Ed. 




16 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



only conceive in the shape of a “stick” (see Wigand’s Vierteljahrsschrift, 
p. 130), an instrument for chastising its theological bareness. 

In his superficial haste the Westphalian reviewer gives a ridiculous 
summary which is utterly at variance with the book he is reviewing. 
The “ hard-working ” critic copies the fabrications of the reviewer, 
attributes them to Engels and Marx and triumphantly shouts to the 
uncritical mass — which he annihilates with one eye, while with the 
other he flirtatiously invites it to come nearer — see, these are my 
opponents! 

Let us now place side by side the words of these documents. 

The reviewer writes in the Westphalische Dampfboot : 

“In order to kill the Jews he” ( Bruno Bauer) “transforms them into theologians, and 
the problem of political emancipation into that of human emancipation; to annihilate 
Hegel he transforms him into Herr Hinrichs; to get rid of the French Revolution, 
communism and Feuerbach he shouts ‘mass, mass, mass!’ and again ‘mass, mass, 
mass!’ and crucifies it to the glory of the spirit, which is criticism, the true incarnation 
of the absolute idea in Bruno of Charlottenburg” (Das Westphalische Dampfboot, 1. c., 

p. 212). 

The “ hard-working ” critic writes: 

“The critic of critical criticism” becomes “in the end childish”, “plays the 
Harlequin on the theatro mundi” and “would have us believe”, “asserting in all 
seriousness, that Bruno Bauer in order to kill the Jews”, etc., etc. — there follows verba- 
tim the whole passage from the Westphalische Dampfboot, which is nowhere to be found 
in Die heilige Familie ( Wigand’s Vierteljahrsschrift, p. 142). 

Compare this with the attitude of critical criticism to the Jewish 
question and to political emancipation in Die heilige Familie, inter alia, 
pp. 163-85; regarding its attitude to the French Revolution cf. pp. 
185-95; and its attitude to socialism and communism, pp. 22-74, 
p. 21 1 ff., pp. 243-44 and the whole chapter on critical criticism in 
the person of Rudolph, Prince of Geroldstein, pp. 258-333.® Regar- 
ding the attitude of critical criticism to Hegel see the mystery of “spe- 
culative construction” and the following explanation on p. 79 ff., also 
pp. 121 and 122, 126-28, 136-37, 208-09, 215-27 and 304-08; on the 
attitude of critical criticism to Feuerbach see pp. 138-41, and finally 
on the result and the trend of the critical fight against the French Re- 
volution, materialism and socialism see pp. 214-15. b 

One can see from these quotations that the Westphalian reviewer 
has given a completely distorted and only imaginary summary 

a See present edition, Vol. 4, pp. 106-18, 118-24, 23-72, 134 ff., 151-53, 162- 
209. — Ed. 

b Ibid., pp. 57 ff., 82 and 83, 85-87, 91-92, 131-32, 136-43, 191-93, 92-94, 135- 
36.— Ed. 




A Reply to Bruno Bauer’s Anti-Critique 



17 



showing that he has absurdly misunderstood the arguments. It is this 
summary which with “creative and devastating” agility the “pure” 
and “ hard-working ” critic substitutes for the original. 

Furthermore. 

The reviewer writes in the W estphalische Dampfboot : 

“To his” (that is, Bruno Bauer’s) “ silly self-apotheosis, in which he seeks to prove that 
wherever he was formerly in thrall to the prejudices of the mass, this enthralment was 
merely a necessary guise of criticism, Marx replies by offering to provide the following 
little scholastic treatise: ‘Why the conception of the Virgin Mary had to be proved by no 
other than Herr Bruno Bauer* ” etc., etc. ( Dampfboot , p. 213). 

The “hard-working” critic: 

“He” (the critic of critical criticism) “wants to make us believe, and in the end 
himself believes his humbug, that wherever Bauer was formerly in thrall to the 
prejudices of the mass he wants to present this enthralment merely as a necessary 
guise of criticism and not on the contrary as the result of the necessary development of 
criticism; in reply to this ‘silly self-apotheosis’ he therefore offers the following 
little scholastic treatise: ‘Why the conception of the Virgin Mary’” etc., etc. ( Wigand’s 
Vierteljahrsschrift, pp. 142-43). 

The reader will find in Die heilige Familie, pp. 1 50-63, a a special 
section on Bruno Bauer's self-apology, but unfortunately nothing is 
written there about the little scholastic treatise, which is therefore by 
no means offered in reply to Bruno Bauer's self-apology, as the 
Westphalian reviewer writes; and the obliging Bruno Bauer copies 
this — even enclosing some words in inverted commas — assuming it to 
be a quotation from Die heilige Familie. The little treatise is 
mentioned in a different section and in a different context (see Die 
heilige Familie, pp. 164 and 165 b ). What it signifies there the reader 
may find out for himself and again admire the “pure” cunning of 
the “hard-working critic”. 

In the end the “ hard-working ” critic exclaims: 

“This” (namely the quotations which Bruno Bauer has borrowed from the 
W estphalische Dampfboot and attributed to the authors of Die heilige Familie) “has of 
course reduced Bruno Bauer to silence and brought criticism to its senses. On the 
contrary, Marx has presented us with a spectacle by finally himself appearing in the role 
of the amusing comedian” ( Wigand’s Vierteljahrsschrift, p. 143). 

To understand this “on the contrary” one has to know that the 
Westphalian reviewer, for whom Bruno Bauer works as a copyist, 
dictates the following to his critical and hard-working scribe: 

“The world-historic drama” (that is, the fight of Bauer’s criticism against the mass) 
“quite simply disintegrates into the most amusing comedy ” (Das W estphalische Dampfboot, 
p. 213). 

a See present edition, Vol. 4, pp. 99-106. — Ed. 

b Ibid., pp. 106-08. — Ed. 




18 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



Here the hapless copyist jumps to his feet: to transcribe his own 
condemnation is beyond his power. “On the contrary he cries 
interrupting the dictation of the Westphalian reviewer, “on the 
contrary ... Marx ... is the most amusing comedian! ” and he wipes the 
cold sweat from his brow. 

By resorting to incompetent jugglery , to the most deplorable 
conjuring trick, Bruno Bauer has in the final analysis confirmed the 
death sentence passed upon him by Engels and Marx in Die heilige 
Familie. 



Printed according to the journal 



Written on November 20, 1845 

Published in Gesellschaftsspiegel, 
Heft VII, Januar 1846 




Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 
THE GERMAN IDEOLOGY 



CRITIQUE OF MODERN GERMAN PHILOSOPHY 
ACCORDING TO ITS REPRESENTATIVES 
FEUERBACH, B. BAUER AND STIRNER, 

AND OF GERMAN SOCIALISM 
ACCORDING TO ITS VARIOUS PROPHETS 7 




Written between November 1 845 Printed according to the manu- 

and August 1846 script 

First published in full in 1932 

by the Institute of Marxism-Leninism 

of the Central Committee of the C.P.S.U. 

in Marx/Engels, Gesamtausgabe, 

Erste Abteilung, Bd. 5 




CRITIQUE 



OF MODERN GERMAN PHILOSOPHY 
ACCORDING TO ITS REPRESENTATIVES 
FEUERBACH, B. BAUER AND STIRNER 




Preface 



Hitherto men have always formed wrong ideas about themselves, 
about what they are and what they ought to be. They have arranged 
their relations according to their ideas of God, of normal man, 
etc. The products of their brains have got out of their hands. They, 
the creators, have bowed down before their creations. Let us liberate 
them from the chimeras, the ideas, dogmas, imaginary beings under 
the yoke of which they are pining away. Let us revolt against this rule 
of concepts. Let us teach men, says one, 3 how to exchange these 
imaginations for thoughts which correspond to the essence of man; 
says another, 15 how to take up a critical attitude to them; says the 
third, 0 how to get them out of their heads; and existing reality will 
collapse. 

These innocent and child-like fancies are the kernel of the modern 
Young-Hegelian philosophy, which not only is received by the 
German public with horror and awe, but is announced by our 
philosophic heroes with the solemn consciousness of its world-shatter- 
ing danger and criminal ruthlessness. The first volume of the 
present publication has the aim of uncloaking these sheep, who take 
themselves and are taken for wolves; of showing that their bleating 
merely imitates in a philosophic form the conceptions of the German 
middle class; that the boasting of these philosophic commentators 
only mirrors the wretchedness of the real conditions in Germany. It 
is its aim to ridicule and discredit the philosophic struggle with the 



a Ludwig Feuerbach. — Ed. 
b Bruno Bauer.— Ed. 
c Max Stirner. — Ed. 




24 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



shadows of reality, which appeals to the dreamy and muddled 
German nation. 

Once upon a time a valiant fellow had the idea that men were 
drowned in water only because they were possessed with the idea of 
gravity.. If they were to get this notion out of their heads, say by 
avowing it to be a superstitious, a religious concept, they would be 
sublimely proof against any danger from water. His whole life long 
he fought against the illusion of gravity, of whose harmful 
consequences all statistics brought him new and manifold evidence. 
This valiant fellow was the type of the new revolutionary 
philosophers in Germany.* 



* [The following passage is crossed out in the manuscript:] There is no specific 
difference between German idealism and the ideology of all the other nations. The 
latter too regards the world as dominated by ideas, ideas and concepts as the 
determining principles, and certain notions as the mystery of the material world 
accessible to the philosophers. 

Hegel completed positive idealism. He not only turned the whole material world 
into a world of ideas and the whole of history into a history of ideas. He was not 
content with recording thought entities, he also sought to describe the act of creation. 

Roused from their world of fancy, the German philosophers protest against the world 
of ideas to which they [...] the conception of the real, material [...] 

All the German philosophical critics assert that the real world of men has hitherto 
been dominated and determined by ideas, images, concepts, and that the real world is 
a product of the world of ideas. This has been the case up to now, but it ought to be 
changed. They differ from each other in the manner in which they intend to deliver 
mankind, which in their opinion is groaning under the weight of its own fixed ideas; 
they differ in respect of what they proclaim to be fixed ideas; they agree in their belief 
in the hegemony of ideas, they agree in the belief that the action of their critical reason 
must bring about the destruction of the existing order of things: whether they 
consider their isolated rational activity sufficient or want to conquer universal 
consciousness. 

The belief that the real world is the product of the ideal world, that the world of 
ideas [...] 

Having lost their faith in the Hegelian world of ideas, the German philosophers 
protest against the domination of thoughts, ideas, and concepts which, according to 
their opinion, i.e., according to Hegel’s illusion, have hitherto produced, determined 
and dominated the real world. They make their protest and expire [...] 

According to the Hegelian system ideas, thoughts and concepts have produced, 
determined, dominated the real life of men, their material world, their actual 
relations. His rebellious disciples take this [...] 




»i;.wvV r- ^ T T: , 1 " 

^-v-V- ^* :V ~ ^!toT 

’V- fyK. V* V * "W-J v\-*A ^L-V'V* 

*' sA - V^Lfir* 1> 3 V* -La-. Jj\ ^ 

■ Lr^- -**V -v- a ,%JL. /— 9~v 

^•..>H* ^.UJ-a* — iV-^ ‘V^vi'lv- S -‘M^ *^1^r 'V* 

+-* W-H v>*V- <**«*- ♦ty*- >— Ijlflhr-.W’ 

%>H- . w w»4 » P r Aa» £*w/L^>. *Mfr^ y •Vyutt-ttf'/l* 

**^W»V >V-^~ 

%>mu a-w-* 3Ut*^ £avv s-ft^-tf HHr^^^ifitri 

V>*~ ^-v^V- 

«* O-vHiV tL4^^ 

* ^’-W^ <M .vv*V x*"VH ~ J 5 4r» ***»■* -ty>-.f*' 4Uir ^ V 

-VJY- »w-V3=. V-A-u.^ 4^- *<-ui$~J^- 

^W* ^-^JLi^ »-w'*V- A ~rYr* 

^•-va v ->_ 0^-ji 5 -^ 6 y**~ s ** 

* 5 - £^> V4k ^ V^x V ^ I *~' 

^ *~ -> ^ v ^T+f-\ ^ . 

T*Uni» ^ mT — r-* *3* •— 4 ^ ' 

^£db^L-i!b2r <!pT-VVl >J r 'H**’'^ 

'V~lfcx -**>•*— V'-Vt t*-— J-F'W • V-- t - rV ^ 

" At * v " -Vv- V =v.^ vh-r^f ~V~ ^ 7?, 



W *~*/ L m ««. >-. 6^ < lv >u V- ‘•‘r- » 

*V- ' ‘ " 1 

A< - 






vi^v i-^-v ‘^•x'A.. >vju 'h— * .-•.^'Jnir 



First page of the Preface to The German Ideology 
in Marx’s handwriting 




FEUERBACH 



OPPOSITION OF THE MATERIALIST 
* AND IDEALIST OUTLOOKS 8 

[I] 

|sh.l| According to German ideologists, Germany has in the last 
few years gone through an unparalleled revolution. The decomposi- 
tion of the Hegelian system, which began with Strauss, 9 has 
developed into a universal ferment into which all the “powers of the 
past” are swept. In the general chaos mighty empires have arisen 
only to meet with immediate doom, heroes have emerged momen- 
tarily to be again hurled into obscurity by bolder and stronger rivals. 
It was a revolution beside which the French Revolution was child’s 
play, a world struggle beside which the struggles of the Diadochi 10 
appear insignificant. Principles ousted one another, intellectual 
heroes overthrew each other with unheard-of rapidity, and in the 
three years 1842-45 more was cleared away in Germany than at other 
times in three centuries. 

All this is supposed to have taken place in the realm of pure 
thought. 

Certainly it is an interesting event we are dealing with: the 
putrescence of the absolute spirit. When the last spark of its life had 
failed, the various components of this caput mortuum a began to 
decompose, entered into new combinations and formed new 
substances. The industrialists of philosophy, who till then had lived 
on the exploitation of the absolute spirit, now seized upon the new 
combinations. Each with all possible zeal set about retailing his 
apportioned share. This was bound to give rise to competition, 
which, to start with, was carried on in moderately civil and staid 



a Literally: dead head; a term used in chemistry for the residuum left after 
distillation; here: remainder, residue. — Ed. 




28 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



fashion. Later, when the German market was glutted, and the 
commodity in spite of all efforts was not favourably received in 
the world market, the business was spoiled in the usual German 
manner by cheap and spurious production, deterioration in 
quality, adulteration of the raw materials, falsification of labels, 
fictitious purchases, bill-jobbing and a credit system devoid of 
any real basis. The competition turned into a bitter struggle, which 
is now being extolled and interpreted to us as an upheaval of 
world significance, the begetter of the most prodigious results 
and achievements. 

If we wish to rate at its true value this philosophic charlatanry, 
which awakens even in the breast of the righteoifs German citizen a 
glow of patriotic feeling, if we wish to bring out clearly the pettiness, 
the parochial narrowness of this whole Young-Hegelian movement 
and in particular the tragicomic contrast between the illusions of 
these heroes about their achievements and the actual achievements 
themselves, we must look at the whole spectacle from a standpoint 
beyond the frontiers of Germany.* 



[1.] IDEOLOGY IN GENERAL, GERMAN IDEOLOGY 
IN PARTICULAR 



|sh.2| German criticism has, right up to its latest efforts, never left 
the realm of philosophy. It by no means examines its general 
philosophic premises, but in fact all its problems originate in a 
definite philosophical system, that of Hegel. Not only in its answers, 
even in its questions there was a mystification. This dependence on 
Hegel is the reason why not one of these modern critics has even 



* [In the first version of the clean copy there follows a passage, which is crossed 
out:] |p. 2 1 

We preface therefore the specific criticism of individual representatives of 
this movement with a few general observations, elucidating the ideological premises 
common to all of them. These remarks will suffice to indicate the standpoint of our 
criticism insofar as it is required for the understanding and the motivation of the 
subsequent individual criticisms. We oppose these remarks |p. 3| to Feuerbach in 
particular because he is the only one who has at least made some progress and whose 
works can be examined de bonne foi. 

1. Ideology in General, and Especially German Philosophy 
A. We know only a single science, the science of history. One can look at history 
from two sides and divide it into the history of nature and the history of men. The two 
sides are, however, inseparable; the history of nature and the history of men are 
dependent on each other so long as men exist. The history of nature, called natural 




The German Ideology. I. Feuerbach 



29 



attempted a comprehensive criticism of the Hegelian system, 
however much each professes to have advanced beyond Hegel. 
Their polemics against Hegel and against one another are 
confined to this — each takes one aspect of the Hegelian system and 
turns this against the whole system as well as against the aspects 
chosen by the others. To begin with they took pure, unfal- 
sified Hegelian categories such as “substance” and “self-con- 
sciousness”, a later they secularised these categories by giving 
them more profane names such as “species”, “the unique”, 
“man”, b etc. 

The entire body of German philosophical criticism from Strauss to 
Stirner is confined to criticism of religious conceptions.* The critics 
started from real religion and theology proper. What religious 
consciousness and religious conception are was subsequently defined 
in various ways. The advance consisted in including the allegedly 
dominant metaphysical, political, juridical, moral and other concep- 
tions under the category of religious or theological conceptions; and 
similarly in declaring that political, juridical, moral consciousness 
was religious or theological consciousness, and that the political, 
juridical, moral man — “Man” in the last resort — was religious. The 
dominance of religion was presupposed. Gradually every dominant 
relationship was declared to be a religious relationship and 
transformed into a cult, a cult of law, a cult of the state, etc. It was 
throughout merely a question of dogmas and belief in dogmas. The 
world was sanctified to an ever-increasing extent till at last the 
venerable Saint Max c was able to canonise it en bloc and thus dispose 
of it once for all. 

The Old Hegelians had understood everything as soon as it was 



science, does not concern us here; but we will have to examine the history of men, 
since almost the whole ideology amounts either to a distorted conception of this 
history or to a complete abstraction from it. Ideology is itself only one of the aspects of 
this history. 

[There follows a passage dealing with the premises of the materialist conception of 
history. It is not crossed out and in this volume it is reproduced as Section 2; see 
pp. 31-32.] 

* [The following passage is crossed out in the manuscript:] claiming to be the 
absolute redeemer of the world from all evil. Religion was continually regarded and 
treated as the arch-enemy, as the ultimate cause of all relations repugnant to these 
philosophers. 



a The basic categories of David Friedrich Strauss and Bruno Bauer. — Ed. 
b The basic categories of Ludwig Feuerbach and Max Stirner. — Ed. 
c Max Stirner. — Ed. 




30 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



reduced to a Hegelian logical category. The Young Hegelians 
criticised everything by ascribing religious conceptions to it or by 
declaring that it is a theological matter. The Young Hegelians are in 
agreement with the Old Hegelians in their belief in the rule of 
religion, of concepts, of a universal principle in the existing world. 
Except that the one party attacks this rule as usurpation, while the 
other extols it as legitimate. 

Since the Young Hegelians consider conceptions, thoughts, ideas, 
in fact all the products of consciousness, to which they attribute an 
independent existence, as the real chains of men (just as the Old 
Hegelians declare them the true bonds of human society), it is 
evident that the Young Hegelians have to fight only against these 
illusions of consciousness. Since, according to their fantasy, 
the relations of men, all their doings, their fetters and their 
limitations are products of their consciousness, the Young Hegelians 
logically put to men the moral postulate of exchanging their present 
consciousness for human, critical or egoistic consciousness, 3 and thus 
of removing their limitations. This demand to change consciousness 
amounts to a demand to interpret the existing world in a different 
way, i.e., to recognise it by means of a different interpretation. The 
Young-Hegelian ideologists, in spite of their allegedly “world- 
shattering” b phrases, are the staunchest conservatives. The most 
recent of them have found the correct expression for their activity 
when they declare they are only fighting against “phrases”. They 
forget, however, that they themselves are opposing nothing but 
phrases to these phrases, and that they are in no way combating the 
real existing world when they are combating solely the phrases of 
this world. The only results which this philosophic criticism was 
able to achieve were a few (and at that one-sided) elucidations of 
Christianity from the point of view of religious history; all the rest 
of their assertions are only further embellishments of their claim 
to have furnished, in these unimportant elucidations, discoveries 
of world-historic importance. 

It has not occurred to any one of these philosophers to inquire into 
the connection of German philosophy with German reality, the 
connection of their criticism with their own material surroundings. c 



3 A reference to Ludwig Feuerbach, Bruno Bauer and Max Stirner, whose basic 
categories were, respectively, “man”, “criticism” and “ego”. — Ed. 

b Cf. “Ueber das Recht des Freigesprochenen ...” published anonymously in 
Wigand’s Vierteljahrsschrift, 1845, Bd. IV. — Ed. 

c The rest of this page of the manuscript is left blank. The text following on the 
next page of the manuscript is reproduced in this volume as Section 3; see pp. 32- 
35 .—Ed. 




The German Ideology. I. Feuerbach 



31 



[2. PREMISES OF THE MATERIALIST CONCEPTION OF HISTORY 3 ] 

|p. 3 1 The premises from which we begin are not arbitrary ones, 
not dogmas, but real premises from which abstraction can only be 
made in the imagination. They are the real individuals, their activity 
and the material conditions of their life, both those which they find 
already existing and those produced by their activity. These premises 
can thus be |p. 4| verified in a purely empirical way. 

The first premise of all human history is, of course, the existence 
of living human individuals.* Thus the first fact to be established is 
the physical organisation of these individuals and their consequent 
relation to the rest of nature. Of course, we cannot here go either 
into the actual physical nature of man, or into the natural conditions 
in which man finds himself — geological, oro-hydrographical, 
climatic and so on.** All historical writing must set out from these 
natural bases and their modification in the course of history through 
the action of men. 

Men can be distinguished from animals by consciousness, by 
religion or anything else you like. They themselves begin to 
distinguish themselves from animals as soon as they begin to produce 
their means of subsistence, a step which is conditioned by their 
physical organisation. By producing their means of subsistence men 
are indirectly producing their material life. 

The way in which men produce their means of subsistence 
depends first of all on the nature of the means of subsistence they 
actually find in existence and have to reproduce. 

|p. 5 1 This mode of production must not be considered simply as 
being the reproduction of the physical existence of the individuals. 
Rather it is a definite form of activity of these individuals, a definite 
form of expressing their life, a definite mode of life on their part. As 
individuals express their life, so they are. What they are, therefore, 
coincides with their production, both with what they produce and 



* [The following passage is crossed out in the manuscript:] The first historical act 
of these individuals distinguishing them from animals is not that they think, but that 
they begin to produce their means of subsistence. 

** [The following passage is crossed out in the manuscript:] These conditions 
determine not only the original, spontaneous organisation of men, especially racial 
differences, but also the entire further development, or lack of development, of men 
up to the present time. 



3 The text of the following section has been taken from the first version 
of the clean copy. — Ed. 




32 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



with how they produce. Hence what individuals are depends on the 
material conditions of their production. 

This production only makes its appearance with the increase of 
population. In its turn this presupposes the intercourse [Verkehr] 11 of 
individuals with one another. The form of this intercourse is again 
determined by production. 



[3. PRODUCTION AND INTERCOURSE. 

DIVISION OF LABOUR 

AND FORMS OF PROPERTY— TRIBAL, ANCIENT, FEUDAL] 

[sh.3| The relations of different nations among themselves depend 
upon the extent to which each has developed its productive forces, 
the division of labour and internal intercourse. This proposition is 
generally recognised. But not only the relation of one nation to 
others, but also the whole internal structure of the nation itself 
depends on the stage of development reached by its production and 
its internal and external intercourse. How far the productive forces 
of a nation are developed is shown most manifestly by the degree to 
which the division of labour has been carried. Each new productive 
force, insofar as it is not merely a quantitative extension of 
productive forces already known (for instance, the bringing into 
cultivation of fresh land), causes a further development of the 
division of labour. 

The division of labour inside a nation leads at first to the separation 
of industrial and commercial from agricultural labour, and hence to 
the separation of town and country and to the conflict of their 
interests. Its further development leads to the separation of 
commercial from industrial labour. At the same time through the 
division of labour inside these various branches there develop 
various divisions among the individuals co-operating in definite 
kinds of labour. The relative position of these individual groups is 
determined by the way work is organised in agriculture, industry 
and commerce (patriarchalism, slavery, estates, classes). These same 
conditions are to be seen (given a more developed intercourse) in the 
relations of different nations to one another. 

The various stages of development in the division of labour are 
just so many different forms of property, i.e., the existing stage in 
the division of labour determines also the relations of individuals to 
one another with reference to the material, instrument and product 
of labour. 

The first form of property is tribal property [ Stammeigentum ]. 12 




The German Ideology. I. Feuerbach 



33 



It corresponds to the undeveloped stage of production, at which a 
people lives by hunting and fishing, by cattle-raising or, at most, by 
agriculture. In the latter case it presupposes a great mass of 
uncultivated stretches of land. The division of labour is at this 
stage still very elementary and is confined to a further extension 
of the natural division of labour existing in the family. The 
social structure is, therefore, limited to an extension of the 
family: patriarchal chieftains, below them the members of the 
tribe, finally slaves. The slavery latent in the family only develops 
gradually with the increase of population, the growth of wants, 
and with the extension of external intercourse, both of war and 
of barter. 

The second form is the ancient communal and state property, 
which proceeds especially from the union of several tribes into a city 
by agreement or by conquest, and which is still accompanied by 
slavery. Beside communal property we already find movable, and 
later also immovable, private property developing, but as an 
abnormal form subordinate to communal property. The citizens 
hold power over their labouring slaves only in their community, and 
even on this account alone they are bound to the form of communal 
property. It constitutes the communal private property of the active 
citizens who, in relation to their slaves, are compelled to remain in 
this spontaneously derived form of association. For this reason the 
whole structure of society based on this communal property, and 
with it the power of the people, decays in the same measure in which 
immovable private property evolves. The division of labour is already- 
more developed. We already find the opposition of town and country; 
later the opposition between those states which represent town 
interests and those which represent country interests, and inside the 
towns themselves the opposition between industry and maritime 
commerce. The class relations between citizens and slaves are now 
completely developed. 

With the development of private property, we find here for the first 
time the same relations which we shall find again, only on a more 
extensive scale, with modern private property. On the one hand, the 
concentration of private property, which began very early in Rome (as 
the Licinian agrarian law proves) and proceeded very rapidly from 
the time of the civil wars and especially under the emperors 13 ; on the 
other hand, coupled with this, the transformation of the plebeian 
small peasantry into a proletariat, which, however, owing to its 
intermediate position between propertied citizens and slaves, never 
achieved an independent development. 

The third form is feudal or estate property. If antiquity started out 




34 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



from the town and its small territory, the Middle Ages started out 
from the country. This different starting-point was determined by the 
sparseness of the population at that time, which was scattered over a 
large area and which received no large increases from the 
conquerors. In contrast to Greece and Rome, feudal development, 
therefore, begins over a much wider territory, prepared by the 
Roman conquests and the spread of agriculture at first associated 
with them. The last centuries of the declining Roman Empire and its 
conquest by the barbarians destroyed a considerable part of the 
productive forces; agriculture had declined, industry had decayed 
for want of a market, trade had died out or been violently 
interrupted, the rural and urban population had decreased. These 
conditions and the mode of organisation of the conquest determined 
by them, together with the influence of the Germanic military 
constitution, led to the development of feudal property. Like tribal 
and communal property, it is also based on a community; but the 
directly producing class standing over against it is not, as in the case 
of the ancient community, the slaves, but the enserfed small 
peasantry. As soon as feudalism is fully developed, there also arises 
antagonism to the towns. The hierarchical structure of landowner- 
ship, and the armed bodies of retainers associated with it, gave the 
nobility power over the serfs. This feudal organisation was, just 
as much as the ancient communal property, an association against a 
subjected producing class; but the form of association and the 
relation to the direct producers were different because of the 
different conditions of production. 

This feudal structure of landownership had its counterpart in the 
towns in the shape of corporative property, the feudal organisation of 
trades. Here property consisted |sh.4| chiefly in the labour of each 
individual. The necessity for associating against the association of the 
robber-nobility, the need for communal covered markets in an age 
when the industrialist was at the same time a merchant, the growing 
competition of the escaped serfs swarming into the rising towns, the 
feudal structure of the whole country: these combined to bring about 
the guilds. The gradually accumulated small capital of individual 
craftsmen and their stable numbers, as against the growing 
population, evolved the relation of journeyman and apprentice, 
which brought into being in the towns a hierarchy similar to that in 
the country. 

Thus property during the feudal epoch primarily consisted on the 
one hand of landed property with serf labour chained to it, and on 
the other of the personal labour of the individual who with his small 
capital commands the labour of journeymen. The organisation of 




36 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



materially, and hence as they work under definite material limits, 
presuppositions and conditions independent of their will.* 

The production of ideas, of conceptions, of consciousness, is at 
first directly interwoven with the material activity and the material 
intercourse of men — the language of real life. Conceiving, thinking, 
the mental intercourse of men at this stage still appear as the direct 
efflux of their material behaviour. The same applies to mental 
production as expressed in the language of the politics, laws, 
morality, religion, metaphysics, etc., of a people. Men are the 
producers of their conceptions, ideas, etc., that is, real, active men, as 
they are conditioned by a definite development of their productive 
forces and of the intercourse corresponding to these, up to its 
furthest forms.** Consciousness [das Bewusstsein ] can never be 
anything else than conscious being [ das bewusste Seiri\, and the being 
of men is their actual life-process. If in all ideology men and their 
relations appear upside-down as in a camera obscura, this phenome- 
non arises just as much from their historical life-process as the 
inversion of objects on the retina does from their physical 
life-process. 

In direct contrast to German philosophy which descends from 
heaven to earth, here it is a matter of ascending from earth to 
heaven. That is to say, not of setting out from what men say, imagine, 
conceive, nor from men as narrated, thought of, imagined, 
conceived, in order to arrive at men in the flesh; but setting out from 
real, active men, and on the basis of their real life-process 
demonstrating the development of the ideological reflexes and 
echoes of this life-process. The phantoms formed in the brains of 
men are also, necessarily, sublimates of their material life-process, 
which is empirically verifiable and bound to material premises. 
Morality, religion, metaphysics, and all the rest of ideology as well as 
the forms of consciousness corresponding to these, thus no longer 

* [The following passage is crossed out in the manuscript:] The ideas which these 
individuals form are ideas either about their relation to nature or about their mutual 
relations or about their own nature. It is evident that in all these cases their ideas are 
the conscious expression — real or illusory — of their real relations and activities, of 
their production, of their intercourse, of their social and political conduct. The 
opposite assumption is only possible if in addition to the spirit of the real, materially 
evolved individuals a separate spirit is presupposed. If the conscious expression of the 
real relations of these individuals is illusory, if in their imagination they turn reality 
upside-down, then this in its turn is the result of their limited material mode of activity 
and their limited social relations arising from it. 

** [The manuscript originally had:] Men are the producers of their conceptions, 
ideas, etc., and precisely men conditioned by the mode of production of their material 
life, by their material intercourse and its further development in the social and political 
structure. 




The German Ideology. I. Feuerbach 



37 



retain the semblance of independence. They have no history, no 
development; but men, developing their material production and 
their material intercourse, alter, along with this their actual world, 
also their thinking and the products of their thinking. It is not 
consciousness that determines life, but life that determines con- 
sciousness. For the first manner of approach the starting-point is 
consciousness taken as the living individual; for the second manner 
of approach, which conforms to real life, it is the real living 
individuals themselves, and consciousness is considered solely as their 
consciousness. 

This manner of approach is not devoid of premises. It starts out 
from the real premises and does not abandon them for a moment. Its 
premises are men, not in any fantastic isolation and fixity, but in 
their actual, empirically perceptible process of development under 
definite conditions. As soon as this active life-process is described, 
history ceases to be a collection of dead facts, as it is with the 
empiricists (themselves still abstract), or an imagined activity of 
imagined subjects, as with the idealists. 

Where speculation ends, where real life starts, there consequently 
begins real, positive science, the expounding of the practical activity, 
of the practical process of development of men. Empty phrases 
about consciousness end, and real knowledge has to take their place. 
When the reality is described, a self-sufficient philosophy [die 
selbstandige Philosophie ] loses its medium of existence. At the best its 
place can only be taken by a summing-up of the most general results, 
abstractions which are derived from the observation of the historical 
development of men. These abstractions in themselves, divorced 
from real history, have no value whatsoever. They can only serve to 
facilitate the arrangement of historical material, to indicate the 
sequence of its separate strata. But they by no means afford a recipe or 
schema, as does philosophy, for neatly trimming the epochs of history. 
On the contrary, the difficulties begin only when one sets about the 
examination and arrangement of the material — whether of a past 
epoch or of the present — and its actual presentation. The removal of 
these difficulties is governed by premises which certainly cannot be 
stated here, but which only the study of the actual life-process and 
the activity of the individuals of each epoch will make evident. We 
shall select here some of these abstractions, which we use in 
contradistinction to ideology, and shall illustrate them by historical 
examples. 3 



a The clean copy ends here. The text that follows in this edition are the three parts 
of the rough copy of the manuscript. — Ed. 




38 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



[II] 

[1. PRECONDITIONS OF THE REAL LIBERATION OF MAN] 

1 1 j We shall, of course, not take the trouble to explain to our wise 
philosophers that the “liberation” of “man” is not advanced a single 
step by reducing philosophy, theology, substance and all the rubbish 
to “self-consciousness” and by liberating “man” from the domina- 
tion of these phrases, which have never held him in thrall.* Nor shall 
we explain to them that it is possible to achieve real liberation only in 
the real world and by real means, that slavery cannot be abolished 
without the steam-engine and the mule jenny, serfdom cannot be 
abolished without improved agriculture, and that, in general, people 
cannot be liberated as long as they are unable to obtain food and 
drink, housing and clothing in adequate quality and quantity. 
“Liberation” is a historical and not a mental act, and it is brought 
about by historical conditions, the [level j of industry, com[merce], 
[agriculture, [intercourse...] 3 |2| then subsequently, in accordance 
with the different stages of their development, [they make up] the 
nonsense of substance, subject, self-consciousness and pure criticism, 
as well as religious and theological nonsense, and later they get ricf of 
it again when their development is sufficiently advanced.** In 
Germany, a country where only a trivial historical development is 
taking place, these mental developments, these glorified and 
ineffective trivialities, naturally serve as a substitute for the lack of 
historical development, and they take root and have to be combated. 
But this fight is of local importance.*** 



[2. FEUERBACH’S CONTEMPLATIVE AND INCONSISTENT MATERIALISM] 

[...] b 1 8 1 in reality and for the practical materialist, i.e., the 
communist, it is a question of revolutionising the existing world, of 
practically coming to grips with and changing the things found in 

* [Marginal notes by Marx:] Philosophic liberation and real liberation. — Man. 
The unique. The individual. — Geological, hydrographical, etc., conditions. The human 
body. Needs and labour. 

** [Marginal note by Marx:] Phrases and real movement. The importance of 
phrases in Germany. 

*** [Marginal note by Marx:] Language is the language of re[ality]. 



a The manuscript is damaged here: the lower part of the sheet is torn off; one line 
of the text is missing. — Ed. 

Five pages of the manuscript are missing. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. I. Feuerbach 



39 



existence. When occasionally we find such views with Feuerbach, 
they are never more than isolated surmises and have much too little 
influence on his general outlook to be considered here as anything 
but embryos capable of development. Feuerbach’s “conception” of 
the sensuous world is confined on the one hand to mere 
contemplation of it, and on the other to mere feeling; he posits 
“Man” instead of “real historical man”. 14 “Man” is really “the 
German”. In the first case, the contemplation of the sensuous world, 
he necessarily lights on things which contradict his consciousness and 
feeling, which disturb the harmony he presupposes, the harmony of 
all parts of the sensuous world and especially of man and nature.* 
To remove this disturbance, he must take refuge in a double 
perception, a profane one which perceives “only the flatly obvious” 
and a higher, philosophical, one which perceives the “true essence” 
of things. He does not see that the sensuous world around him is not 
a thing given direct from all eternity, remaining ever the same, but 
the product of industry and of the state of society; and, indeed [a 
product] in the sense that it is an historical product, the result of the 
activity of a whole succession of generations, each standing on the 
shoulders of the preceding one, developing its industry and its 
intercourse, and modifying its social system according to the 
changed needs. Even the objects of the simplest “sensuous certainty” 
are only given him through social development, industry and 
commercial intercourse. The cherry-tree, like almost all fruit-trees, 
was, as is well known, only a few centuries ago transplanted by 
commerce into our zone, and therefore only |9J by this action of a 
definite society in a definite age has it become “sensuous certainty” 
for Feuerbach. 

Incidentally, when things are seen in this way, as they really are 
and happened, every profound philosophical problem is resolved, as 
will be seen even more clearly later, quite simply into an empirical 
fact. For instance, the important question of the relation of man to 
nature (Bruno goes so far as to speak of “the antitheses in nature and 
history” (p. 110), a as though these were two separate “things” and 
man did not always have before him an historical nature and a 



* NB. F[euerbach’s] error is not that he subordinates the flatly obvious, the 
sensuous appearance to the sensuous reality established by detailed investigation of the 
sensuous facts, but that he cannot in the last resort cope with the sensuous world 
except by looking at it with the “eyes”, i.e., through the “spectacles”, of the 
philosopher. 



Bruno Bauer, “Charakteristik Ludwig Feuerbachs”. — Ed. 




40 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



natural history), which gave rise to all the “unfathomably lofty 
works” 3 on “substance” and “self-consciousness”, crumbles of itself 
when we understand that the celebrated “unity of man with nature” 
has always existed in industry and has existed in varying forms in 
every epoch according to the lesser or greater development of 
industry, and so has the “struggle” of man with nature, right up to 
the development of his productive forces on a corresponding basis. 
Industry and commerce, production and the exchange of the 
necessities of life in their turn determine distribution, the structure 
of the different social classes and are, in turn, determined by it as to 
the mode in which they are carried on; and so it happens that in 
Manchester, for instance, Feuerbach sees only factories and 
machines, where a hundred years ago only spinning-wheels and 
weaving-looms were to be seen, or in the Campagna di Roma he 
finds only pasture lands and swamps, where in the time of Augustus 
he would have found nothing but the vineyards and villas of Roman 
capitalists. Feuerbach speaks in particular of the perception of 
natural science; he mentions secrets which are disclosed only to the 
eye of the physicist and chemist; but where would natural science be 
without industry and commerce? Even this “pure” natural science is 
provided with an aim, as with its material, only through trade and 
industry, through the sensuous activity of men. So much is this 
activity, this unceasing sensuous labour and creation, this produc- 
tion, the foundation of the whole sensuous world as it now exists 
that, were it interrupted only for a year, Feuerbach would not only 
find an enormous change in the natural world, but would very soon 
find that the whole world of men and his own perceptive faculty, nay 
his own existence, were missing. Of course, in all this the priority of 
external nature remains unassailed, and all this has no 1 1 0 j 
application to the original men produced by generatio aequivocd 3 ; but 
this differentiation has meaning only insofar as man is considered 
to be distinct from nature. For that matter, nature, the nature 
that preceded human history, is not by any means the nature 
in which Feuerbach lives, it is nature which today no longer exists 
anywhere (except perhaps on a few Australian coral islands of 
recent origin) and which, therefore, does not exist for Feuerbach 
either. 

1 9 1 Certainly Feuerbach has |10| a great advantage over the 
“pure” materialists since he realises that man too is an “object of the 



3 Paraphrase of a line from Goethe’s Faust, “Prolog im Himmel”. — Ed. 
b Spontaneous generation. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. I. Feuerbach 



41 



senses”. But apart from the fact that he only conceives him as an 
“object of the senses”, not as “sensuous activity”, because he still 
remains in the realm of theory and conceives of men not in their 
given social connection, not under their existing conditions of life, 
which have made them what they are, he never arrives at the actually 
existing, active men, but stops at the abstraction “man”, and gets no 
further than recognising “the actual, individual, corporeal man” 
emotionally, i.e., he knows no other “human relations” “of man to 
man” than love and friendship, and even then idealised. He gives no 
criticism of the present conditions of life. Thus he never manages to 
conceive the sensuous world as the total living sensuous activity of the 
individuals composing it; therefore when, for example, he sees 
instead of healthy men a crowd of scrofulous, overworked and 
consumptive starvelings, he is compelled to take refuge in the 
“higher perception” and in the ideal “compensation in the species”, 
and thus to relapse into idealism at the very point where the 
communist materialist sees the necessity, and at the same time the 
condition, of a transformation both of industry and of the social 
structure. 

As far as Feuerbach is a materialist he does not deal with history, 
and as far as he considers history he is not a materialist. With him 
materialism and history diverge completely, a fact which incidentally 
already follows from what has been said.* 



[3. PRIMARY HISTORICAL RELATIONS, 

OR THE BASIC ASPECTS OF SOCIAL ACTIVITY: 

PRODUCTION OF THE MEANS OF SUBSISTENCE, 

PRODUCTION OF NEW NEEDS, REPRODUCTION OF MEN (THE FAMILY), 
SOCIAL INTERCOURSE, CONSCIOUSNESS] 

1 1 1 1 ** Since we are dealing with the Germans, who are devoid of 
premises, we must begin by stating the first premise of all human 
existence and, therefore, of all history, the premise, namely, that 
men must be in a position to live in order to be able to “make 
history”. 3 But life involves before everything else eating and 

* [The following passage is crossed out in the manuscript:] The reason why we 
nevertheless discuss history here in greater detail is that the words “history” and 
“historical” usually mean everything possible to the Germans except reality, a brilliant 
example of this is in particular Saint Bruno with his “pulpit eloquence”. 

** [Marginal note by Marx:] History. 



See this volume, pp. 56-57. — Ed. 




42 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



drinking, housing, clothing and various other things.* The first 
historical act is thus the production of the means to satisfy these 
needs, the production of material life itself. And indeed this is an 
historical act, a fundamental condition of all history, which today, as 
thousands of years ago, must daily and hourly be fulfilled merely in 
order to sustain human life. Even when the sensuous world is 
reduced to a minimum, to a stick 3 as with Saint Bruno, it 
presupposes the action of producing this stick. Therefore in any 
conception of history one has first of all to observe this fundamental 
fact in all its significance and all its implications and to accord it its 
due importance. It is well known that the Germans have never done 
this, and they have never, therefore, had an earthly basis for history 
and consequently never a historian. The French and the English, 
even if they have conceived the relation of this fact with so-called 
history only in an extremely one-sided fashion, especially since they 
remained in the toils of political ideology, have nevertheless made 
the first attempts to give the writing of history a materialistic basis by 
being the first to write histories of civil society, of commerce and 
industry. 16 

The second point is [12] that the satisfaction of the first need, the 
action of satisfying and the instrument of satisfaction which has been 
acquired, leads to new needs; and this creation of new needs is the 
first historical act. Here we recognise immediately the spiritual 
ancestry of the great historical wisdom of the Germans who, when 
they run out of positive material and when they can serve up neither 
theological nor political nor literary rubbish, assert that this is not 
history at all, but the “prehistoric age”. They do not, however, 
enlighten us as to how we proceed from this nonsensical “prehis- 
tory” to history proper; although, on the other hand, in their 
historical speculation they seize upon this “prehistory” with especial 
eagerness because they imagine themselves safe there from interfer- 
ence on the part of “crude facts”, and, at the same time, because 
there they can give full rein to their speculative impulse and set up 
and knock down hypotheses by the thousand. 

The third circumstance which, from the very outset, enters into 
historical development, is that men, who daily re-create their own life, 
begin to make other men, to propagate their kind: the relation 

* [Marginal note by Marx:] Hegel Geological, hydrographical, etc., conditions. 15 
Human bodies. Needs, labour. 



a See Bruno Bauer’s article “Charakteristik Ludwig Feuerbachs”. Cf. this volume, 
pp. 94, 104. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. I. Feuerbach 



43 



between man and woman, parents and children, the family. The 
family, which to begin with is the only social relation, becomes later, 
when increased needs create new social relations and the increased 
population new needs, a subordinate one (except in Germany), and 
must then be treated and analysed according to the existing empirical 
data, not according to “the concept of the family”, as is the custom in 
Germany. 

These three aspects of social activity are not of course to be taken 
as three different stages, but just as three aspects or, to make it clear 
to the Germans, three “moments”, which have existed simultaneous- 
ly since the dawn of history and the first men, and which still assert 
themselves in history today. 

The production of life, both of one’s own in labour and of fresh 
life in procreation, now appears as a twofold 1 13 1 relation: on the one 
hand as a natural, on the other as a social relation — social in the 
sense that it denotes the co-operation of several individuals, no 
matter under what conditions, in what manner and to what end. It 
follows from this that a certain mode of production, or industrial 
stage, is always combined with a certain mode of co-operation, or 
social stage, and this mode of co-operation is itself a “productive 
force”. Further, that the aggregate of productive forces accessible to 
men determines the condition of society, hence, the “history of 
humanity” must always be studied and treated in relation to the 
history of industry and exchange. But it is also clear that in Germany 
it is impossible to write this sort of history, because the Germans lack 
not only the necessary power of comprehension and the material but 
also the “sensuous certainty”, for across the Rhine one cannot have 
any experience of these things since there history has stopped 
happening. Thus it is quite obvious from the start that there exists a 
materialist connection of men with one another, which is determined 
by their needs and their mode of production, and which is as old as 
men themselves. This connection is ever taking on new forms, 
and thus presents a “history” irrespective of the existence of any 
political or religious nonsense which would especially hold men 
together. 

Only now, after having considered four moments, four aspects of 
primary historical relations, do we find that man also possesses 
“consciousness”.* But even from the outset this is not “pure” 
consciousness. The “mind” is from the outset afflicted with 1 14 1 the 



* [Marginal note by Marx:] Men have history because they must produce their life, 
and because they must produce it moreover in a certain way: this is determined by 
their physical organisation: their consciousness is determined in just the same way. 




44 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



curse of being “burdened” with matter, which here makes its 
appearance in the form of agitated layers of air, sounds, in short, 
of language. Language is as old as consciousness, language is 
practical, real consciousness that exists for other men as well, and 
only therefore does it also exist for me; language, like consciousness, 
only arises from the need, the necessity, of intercourse with other 
men.* Where there exists a relationship, it exists for me: the animal 
does not “ relate ” itself to anything, it does not “ relate ” itself at all. For 
the animal its relation to others does not exist as a relation. 
Consciousness is, therefore, from the very beginning a social 
product, and remains so as long as men exist at all. Consciousness is 
at first, of course, merely consciousness concerning the immediate 
sensuous environment and consciousness of the limited connection 
with other persons and things outside the individual who is growing 
self-conscious. At the same time it is consciousness of nature, which 
first confronts men as a completely alien, all-powerful and unassail- 
able force, with which men’s relations are purely animal and by which 
they are overawed like beasts; it is thus a purely animal consciousness 
of nature (natural religion) precisely because nature is as yet hardly 
altered by history — on the other hand, it is man’s consciousness of 
the necessity of associating with the individuals around him, the 
beginning of the consciousness that he is living in society at all. This 
beginning is as animal as social life itself at this stage. It is mere 
herd-consciousness, and at this point man is distinguished from 
sheep only by the fact that with him consciousness takes the place of 
instinct or that his instinct is a conscious one.** This sheep-like or 
tribal consciousness receives its further development and extension 
through increased productivity, the increase of needs, and, what is 
fundamental to both of these, 1 15 1 the increase of population. With 
these there develops the division of labour, which was originally 
nothing but the division of labour in the sexual act, then the division 
of labour which develops spontaneously or “naturally” by virtue of 
natural predisposition (e.g., physical strength), needs, accidents, etc., 
etc.*** Division of labour only becomes truly such from the moment 

* [The following words are crossed out in the manuscript:] My relation to my 
surroundings is my consciousness. 

** [Marginal note by Marx:] We see here immediately: this natural religion or this 
particular attitude to nature is determined by the form of society and vice versa. Here, 
as everywhere, the identity of nature and man also appears in such a way that the 
restricted attitude of men to nature determines their restricted relation to one 
another, and their restricted attitude to one another determines men’s restricted 
relation to nature. 

*** [Marginal note by Marx, which is crossed out in the manuscript:] Men’s 
consciousness develops in the course of actual historical development. 




The German Ideology. I. Feuerbach 



45 



when a division of material and mental labour appears.* From this 
moment onwards consciousness can really flatter itself that it is 
something other than consciousness of existing practice, that it really 
represents something without representing something real; from 
now on consciousness is in a position to emancipate itself trom the 
world and to proceed to the formation of “pure” theory, theology, 
philosophy, morality, etc. But even if this theory, theology, 
philosophy, morality, etc., come into contradiction with the existing 
relations, this can only occur because existing social relations have 
come into contradiction with existing productive forces; moreover, 
in a particular national sphere of relations this can also occur 
through the contradiction, arising not within the national orbit, but 
between this national consciousness and the practice of other 
nations,** i.e., between the national and the general consciousness of 
a nation (as is happening now in Germany); but since this 
contradiction appears to exist only as a contradiction within the 
national consciousness, it seems to this nation that the struggle too is 
confined to this |16| national muck, precisely because this nation 
represents this muck as such. 

Incidentally, it is quite immaterial what consciousness starts to 
do on its own: out of all this trash we get only the one inference 
that these three moments, the productive forces, the state of 
society and consciousness, can and must come into contradiction 
with one another, because the division of labour implies the possibility, 
nay the fact, that intellectual and material activity,*** that enjoyment 
and labour, production and consumption, devolve on different 
individuals, and that the only possibility of their not coming into 
contradiction lies in negating in its turn the division of labour. It is 
self-evident, moreover, that “spectres”, “bonds”, “the higher 
being”, “concept”, “scruple”, are merely idealist, speculative, mental 
expressions, the concepts apparently of the isolated individual, the 
mere images of very empirical fetters and limitations, within which 
move the mode of production of life, and the form of intercourse 
coupled with it.**** 



* [Marginal note by Marx:] The first form of ideologists, priests, is coincident 

** [Marginal note by Marx:] Religions. The Germans and ideology as such. 

*** [Marginal note by Marx, which is crossed out in the manuscript:] activity 
and thinking, i.e., action without thought and thought without action. 

**** [The following sentence is crossed out in the manuscript:] This idealist 
expression of actually present economic limitations exists not only purely theoretically 
but also in the practical consciousness, i.e., consciousness which emancipates itself and 
comes into contradiction with the existing mode of production devises not only 
religions and philosophies but also states. 




46 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



[4. SOCIAL DIVISION OF LABOUR AND ITS CONSEQUENCES: 

PRIVATE PROPERTY, THE STATE, 

“ESTRANGEMENT” OF SOCIAL ACTIVITY] 

The division of labour in which all these contradictions are 
implicit, and which in its turn is based on the natural division of 
labour in the family and the separation of society into individual 
families opposed to one another, simultaneously implies the 
distribution, and indeed the unequal distribution, both quantitative 
and qualitative, of labour and its products, hence property, 1 1 7 1 the 
nucleus, the first form of which lies in the family, where wife and 
children are the slaves of the husband. This latent slavery in the 
family, though still very crude, is the first form of property, but even 
at this stage it corresponds perfectly to the definition of modern 
economists, who call it the power of disposing of the labour-power of 
others. Division of labour and private property are, after all, 
identical expressions: in the one the same thing is affirmed with 
reference to activity as is affirmed in the other with reference to the 
product of the activity. 

Further, the division of labour also implies the contradiction 
between the interest of the separate individual or the individual 
family and the common interest of all individuals who have 
intercourse with one another. And indeed, this common interest 
does not exist merely in the imagination, as the “general interest”, 
but first of all in reality, as the mutual interdependence of the 
individuals among whom the labour is divided. 3 

Out of this very contradiction between the particular and the 
common interests, the common interest assumes an independent 
form as the state, which is divorced from the real individual and 
collective interests, and at the same time as an illusory community, 
always based, however, on the real ties existing in every family 
conglomeration and tribal conglomeration — such as flesh and blood, 
language, division of labour on a larger scale, and other inter- 
ests — and especially, as we shall show later, on the classes, already 
implied by the division of labour, which in every such mass of men 
separate out, and one of which dominates all the others. It follows 
from this that all struggles within the state, the struggle between 
democracy, aristocracy, and monarchy, the struggle for the fran- 
chise, etc., etc., are merely the illusory forms — altogether the general 



3 The following two paragraphs are written in the margin: the first by Engels and 
the second by Marx. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. I. Feuerbach 



47 



interest is the illusory form of common interests — in which the real 
struggles of the different classes are fought out among one another 
(of this the German theoreticians have not the faintest inkling, 
although they have received a sufficient initiation into the subject in 
the Deutsch-Franzosische Jahrbiicher 17 and Die heilige Familie). Further, 
it follows that every class which is aiming at domination, even when its 
domination, as is the case with the proletariat, leads to the abolition 
of the old form of society in its entirety and of domination in general, 
must first conquer political power in order to represent its interest 
in turn as the general interest, which in the first moment it is 
forced to do. 

Just because individuals seek only their particular interest, which 
for them does not coincide with their common interest, the latter is 
asserted as an interest “alien” [“fremd”] to them, and 1 1 8 1 
“independent” of them, as in its turn a particular and distinctive 
“general” interest; or they themselves must remain within this 
discord, as in democracy. On the other hand, too, the practical 
struggle of these particular interests, which actually constantly run 
counter to the common and illusory common interests, necessitates 
practical intervention and restraint by the illusory “general” interest 
in the form of the state. 

1 1 7 1 And finally, the division of labour offers us the first example 
of the fact that, as long as man remains in naturally evolved society, 
that is, as long as a cleavage exists between the particular and the 
common interest, as long, therefore, as activity is not voluntarily, but 
naturally, divided, man’s own deed becomes an alien power opposed 
to him, which enslaves him instead of being controlled by him. For as 
soon as the division of labour comes into being, each man has a 
particular, exclusive sphere of activity, which is forced upon him and 
from which he cannot escape. He is a hunter, a fisherman, a 
shepherd, or a critical critic, and must remain so if he does not want 
to lose his means of livelihood; whereas in communist society, where 
nobody has one exclusive sphere of activity but each can become 
accomplished in any branch he wishes, society regulates the general 
production and thus makes it possible for me to do one thing today 
and another tomorrow, to hunt in the morning, fish in the 
afternoon, rear cattle in the evening, criticise after dinner, just as I 
have a mind, without ever becoming hunter, fisherman, shepherd 
or critic. 

1 18 1 This fixation of social activity, this consolidation of what we 
ourselves produce into a material power above us, growing out of 
our, control, thwarting our expectations, bringing to naught our 
calculations, is one of the chief factors in historical development up 




48 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



till now. 3 The social power, i.e., the multiplied productive force, 
which arises through the co-operation of different individuals as it is 
caused by the division of labour, appears to these individuals, since 
their co-operation is not voluntary but has come about naturally, not 
as their own united power, but as an alien force existing outside 
them, of the origin and goal of which they are ignorant, which they 
thus are no longer able to control, which on the contrary passes 
through a peculiar series of phases and stages independent of the 
will and the action 18 of man, nay even being the prime governor of 
these. How otherwise could for instance property have had a history 
at all, have taken on different forms, and landed property, for 
example, according to the different premises given, have 
proceeded in France from parcellation to centralisation in the hands 
of a few, in England from centralisation in the hands of a few to 
parcellation, as is actually the case today? Or how does it happen that 
trade, which after all is nothing more than the exchange of products 
of various individuals and countries, rules the whole world through 
the relation of supply and demand — a relation which, as an English 
economist says, hovers over the earth like the fate of the ancients, 
and with invisible hand allots fortune and misfortune to men, sets up 
empires |19| and wrecks empires, causes nations to rise and to 
disappear — whereas with the abolition of the basis, private property, 
with the communistic regulation of production (and, implicit in this, 
the abolition of the alien attitude [Fremdheit] of men to their own 
product), the power of the relation of supply and demand is dissolved 
into nothing, and men once more gain control of exchange, 
production and the way they behave to one another? 



[5. DEVELOPMENT OF THE PRODUCTIVE FORCES 
AS A MATERIAL PREMISE OF COMMUNISM] 

[ 18 1 This “estrangement” [“ Entfremdung ”] (to use a term which 
will be comprehensible to the philosophers) can, of course, only be 
abolished given two practical premises. In order to become an 
“unendurable” power, i.e., a power against which men make a revolu- 
tion, it must necessarily have rendered the great mass of humanity 
“propertyless”, and moreover in contradiction to an existing world 
of wealth and culture; both these premises presuppose a great 
increase in productive power, a high degree of its development. 



a Here Marx added a passage in the margin which is given in this edition as the 
first two paragraphs of Section 5. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. I. Feuerbach 



49 



And, on the other hand, this development of productive forces 
(which at the same time implies the actual empirical existence of men 
in their world-historical, instead of local, being) is an absolutely 
necessary practical premise, because without it privation, want is 
merely made general, and with want the struggle for necessities 
would begin again, and all the old filthy business would necessarily 
be restored; and furthermore, because only with this universal 
development of productive forces is a universal intercourse between 
men established, which on the one side produces in all nations 
simultaneously the phenomenon of the “propertyless” mass (univer- 
sal competition), making each nation dependent on the revolutions 
of the others, and finally puts world-historical, empirically universal 
individuals in place of local ones. Without this, 1) communism could 
only exist as a local phenomenon; 2) the forces of intercourse 
themselves could not have developed as universal, hence unendurable 
powers: they would have remained home-bred “conditions” sur- 
rounded by superstition; and 3) each extension of intercourse would 
abolish local communism. Empirically, communism is only possible 
as the act of the dominant peoples “all at once” and simultaneously, 19 
which presupposes the universal development of productive forces 
and the world intercourse bound up with them.* 

[19 1 Moreover, the mass of workers who are nothing but 
workers — labour-power on a mass scale cut off from capital or from 
even a limited satisfaction [of their needs] and, hence, as a result of 
competition their utterly precarious position, the no longer merely 
temporary loss of work as a secure source of life — presupposes the 
world market. The proletariat can thus only exist world-historically, just 
as communism, its activity, can only have a “world-historical” 
existence. World-historical existence of individuals, i.e., existence of 
individuals which is directly linked up with world history. 

1 1 8 1 Communism is for us not a state of affairs which is to be 
established, an ideal to which reality [will] have to adjust itself. We 
call communism the real movement which abolishes the present state 
of things. The conditions of this movement result from the now 
existing premise. 3 



* * * 

* [Above the continuation of this passage, which follows on the next page of the 
manuscript, Marx wrote:] Communism. 



3 In the manuscript this paragraph was written down by Marx in a free space 
above the paragraph starting with the words: This “estrangement”. — Ed. 




50 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



1 1 9| The form of intercourse determined by the existing 
productive forces at all previous historical stages, and in its turn 
determining these, is civil society. The latter, as is clear from what we 
have said above, has as its premise and basis the simple family 
and the multiple, called the tribe, and the more precise definition of 
this society is given in our remarks above. Already here we see that 
this civil society is the true focus and theatre of all history, and 
how absurd is the conception of history held hitherto, which neg- 
lects the real relations and confines itself to spectacular historical 
events. 20 

In the main we have so far considered only one aspect of human 
activity, the reshaping of nature by men. The other aspect, the 
reshaping of men by men. ... * 

Origin of the state and the relation of the state to civil society. 3 

[6. CONCLUSIONS FROM THE MATERIALIST CONCEPTION 
OF HISTORY: HISTORY AS A CONTINUOUS PROCESS, 

HISTORY AS BECOMING WORLD HISTORY, 

THE NECESSITY OF COMMUNIST REVOLUTION] 

1 20 1 History is nothing but the succession of the separate 
generations, each of which uses the materials, the capital funds, the 
productive forces handed down to it by all preceding generations, 
and thus, on the one hand, continues the traditional activity in 
completely changed circumstances and, on the other, modifies the 
old circumstances with a completely changed activity. This can be 
speculatively distorted so that later history is made the goal of earlier 
history, e.g., the goal ascribed to the discovery of America is to 
further the eruption of the French Revolution. Thereby history 
receives its own special goals and becomes “a person ranking with 
other persons” (to wit: “self-consciousness, criticism, the unique”, 
etc.), while what is designated with the words “destiny”, “goal”, 
“germ”, or “idea” of earlier history is nothing more than an 
abstraction from later history, from the active influence which earlier 
history exercises on later history. 

The further the separate spheres, which act on one another, 
extend in the course of this development and the more the original 
isolation of the separate nationalities is destroyed by the advanced 



* [Marginal note by Marx:] Intercourse and productive power. 



a The end of this page of the manuscript is left blank. The next page begins with 
an exposition of the conclusions from the materialist conception of history. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. I. Feuerbach 



51 



mode of production, by intercourse and by the natural division of 
labour Between various nations arising as a result, the more history 
becomes world history. Thus, for instance, if in England a machine is 
invented which deprives countless workers of bread in India and 
China, and overturns the whole form of existence of these empires, 
this invention becomes a world-historical fact. Or again, take the case 
of sugar and coffee, which have proved their world-historical 
importance in the nineteenth century by the fact that the lack of 
these products, occasioned by the Napoleonic Continental System, 21 
caused the Germans [21] to rise against Napoleon, and thus became 
the real basis of the glorious Wars of Liberation of 1813. From this it 
follows that this transformation of history into world history is by no 
means a mere abstract act on the part of “self-consciousness”, the 
world spirit, or of any other metaphysical spectre, but a quite 
material, empirically verifiable act, an act the proof of which every 
individual furnishes as he comes and goes, eats, drinks and clothes 
himself. 

In history up to the present it is certainly likewise an empirical fact 
that separate individuals have, with the broadening of their activity 
into world-historical activity, become more and more enslaved under 
a power alien to them (a pressure which they have conceived of as a 
dirty trick on the part of the so-called world spirit, etc.), a power 
which has become more and more enormous and, in the last 
instance, turns out to be the world market. But it is just as empirically 
established that, by the overthrow of the existing state of society by 
the communist revolution (of which more below) and the abolition of 
private property which is identical with it, this power, which so 
baffles the German theoreticians, will be dissolved; and that then the 
liberation of each single individual will be accomplished in the 
measure in which history becomes wholly transformed into world 
history.* From the above it is clear that the real intellectual wealth of 
the individual depends entirely on the wealth of his real connections. 
Only this will liberate the separate individuals from the various 
national and local barriers, bring them into practical connection with 
the production (including intellectual production) of the whole 
world and make it possible for them to acquire the capacity to enjoy 
this all-sided production of the whole earth (the creations of man). 
All-round dependence, this primary natural form of the world- 
historical co-operation of individuals, will be transformed by [22] this 
communist revolution into the control and conscious mastery of 
these powers, which, born of the action of men on one another, have 



[Marginal note by Marx:] On the production of consciousness. 




52 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



till now overawed and ruled men as powers completely alien to them. 
Now this view can be expressed again in a speculative-idealistic, i.e., 
fantastic, way as “self-generation of the species” (“society as the 
subject”), and thereby the consecutive series of interrelated individu- 
als can be regarded as a single individual, which accomplishes the 
mystery of generating itself. In this context it is evident that 
individuals undoubtedly make one another, physically and mentally, 
but do not make themselves, either in the nonsense of Saint Bruno, 
or in the sense of the “unique”, of the “made” man. 

Finally, from the conception of history set forth by us we obtain 
these further conclusions: 1) In the development of productive 
forces there comes a stage when productive forces and means of 
intercourse are brought into being which, under the existing 
relations, only cause mischief, and are no longer productive but 
destructive forces (machinery and money); and connected with this a 
class is called forth which has to bear all the burdens of society 
without enjoying its advantages, which is ousted from society and 
[23] forced into the sharpest contradiction to all other classes; a class 
which forms the majority of all members of society, and from which 
emanates the consciousness of the necessity of a fundamental 
revolution, the communist consciousness, which may, of course, arise 
among the other classes too through the contemplation of the 
situation of this class. 2) The conditions under which definite 
productive forces can be applied are the conditions of the rule of a 
definite class of society, whose social power, deriving from its 
property, has its practical-idealistic expression in each case in the 
form of the state and, therefore, every revolutionary struggle is 
directed against a class which till then has been in power.* 3) In all 
previous revolutions the mode of activity always remained un- 
changed and it was only a question of a different distribution of this 
activity, a new distribution of labour to other persons, whilst the 
communist revolution is directed against the hitherto existing mode 
of activity, does away with labour,** and abolishes the rule of all 
classes with the classes themselves, because it is carried through by 
the class which no longer counts as a class in society, which is not 
recognised as a class, and is in itself the expression of the dissolution 
of all classes, nationalities, etc., within present society; and 4) Both 
for the production on a mass scale of this communist consciousness, 



* [Marginal note by Marx:] These men are interested in maintaining the 
present state of production. 

** [The following words are crossed out in the manuscript:] the modern form of 
activity under the rule of [...]. 




The German Ideology. I. Feuerbach 



53 



and for the success of the cause itself, the alteration of men on a mass 
scale is necessary, an alteration which can only take place in a 
practical movement, a revolution ; the revolution is necessary, 
therefore, not only because the ruling class cannot be overthrown in 
any other way, but also because the class overthrowing it can only in a 
revolution succeed in ridding itself of all the muck of ages and 
become fitted to found society anew.* 



[7. SUMMARY OF THE MATERIALIST CONCEPTION 
OF HISTORY] 

|24(This conception of history thus relies on expounding the real 
process of production — starting from the material production of life 
itself — ^and comprehending the form of intercourse connected with 
and created by this mode of production, i.e., civil society in its various 
stages, as the basis of all history; describing it in its action as the state, 
and also explaining how all the different theoretical products and 
forms of consciousness, religion, philosophy, morality, etc., etc., arise 
from it, and tracing the process of their formation from that basis; 
thus the whole thing can, of course, be depicted in its totality (and 
therefore, too, the reciprocal action of these various sides on one 
another). It has not, like the idealist view of history, to look for a 
category in every period, but remains constantly on the real ground of 



* [The following passage is crossed out in the manuscript:] Whereas all 
communists in France as well as in England and Germany have long since agreed on 
the necessity of the revolution, Saint Bruno quietly continues to dream, opining that 
“real humanism”, i. e., communism, is to take “the place of spiritualism” (which has 
no place) only in order that it may gain respect. Then, he continues in his dream, 
“salvation” would indeed “be attained, the earth becoming heaven, and heaven 
earth”. (The theologian is still unable to forget heaven.) “Then joy and bliss will 
resound in celestial harmonies to all eternity” (p. 140). a The holy father of the 
church will be greatly surprised when judgment day overtakes him, the day when all 
this is to come to pass — a day when the reflection in the sky of burning cities will mark 
the dawn, when together with the “celestial harmonies” the tunes of the Marseillaise 
and Carmagnole will echo in his ears accompanied by the requisite roar of cannon, with 
the guillotine beating time; when the infamous “masses” will shout fa ira, f a ira and 
suspend “self-consciousness” by means of the lamp-post. 22 Saint Bruno has no reason 
at all to draw an edifying picture “of joy and bliss to all eternity”. We forego the 
pleasure of a priori forecasting Saint Bruno’s conduct on judgment day. Moreover, it 
is really difficult to decide whether the proletaires en revolution have to be conceived as 
“substance”, as “mass”, desiring to overthrow' criticism, or as an “emanation” of the 
spirit which is, however, still lacking the consistency necessary to digest Bauer’s ideas. 



Bruno Bauer, “Charakteristik Ludwig Feuerbachs”. — Ed. 




54 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



history; it does not explain practice from the idea but explains the 
formation of ideas from material practice, and accordingly it comes to 
the conclusion that all forms and products of consciousness cannot be 
dissolved by mental criticism, by resolution into “self-consciousness” 
or transformation into “apparitions”, “spectres”, “whimsies”, 3 etc., 
but only by the practical overthrow of the actual social relations which 
gave rise to this idealistic humbug; that not criticism but revolution is 
the driving force of history, also of religion, of philosophy and all 
other kinds of theory. It shows that history does not end by being 
resolved into “self-consciousness” as “spirit of the spirit”, b but that 
each stage contains a material result, a sum of productive forces, a 
historically created relation to nature and of individuals to one 
another, which is handed down to each generation from its 
predecessor; a mass of productive forces, capital funds and 
circumstances, which on the one hand is indeed modified by the new 
generation, but on the other also prescribes for it its conditions of life 
and gives it a definite development, a special character. It shows that 
circumstances make [25] men just as much as men make 
circumstances. 

This sum of productive forces, capital funds and social forms of 
intercourse, which every individual and every generation finds in 
existence as something given, is the real basis of what the 
philosophers have conceived as “substance” and “essence of man”, 
and what they have deified and attacked: a real basis which is not in 
the least disturbed, in its effect and influence on the development of 
men, by the fact that these philosophers revolt against it as 
“self-consciousness” and the “unique”. These conditions of life, 
which different generations find in existence, determine also 
whether or not the revolutionary convulsion periodically recurring 
in history will be strong enough to overthrow the basis of everything 
that exists. And if these material elements of a complete revolution are 
not present — namely, on the one hand the existing productive 
forces, on the other the formation of a revolutionary mass, which 
revolts not only against separate conditions of the existing society, 
but against the existing “production of life” itself, the “total activity” 
on which it was based — then it is absolutely immaterial for practical 
development whether the idea of this revolution has been expres- 
sed a hundred times already, as the history of communism proves. 



a These terms are used by Max Stirner in Der Einzige und sein Eigenthum. Cf. 
pp. 157-63 of this volume. — Ed. 

The terms are used by Bruno Bauer in “Charakteristik Ludwig Feuer- 
bachs”. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. I. Feuerbach 



55 



[8. THE INCONSISTENCY OF THE IDEALIST CONCEPTION 
OF HISTORY IN GENERAL AND OF GERMAN POST-HEGELIAN 
PHILOSOPHY IN PARTICULAR] 

In the whole conception of history up to the present this real basis 
of history has either been totally disregarded or else considered as a 
minor matter quite irrelevant to the course of history. History must, 
therefore, always be written according to an extraneous standard; 
the real production of life appears as non-historical, while the histori- 
cal appears as something separated from ordinary life, something 
extra-superterrestrial. With this the relation of man to nature is 
excluded from history and hence the antithesis of nature and history 
is created. The exponents of this conception of history have 
consequently only been able to see in history the spectacular political 
events and religious and other theoretical struggles, and in particular 
with regard to each historical epoch they were compelled to share the 
illusion of that epoch. For instance, if an epoch imagines itself to be 
actuated by purely ‘ political” or “religious” motives, although 
“religion” and ‘ politics” are only forms of its true motives, the 
historian accepts this opinion. The “fancy”, the “conception” of the 
people in question about their real practice is transformed into the 
soie determining and effective force, which dominates and deter- 
mines their practice. When the crude form of the division of labour 
which is to be found among the Indians and Egyptians calls forth the 
caste-svstem in their state and religion, the historian believes that the 
caste-system [26] is the power which has produced this crude social 
form. 

While the French and the English at least stick to the political 
illusion, which is after all closer to reality, the Germans move in the 
realm of the “pure spirit”, and make religious illusion the driving 
force of history. The Hegelian philosophy of history is the last 
consequence, reduced to its “clearest expression”, of all this German 
historiography for which it is not a question of real, nor even of poli- 
tical, interests, but of pure thoughts, which must therefore appear to 
Saint Bruno as a series of “thoughts” that devour one another and 
are finally swallowed up in “self-consciousness” *; and even more 
consistently the course of history must appear to Saint Max Stirner, 
who knows not a thing about real history, as a mere “tale of knights, 
robbers and ghosts”, 24 from whose visions he can, of course, only save 
himself by “unholiness”. This conception is truly religious: it 
postulates religious man as the primitive man, the starting-point of 

* [Marginal note by Marx:] So-called objective historiography 23 consisted precisely 
in treating the historical relations separately from activity. Reactionary character. 



4—2086 




56 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



history, and in its imagination puts the religious production of fancies 
in the place of the real production of the means of subsistence and of 
life itself. 

This whole conception of history, together with its dissolution and 
the scruples and qualms resulting from it, is a purely national affair 
of the Germans and has merely local interest for Germany, as for 
instance the important question which has been under discussion in 
recent times: how exactly one “passes from the realm of God to the 
realm of Man” 3 — as if this “realm of God” had ever existed 
anywhere save in the imagination, and the learned gentlemen, 
without being aware of it, were not constantly living in the “realm of 
Man” to which they are now seeking the way; and as if the learned 
pastime (for it is nothing more) of explaining the mystery of this 
theoretical bubble-blowing did not on the contrary lie in demonstrat- 
ing its origin in actual earthly relations. For these Germans, it is 
altogether simply a matter of resolving the ready-made nonsense 
they find into [27] some other freak, i.e., of presupposing that all 
this nonsense has a special sense which can be discovered; while really 
it is only a question of explaining these theoretical phrases from the 
actual existing relations. The real, practical dissolution of these 
phrases, the removal of these notions from the consciousness of 
men, will, as we have already said, be effected by altered circum- 
stances, not by theoretical deductions. For the mass of men, i.e., 
the proletariat, these theoretical notions do not exist and hence do 
not require to be dissolved, and if this mass ever had any theoret- 
ical notions, e.g., religion, these have now long been dissolved by 
circumstances. 

The purely national character of these questions and solutions is 
moreover shown by the fact that these theorists believe in all 
seriousness that chimeras like “the God-Man”, “Man”, etc., have 
presided over individual epochs of history (Saint Bruno even goes so 
far as to assert that only “criticism and critics have made history”, 1 ’ 
and when they themselves construct historical systems, they skip over 
all earlier periods in the greatest haste and pass immediately from 
“Mongolism” c to history “with meaningful content”, that is to say, to 
the history of the Hallische and Deutsche Jahrhiicher and the 
dissolution of the Hegelian school into a general squabble. They 
forget all other nations, all real events, and the theatrum mundi is 



3 Ludwig Feuerbach, “Ueber das ‘Wesen des Christenthums’.;.”. — Ed. 

Bruno Bauer, “Charakteristik Ludwig Feuerbachs”. — Ed. 
c Max Stirner, Der Einzige und sein Eigenthum. Cf. this volume, pp. 130-36. and 
pp. 163-70. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. I. Feuerbach 



57 



confined to the Leipzig book fair and the mutual quarrels of 
“criticism”, “man”, and “the unique”. 3 If for once these theorists 
treat really historical subjects, as for instance the eighteenth century, 
they merely give a history of ideas, separated from the facts and the 
practical development underlying them; and even that merely in 
order to represent that period as an imperfect preliminary stage, the 
as yet limited predecessor of the truly historical age, i.e., the period 
of the German philosophic struggle from 1840 to 1844. As might be 
expected when the history of an earlier period is written with the aim 
of accentuating the brilliance of an unhistoric person and his 
fantasies, all the really historic events, even the really historic 
interventions of politics in history, receive no mention. Instead we get 
a narrative based not on research but on arbitrary constructions and 
literary gossip, such as Saint Bruno provided in his now forgotten 
history of the eighteenth century. b These pompous and arrogant 
hucksters of ideas, who imagine themselves infinitely exalted above all 
national prejudices, are thus in practice far more national than the 
beer-swilling philistines who dream of a united Germany. They do not 
recognise the deeds of other nations as historical; they live in Germa- 
ny, within Germany |28| and for Germany; they turn the Rhine- 
song 25 into a religious hymn and conquer Alsace and Lorraine by 
robbing French philosophy instead of the French state, by Germani- 
sing French ideas instead of French provinces. Herr Venedey is a 
cosmopolitan compared with the Saints Bruno and Max, who, in 
the universal dominance of theory, proclaim the universal dominan - 
ce of Germany. 



[9. IDEALIST CONCEPTION OF HISTORY 
AND FEUERBACH’S QUASI-COMMUNISM] 

It is also clear from these arguments how grossly Feuerbach is 
deceiving himself when (Wigand’s Vierteljahrsschrift , 1845, Band 2) by 
virtue of the qualification “common man” he declares himself a 
communist, 26 transforms the latter into a predicate of “Man”, and 
thinks that it is thus possible to change the word “communist”, 
which in the real world means the follower of a definite revolution- 
ary party, into a mere category. Feuerbach’s whole deduction with 
regard to the relation of men to one another is only aimed at proving 
that men need and always have needed each other. He wants to 



3 I. e., Bruno Bauer, Ludwig Feuerbach and Max Stirner. — Ed. 
b Bruno Bauer, Geschichte der Politik, Cultur und Aufklarung des achtzehnten Jahr- 
hmiderts. — Ed. 




58 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



establish consciousness of this fact, that is to say, like the other 
theorists, he merely wants to produce a correct consciousness about 
an existing fact; whereas for the real Communist it is a question of 
overthrowing the existing state of things. We fully appreciate, 
however, that Feuerbach, in endeavouring to produce consciousness 
of just this fact, is going as far as a theorist possibly can, without 
ceasing to be a theorist and philosopher. It is characteristic, however, 
that Saint Bruno and Saint Max immediately put in place of the real 
communist Feuerbach’s conception of the communist; they do this 
partly in order to be able to combat communism too as “spirit of the 
spirit”, as a philosophical category, as an equal opponent and, in the 
case of Saint Bruno, also for pragmatic reasons. 

As an example of Feuerbach’s acceptance and at the same time 
misunderstanding of existing reality, which he still shares with our 
opponents, we recall the passage in the Philosophic der Zukunft where 
he develops the view that the being of a thing or a man is at the 
same time its or his essence, 3 that the determinate conditions of 
existence, the mode of life and activity of an animal or human 
individual are those in which its “essence” feels itself satisfied. Here 
every exception is expressly conceived as an unhappy chance, as an 
abnormality which cannot be altered. Thus if millions of proletarians 
feel by no means contented with their' living conditions, if their 
“being” |29| does not in the least correspond to their “essence”, 
then, according to the passage quoted, this is an unavoidable 
misfortune, which must be borne quietly. These millions of pro- 
letarians or communists, however, think quite differently and will 
prove this in time, when they bring their “being” into harmony 
with their “essence” in a practical way, by means of a revolution. 
Feuerbach, therefore, never speaks of the world of man in such 
cases, but always takes refuge in external nature, and moreover in 
nature which has not yet been subdued by men. But every new 
invention, every advance made by industry, detaches another piece 
from this domain, so that the ground which produces examples 
illustrating such Feuerbachian propositions is steadily shrinking. 
The “essence” of the fish is its “being”, water — to go no further 
than this one proposition. The “essence” of the freshwater fish is the 
water of a river. But the latter ceases to be the “essence” of the fish 
and is no longer a suitable medium of existence as soon as the 
river is made to serve industry, as soon as it is polluted by dyes and 
other waste products and navigated by steamboats, or as soon as its 
water is diverted into canals where simple drainage can deprive the 



a Cf. this volume, p. 13. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. I. Feuerbach 



59 



fish of its medium of existence. The explanation that all such 
contradictions are inevitable abnormalities does not essentially differ 
from the consolation which Saint Max Stirner offers to the 
discontented, saying that this contradiction is their own contradiction 
and this predicament their own predicament, whereupon they 
should either set their minds at ease, keep their disgust to 
themselves, or revolt against it in some fantastic way. It differs just as 
little from Saint Brunos allegation that these unfortunate cir- 
cumstances are due to the fact that those concerned are stuck in the 
muck of “substance”, ’nave not advanced to “absolute self- 
consciousness”, and do not realise that these adverse conditions are 
spirit of their spirit.' 1 

[Ill] 

[I. THE RULING CLASS AND THE RULING IDEAS. 

HOW THE HEGELIAN CONCEPTION OF THE DOMINATION 
OF THE SPIRIT IN HISTORY AROSE] 

1 30 i The ideas of the ruling class are in every epoch the ruling 
ideas: i.e., the class which is the ruling material force of society is at 
the same time its ruling intellectual force. The class which has the 
means of material production at its disposal, consequently also 
controls the means of mental production, so that the ideas of these 
who iack the means of mental production are on the whole subject to 
it. The ruling ideas are nothing more than the ideal expression of the 
dominant material relations, the dominant material relations 
grasped as ideas; hence of the relations which make the one 
ciass the ruling one, therefore, the ideas of its dominance. The 
individuals composing the ruling class possess among other things 
consciousness, and therefore think. Insofar, therefore, as they rule 
as a class and determine the extent and compass of an historical 
epoch, it is self-evident that they do this in its whole range, hence 
among other tilings rule also as thinkers, as producers of ideas, and 
regulate the production and distribution of the ideas of their age: 
thus their ideas are the ruling ideas of the epoch. For instance, in an 
age and in a country where royal power, aristocracy and bourgeoisie 
are contending for domination and where, therefore, domination 
is shared, the doctrine of the separation of powers proves to be 
the dominant idea and is expressed as an “eternal law”. 

The division of labour, which we already saw above (pp. [15-18]) b 
as one of the chief forces of history up till now, manifests itself also in 



3 Bruno Bauer, Charakteristik Ludwig Feuerbachs”. — Ed. 
h See this volume, pp. 44-48. — Ed. 




60 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



the ruling class as the division of mental and [3 1 1 material labour, so 
that inside this class one part appears as the thinkers of the class (its 
active, conceptive ideologists, who make the formation of the 
illusions of the class about itself their chief source of livelihood), 
while the others’ attitude to these ideas and illusions is more passive 
and receptive, because they are in reality the active members of this 
class and have less time to make up illusions and ideas about 
themselves. Within this class this cleavage can even develop into a 
certain opposition and hostility between the two parts, but whenever 
a practical collision occurs in which the class itself is endangered they 
automatically vanish, in which case there also vanishes the 
appearance of the ruling ideas being not the ideas of the ruling class 
and having a power distinct from the power of this class. The 
existence of revolutionary ideas in a particular period presupposes 
the existence of a revolutionary class: about the premises of the 
latter sufficient has already been said above (pp. [18-19, 22-23]). a 

If now in considering the course of history we detach the ideas of 
the ruling class from the ruling class itself and attribute to them an 
independent existence, if we confine ourselves to saying that these or 
those ideas were dominant at a given time, without bothering 
ourselves about the conditions of production and the producers of 
these ideas, if we thus ignore the individuals and world conditions 
which are the source of the ideas, then we can say, for instance, that 
during the time the aristocracy was dominant, the concepts honour, 
loyalty, etc., were dominant, during the dominance of the 
bourgeoisie the concepts freedom, equality, etc. The ruling class 
itself on the whole imagines this to be so. This conception of history, 
which is common to all historians, particularly since the eighteenth 
century, will necessarily come up against [32] the phenomenon that 
ever more abstract ideas hold sway, i.e., ideas which increasingly 
take on the form of universality. For each new class which puts itself 
in the place of one ruling before it is compelled, merely in order to 
carry through its aim, to present its interest as the common interest 
of all the members of society, that is, expressed in ideal form: it has 
to give its ideas the form of universality, and present them as the only 
rational, universally valid ones. The class making a revolution comes 
forward from the very start, if only because it is opposed to a class, 
not as a class but as the representative of the whole of society, as the 
whole mass of society confronting the one ruling class.* It can do this 

* [Marginal note by Marx:] (Universality corresponds to 1) the class versus the 
estate, 2) the competition, world intercourse, etc., 3) the great numerical strength 

a See this volume, pp. 48-49 and 52-53. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. I. Feuerbach 



61 



because initially its interest really is as yet mostly connected with the 
common interest of all other non-ruling classes, because under the 
pressure of hitherto existing conditions its interest has not yet been 
able to develop as the particular interest of a particular class. Its 
victory, therefore, benefits also many individuals of other classes 
which are not winning a dominant position, but only insofar as it now 
enables these individuals to raise themselves into the ruling class. 
When the French bourgeoisie overthrew the rule of the aristocra- 
cy, it thereby made it possible for many proletarians to raise 
themselves above the proletariat, but only insofar as they became 
bourgeois. Every new class, therefore, achieves domination only on 
a broader basis than that of the class ruling previously; on the other 
hand the opposition of the non-ruling class to the new ruling class 
then develops all the more sharply and profoundly. Both these 
things determine the fact that the struggle to be waged against this 
new ruling class, in its turn, has as its aim a more decisive and more 
radical negation of the previous conditions of society than [33] all 
previous classes which sought to rule could have. 

This whole appearance, that the rule of a certain class is only the 
rule of certain ideas, comes to a natural end, of course, as soon as 
class rule in general ceases to be the form in which society is 
organised, that is to say, as soon as it is no longer necessary to 
represent a particular interest as general or the “general interest” as 
ruling. 

Once the ruling ideas have been separated from the ruling 
individuals and, above all, from the relations which result from a 
given stage of the mode of production, and in this way the conclusion 
has been reached that history is always under the sway of ideas, it is 
very easy to abstract from these various ideas “the Idea”, the thought, 
etc., as the dominant force in history, and thus to consider all these 
separate ideas and concepts as “forms of self-determination” of the 
Concept developing in history. It follows then naturally, too, that all 
the relations of men can be derived from the concept of man, man as 
conceived, the essence of man, Man. This has been done by 
speculative philosophy. Hegel himself confesses at the end of the 
Geschichtsphilosophi ? that he “has considered the progress of the 
concept only” and has represented in history the “true theodicy ” 
(p. 446). Now one can go back again to the producers of “the con- 



of the ruling class, 4) the illusion of the common interests, in the beginning this 
illusion is true, 5) the delusion of the ideologists and the division of labour.) 



? G. W. F. Hegel, Vorlesungen Ober die Philosophic der Geschichte. — Ed. 




62 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



cept”, to the theorists, ideologists and philosophers, and one comes 
then to the conclusion that the philosophers, the thinkers as such, 
have at all times been dominant in history: a conclusion, as we see, 27 
already expressed by Hegel. 

The whole trick of proving the hegemony of the spirit in history 
(hierarchy Stirner calls it) is thus confined to the following three 
attempts. 

j 34 1 No. 1. One must separate the ideas of those ruling for 
empirical reasons, under empirical conditions and as corporeal 
individuals, from these rulers, and thus recognise the rule of ideas or 
illusions in history. 

No. 2. One must bring an order into this rule of ideas, prove a 
mystical connection among the successive ruling ideas, which is 
managed by regarding them as “forms of self-determination of the 
concept” (this is possible because by virtue of their empirical basis 
these ideas are really connected with one another and because, 
conceived as mere ideas, they become self-distinctions, distinctions 
made by thought). 

No. 3. To remove the mystical appearance of this “self- 
determining concept” it is changed into a person — “self- 
consciousness” — or, to appear thoroughly materialistic, into a series 
of persons, who represent the “concept” in history, into the 
“thinkers”, the “philosophers”, the ideologists, who again are 
understood as the manufacturers of history, as the “council of 
guardians”, as the rulers.* Thus the whole body of materialistic 
elements has been eliminated from history and now full rein can be 
given to the speculative steed. 

This historical method which reigned in Germany, and especiallv 
the reason why, must be explained from its connection with the 
illusion of ideologists in general, e.g., the illusions of the jurists, 
politicians (including the practical statesmen), from the dogmatic 
dreamings and distortions of these fellows; this is explained 
perfectly easily from then practical position in life, their job, 
and the division of labour. 

1 35 1 Whilst in ordinary life every shopkeeper 3 is very well able to 
distinguish between what somebody professes to be and what he 
really is, our historiography has not yet won this trivial insight. It takes 
every epoch at its word and believes that everything it says and 
imagines about itself is true. 

* [Marginal note by Marx:] Man = the “thinking human spirit”. 

3 This word is in English in the manuscript. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. I. Feuerbach 



63 



[IV] 

[1. INSTRUMENTS OF PRODUCTION 
AND FORMS OF PROPERTY] 

[...] a 1 40 1 From the first point, there follows the premise of a highly 
developed division of labour and an extensive commerce; from the 
second, the locality. In the first case the individuals must have been 
brought together, in the second they are instruments of production 
alongside the given instrument of production. 

Here, therefore, emerges the difference between natural instru- 
ments of production and those created by civilisation. The field 
(water, etc.) can be regarded as a natural instrument of production. 
In the first case, that of the natural instrument of production, 
individuals are subservient to nature; in the second, to a product of 
labour. In the first case, therefore, property (landed property) 
appears as direct natural domination, in the second, as domination 
of labour, particularly of accumulated labour, capital. The first case 
presupposes that the individuals are united by some bond: family, 
tribe, the land itself, etc.; the second, that they are independent of 
one another and are only held together by exchange. In the first 
case, what is involved is chiefly an exchange between men and nature 
in which the labour of the former is exchanged for the products of 
the latter; in the second, it is predominantly an exchange of men 
among themselves. In the first case, average human common sense is 
adequate — physical activity and mental activity are not yet separated; 
in the second, the division between physical and mental labour must 
already have been effected in practice. In the first case, the 
domination of the proprietor over the propertyless may be based on 
personal relations, on a kind of community; in the second, it must 
have taken on a material shape in a third party — money. In the first 
case, small-scale industry exists, but determined by the utilisation of 
the natural instrument of production and therefore without the 
distribution of labour among various individuals; in the second, 
industry exists only in and through the division of labour. 

1 4 1 1 Our investigation hitherto started from the instruments of 
production, and it has already shown that private property was a 
necessity for certain industrial stages. In industrie extractive 28 private 
property still coincides with labour; in small-scale industry and all 
agriculture up till now property is the necessary consequence of the 
existing instruments of production; the contradiction between the 
instrument of production and private property is only the product of 



Four pages of the manuscript are missing. — Ed. 




64 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



large-scale industry, which, moreover, must be highly developed to 
produce this contradiction. Thus only with large-scale industry does 
the abolition of private property become possible. 



[2. THE DIVISION OF MATERIAL AND MENTAL LABOUR. 

SEPARATION OF TOWN AND COUNTRY. 

THE GUILD-SYSTEM] 

The most important division of material and mental labour is the 
separation of town and country. The contradiction between town 
and country begins with the transition from barbarism to civilisation, 
from tribe to state, from locality to nation, and runs through the 
whole history of civilisation to the present day (the Anti-Corn Law 
League 29 ). 

The advent of the town implies, at the same time, the necessity of 
administration, police, taxes, etc., in short, of the municipality [des 
Gemeindewesens], and thus of politics in general. Here first became 
manifest the division of the population into two great classes, which is 
directly based on the division of labour and on the instruments of 
production. The town is in actual fact already the concentration of the 
population, of the instruments of production, of capital, of pleasures, 
of needs, while the country demonstrates just the opposite fact, 
isolation and separation. The contradiction between town and 
country can only exist within the framework of private property. It is 
the most crass expression of the subjection of the individual under the 
division of labour, under a definite activity forced upon him — a 
subjection which makes one man into a restricted town-animal, 
another into a restricted country-animal, and daily creates anew the 
conflict between their interests. Labour is here again the chief thing, 
power over individuals, and as long as this power exists, private 
property must exist. The abolition of the contradiction between town 
and country is one of the first conditions |42J of communal life, a 
condition which again depends on a mass of material premises and 
which cannot be fulfilled by the mere will, as anyone can see at the 
first glance. (These conditions have still to be set forth.) The 
separation of town and country can also be understood as the 
separation of capital and landed property, as the beginning of the 
existence and development of capital independent of landed 
property — the beginning of property having its basis only in labour 
and exchange. 

In the towns which, in the Middle Ages, did not derive ready-made 
from an earlier period but were formed anew by the serfs who had 




The German Ideology. I. Feuerbach 



65 



become free, the particular labour of each man was his only property 
apart from the small capital he brought with him, consisting almost 
solely of the most necessary tools of his craft. The competition of 
serfs constantly escaping into the town, the constant war of the 
country against the towns and thus the necessity of an organised 
municipal military force, the bond of common ownership in a 
particular kind of labour, the necessity of common buildings for the 
sale of their wares at a time when craftsmen were also traders, and 
the consequent exclusion of the unauthorised from these buildings, 
the conflict among the interests of the various crafts, the necessity of 
protecting their laboriously acquired skill, and the feudal organisa- 
tion of the whole of the country: these were the causes of the union 
of the workers of each craft in guilds. In this context we do not have 
to go further into the manifold modifications of the guild-system, 
which arise through later historical developments. The flight of the 
serfs into the towns went on without interruption right through the 
Middle Ages. These serfs, persecuted by their lords in the country, 
came separately into the towns, where they found an organised 
community, against which they were powerless and in which they 
had to subject themselves to the station assigned to them by the 
demand for their labour and the interest of their organised urban 
competitors. These workers, entering separately, were never able to 
attain to any power, since, if their labour was of the guild type which 
had to be learned, the guildmasters bent them to their will and 
organised them according to their interest; or if their labour was not 
such as had to be learned, and therefore not of the guild type, they 
were day-labourers, never managed to organise, but remained an 
unorganised rabble. The need for day-labourers in the towns created 
the rabble. 

These towns were true “unions”, 30 called forth by the direct |43| 
need of providing for the protection of property, and of multiplying 
the means of production and defence of the separate members. The 
rabble of these towns was devoid of any power, composed as it was of 
individuals strange to one another who had entered separately, and 
who stood unorganised over against an organised power, armed for 
war, and jealously watching, over them. The journeymen and 
apprentices were organised in each craft as it best suited the interest 
of the masters. The patriarchal relations existing between them 
and their masters gave the latter a double power — on the one hand 
because of the direct influence they exerted on the whole life of the 
journeymen, and on the other because, for the journeymen who 
worked with the same master, it was a real bond which held them 
together against the journeymen of other masters and separated 




66 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



them from these. And finally, the journeymen were bound to the 
existing order even by their interest in becoming masters themselves. 
While, therefore, the rabble at least carried out revolts against the 
whole municipal order, revolts which remained completely ineffec- 
tive because of its powerlessness, the journeymen never got further 
than small acts of insubordination within separate guilds, such as 
belong to the very nature of the guild-system. The great risings of 
the Middle Ages all radiated from the country, but equally remained 
totally ineffective because of the isolation and consequent crudity of 
the peasants. 31 — 

Capital in these towns was a naturally evolved capital, consisting of 
a house, the tools of the craft, and the natural, hereditary customers; 
and not being realisable, on account of the backwardness of 
intercourse and the lack of circulation, it had to be handed down from 
father to son. Unlike modern capital, which can be assessed in money 
and which may be indifferently invested in this thing or that, this 
capital was directly connected with the particular work of the owner, 
inseparable from it and to this extent estate capital. — 

In the towns, the division of labour between the [44] individual 
guilds was as yet very little developed and, in the guilds themselves, 
it did not exist at all between the individual workers. Every workman 
had to be versed in a whole round of tasks, had to be able to make 
everything that was to be made with his tools. The limited intercourse 
and the weak ties between the individual towns, the lack of population 
and the narrow needs did not allow of a more advanced division of 
labour, and therefore every man who wished to become a master had 
to be proficient in the whole of his craft. Medieval craftsmen therefore 
had an interest in their special work and in proficiency in it, which was 
capable of rising to a limited artistic sense. For this very reason, 
however, every medieval craftsman was completely absorbed in his 
work, to which he had a complacent servile relationship, and in which 
he was involved to a far greater extent than the modern worker, whose 
work is a matter of indifference to him. — 



[3. FURTHER DIVISION OF LABOUR. 
SEPARATION OF COMMERCE AND INDUSTRY. 
DIVISION OF LABOUR BETWEEN THE VARIOUS TOWNS. 
MANUFACTURE] 



The next extension of the division of labour was the separation of 
production and intercourse, the formation of a special class of 
merchants; a separation which, in the towns bequeathed by a former 




The German Ideology. I. Feuerbach 



67 



period, had been handed down (among other things with the Jews) 
and which very soon appeared in the newly formed ones. With this 
there was given the possibility of commercial communications 
transcending the immediate neighbourhood, a possibility the 
realisation of which depended on the existing means of 
communication, the state of public safety in the countryside, which 
was determined by political conditions (during the whole of the 
Middle Ages, as is well known, the merchants travelled in armed 
caravans), and on the cruder or more advanced needs (determined by 
the stage of culture attained) of the region accessible to intercourse. 

With intercourse vested in a particular class, with the extension of 
trade through the merchants beyond the immediate surroundings of 
the town, there immediately appears a reciprocal action between 
production and intercourse. The towns enter into relations with one 
another, new tools are brought from one town into the other, and the 
separation between production and intercourse soon calls forth a new 
division of production between |45| the individual towns, each of 
which is soon exploiting a predominant branch of industry. The local 
restrictions of earlier times begin gradually to be broken down. — 

It depends purely on the extension of intercourse whether the 
productive forces evolved in a locality, especially inventions, are lost 
for later development or not. As long as there exists no intercourse 
transcending the immediate neighbourhood, every invention must be 
made separately in each locality, and mere chances such as irruptions 
of barbaric peoples, even ordinary wars, are sufficient to cause a 
country with advanced productive forces and needs to have to start 
right over again from the beginning. In primitive history every 
invention had to be made daily anew and in each locality 
independently. That even with a relatively very extensive commerce, 
highly developed productive forces are not safe from complete 
destruction, is proved by the Phoenicians, whose inventions were for 
the most part lost for a long time to come through the ousting of this 
nation from commerce, its conquest by Alexander and its consequent 
decline. Likewise, for instance, glass staining in the Middle Ages. Only 
when intercourse has become world intercourse and has as its basis 
large-scale industry, when all nations are drawn into the competitive 
struggle, is the permanence of the acquired productive forces 
assured. — 

The immediate consequence of the division of labour between the 
various towns was the rise of manufactures, branches of production 
which had outgrown the guild-system. Intercourse with foreign 
nations was the historical premise for the first flourishing of 
manufactures, in Italy and later in Flanders. In other countries, 




68 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



England and France for example, manufactures were at first confined 
to the home market. Besides the premises already mentioned 
manufactures presuppose an already advanced concentration of 
population, particularly in the countryside, and of capital, which 
began to accumulate in the hands of individuals, partly in the guilds in 
spite of the guild regulations, partly among the merchants. 

1 46) The kind of labour which from the first presupposed 
machines, even of the crudest sort, soon showed itself the most 
capable of development. Weaving, earlier carried on in the country 
by the peasants as a secondary occupatign to procure their clothing, 
was the first labour to receive an impetus and a further development 
through the extension of intercourse. Weaving was the first 
and remained the principal manufacture. The rising demand for 
clothing materials, consequent on the growth of population, the 
growing accumulation and mobilisation of natural capital through 
accelerated circulation, and the demand for luxuries called forth by 
this and favoured generally by the gradual extension of inter- 
course, gave weaving a quantitative and qualitative stimulus, which 
wrenched it out of the form of production hitherto existing. 
Alongside the peasants weaving for their own use, who continued, 
and still continue, with this sort of work, there emerged a new class 
of weavers in the towns, whose fabrics were destined for the whole 
home market and usually for foreign markets too. 

Weaving, an occupation demanding in most cases little skill and 
soon splitting up into countless branches, by its whole nature resisted 
the trammels of the guild. Weaving was, therefore, carried on mostly 
in villages and market centres, without guild organisation, which 
gradually became towns, and indeed the most flourishing towns in 
each land. 

With guild-free manufacture, property relations also quickly 
changed. The first advance beyond naturally derived estate capital 
was provided by the rise of merchants, whose capital was from the 
beginning movable, capital in the modern sense as far as one can 
speak of it, given the circumstances of those times. The second 
advance came with manufacture, which again mobilised a mass of 
natural capital, and altogether increased the mass of movable capital 
as against that of natural capital. 

At the same time, manufacture became a refuge of the peasants 
from the guilds which excluded them or paid them badly, just as 
earlier the guild-towns had served the peasants as a refuge |47| from 
the landlords. — 

Simultaneously with the beginning of manufactures there was a 
period of vagabondage caused by the abolition of the feudal bodies 




The German Ideology. I. Feuerbach 



69 



of retainers, the disbanding of the armies consisting of a motley 
crowd that served the kings against their vassals, the improvement of 
agriculture, and the transformation of large strips of tillage into 
pasture land. From this alone it is clear that this vagabondage is 
strictly connected with the disintegration of the feudal system. As 
early as the thirteenth century we find isolated epochs of this kind, 
but only at the end of the fifteenth and beginning of the sixteenth 
does this vagabondage make a general and permanent appearance. 
These vagabonds, who were so numerous that, for instance, Henry 
VIII of England had 72,000 of them hanged, 32 were only prevailed 
upon to work with the greatest difficulty and through the most 
extreme necessity, and then only after long resistance. The rapid rise 
of manufactures, particularly in England, absorbed them 
gradually. — 

With the advent of manufacture the various nations entered into 
competitive relations, a commercial struggle, which was fought 
out in wars, protective duties and prohibitions, whereas earlier the 
nations, insofar as they were connected at all, had carried on an 
inoffensive exchange with each other. Trade had from now on a 
political significance. 

With the advent of manufacture the relations between worker 
and employer changed. In the guilds the patriarchal relations 
between journeyman and master continued to exist; in manufacture 
their place was taken by the monetary relations between worker and 
capitalist — relations which in the countryside and in small towns 
retained a patriarchal tinge, but in the larger, the real manufacturing 
towns, quite early lost almost all patriarchal complexion. 

Manufacture and the movement of production in general received 
an enormous impetus through the extension of intercourse which 
came with the discovery of America and the sea-route to the East 
Indies. The new products imported thence, particularly the masses of 
gold and silver which came into circulation, had totally changed the 
position of the classes towards one another, dealing a hard blow to 
feudal landed property and to the workers; the expeditions of 
adventurers, colonisation, and above all the extension of markets 
into a world market, which had now become possible and was 
daily becoming more and more a fact, called forth a new phase 1 48 1 of 
historical development, into which in general we need not here enter 
further. Through the colonisation of the newly discovered countries 
the commercial struggle of the nations against one another was given 
new fuel and accordingly greater extension and animosity. 

The expansion of commerce and manufacture accelerated the 
accumulation of movable capital, while in the guilds, which were not 




70 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



stimulated to extend their production, natural capital remained 
stationary or even declined. Commerce and manufacture created the 
big bourgeoisie; in the guilds was concentrated the petty bourgeoisie, 
which no longer was dominant in the towns as formerly, but had to 
bow to the might of the great merchants and manufacturers.* Hence 
the decline of the guilds, as soon as they came into contact with 
manufacture. 

The relations between nations in their intercourse took on two 
different forms in the epoch of which we have been speaking. At first 
the small quantity of gold and silver in circulation occasioned the ban 
on the export of these metals; and industry, made necessary by the 
need for employing the growing urban population and for the most 
part imported from abroad, could not do without privileges which 
could be granted not only, of course, against home competition, but 
chiefly against foreign. The local guild privilege was in these original 
prohibitions extended over the whole nation. Customs duties 
originated from the tributes which the feudal lords exacted from 
merchants passing through their territories as protection money 
against robbery, tributes later imposed likewise by the towns, and 
which, with the rise of the modern states, were the Treasury’s most 
obvious means of raising money. 

The appearance of American gold and silver on the European 
markets, the gradual development of industry, the rapid expansion 
of trade and the consequent rise of the non-guild bourgeoisie and 
the increasing importance of money, gave these measures another 
significance. The state, which was daily less and less able to do 
without money, now retained the ban on the export of gold and 
silver out of fiscal considerations; the bourgeois, for whom these 
quantities of money which were hurled on to the market became the 
chief object of speculative buying, were thoroughly content with this; 
privileges established earlier became a source of income for the 
government and were sold for money; in the customs legislation 
there appeared export duties which, since they only hampered 
industry, 1 49 j had a purely fiscal aim. — 

The second period began in the middle of the seventeenth century 
and lasted almost to the end of the eighteenth. Commerce and 
navigation had expanded more rapidly than manufacture, which 
played a secondary role; the colonies were becoming considerable 
consumers; and after long struggles the various nations shared out 
the opening world market among themselves. This period begins 
with the Navigation Laws 33 and colonial monopolies. The competi- 



[Marginal note by Marx:] Petty bourgeoisie — Middle class — Big bourgeoisie. 




The German Ideology. I. Feuerbach 



71 



tion of the nations among themselves was excluded as far as possible 
by tariffs, prohibitions and treaties; and in the last resort the 
competitive struggle was carried on and decided by wars (especially 
naval wars). The mightiest maritime nation, the English, retained 
preponderance in commerce and manufacture. Here, already, we 
find concentration in one country. 

Manufacture was all the time sheltered by protective duties in the 
home market, by monopolies in the colonial market, and abroad as 
much as possible by differential duties. The working-up of 
home-produced material was encouraged (wool and linen in 
England, silk in France), the export of home-produced raw material 
forbidden (wool in England), and the [working-upl of imported raw 
material neglected or suppressed (cotton in England). The natioii 
dominant in maritime trade and colonial power naturally secured for 
itself also the greatest quantitative and qualitative expansion of 
manufacture. Manufacture could not be carried on without protec- 
tion, since, if the slightest change takes place in other countries, it can 
lose its market and be ruined; under reasonably favourable 
conditions it may easily be introduced into a country, but for this 
very reason can easily be destroyed. At the same time through the 
mode in which it is carried on, particularly in the eighteenth century 
in the countryside, it is to such an extent interwoven with the 
conditions of life of a great mass of individuals, that no country dare 
jeopardise their existence by permitting free competition. Conse- 
quently, insofar as manufacture manages to export, it depends 
entirely on the extension or restriction of commerce, and exercises a 
relatively very small reaction (on the latter]. Hence its secondary 
[role] and the influence of [the merchants] in the eighteenth century. 

1 50] It was the merchants and especially the shipowners who more 
than anybody else Dressed for state protection and monopolies; the 
manufacturers also demanded and indeed received protection, but 
all the time were inferior in political importance to the merchants. 
The commercial towns, particularlv the maritime towns, became to 
some extent civilised and acquired the outlook of the big bourgeoisie, 
but in the factory towns an extreme petty-bourgeois outlook 
persisted. Cf. Aikin, etc. a The eighteenth century was the century of 
trade. Pinto says this expressly: “Le commerce fait la marotte du siecle ,, ; b 



a John Aikin, A Description of the Country from Thirty to Forty Miles round 
Man Chester. — Ed. 

b “Commerce is the rage of the century.” Isaac Pinto, “Lettre sur la jalousie du 
commerce” (published in Pinto’s book Traite de la circulation et du credit). — Ed. 




72 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



and: “ depuis quelque temps il n’est plus question que de commerce, de 
navigation et de marine” 3 

The movement of capital, although considerably accelerated, still 
remained, however, relatively slow. The splitting-up of the world 
market into separate parts, each of which was exploited by a 
particular nation, the prevention of competition between the 
different nations, the clumsiness of production and the fact that 
finance was only evolving from its early stages, greatly impeded 
circulation. The consequence of this was a haggling, mean and 
niggardly spirit which still clung to all merchants and to the whole 
mode of carrying on trade. Compared with the manufacturers, and 
above all with the craftsmen, they were certainly big bourgeois; 
compared with the merchants and industrialists of the next period 
they remain petty bourgeois. Cf. Adam Smith . b — 

This period is also characterised by the cessation of the bans on the 
export of gold and silver and the beginning of money trade, banks, 
national debts, paper money, speculation in stocks and shares, 
stockjobbing in all articles and the development of finance in 
general. Again capital lost a great part of the natural character which 
had still clung to it. 



[4. MOST EXTENSIVE DIVISION OF LABOUR. 

LARGE-SCALE INDUSTRY] 

The concentration of trade and manufacture in one country, 
England, developing irresistibly in the seventeenth century, gradual- 
ly created for this country a relative world market, and thus a 
demand for the manufactured products of this country which could 
no longer be met by the industrial productive forces hitherto 
existing. This demand, outgrowing the productive forces, was the 
motive power which, by producing large-scale industry — the 
application of elemental forces to industrial ends, machinery and the 
most extensive division of labour — called into existence the third 1 5 1 1 
period of private property since the Middle Ages. There already 
existed in England the other preconditions of this new phase: 
freedom of competition inside the nation, the development of 
theoretical mechanics, etc. (indeed, mechanics, perfected by Newton, 
was altogether the most popular science in France and England in the 
eighteenth century). (Free competition inside the nation itself had 



a “For some time now people have been talking only about commerce, navigation 
and the navy” (ibid.). — Ed. 

b Adam Smith, An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. I. Feuerbach 



73 



everywhere to be won by a revolution — 1640 and 1688 in England, 
1789 in France.) 

Competition soon compelled every country that wished to retain 
its historical role to protect its manufactures by renewed customs 
regulations (the old duties were no longer any good against 
large-scale industry) and soon after to introduce large-scale industry 
under protective duties. In spite of these protective measures 
large-scale industry universalised competition (it is practical free 
trade; the protective duty is only a palliative, a measure of defence 
within free trade), established means of communication and the 
modern world market, subordinated trade to itself, transformed all 
capital into industrial capital, and thus produced the rapid 
circulation (development of the financial system) and the centralisa- 
tion of capital. By universal competition it forced all individuals to 
strain their energy to the utmost. It destroyed as far as possible 
ideology, religion, morality, etc., and, where it could not do this, 
made them into a palpable lie. It produced world history for the first 
time, insofar as it made all civilised nations and every individual 
member of them dependent for the satisfaction of their wants on the 
whole world, thus destroying the former natural exclusiveness of 
separate nations. It made natural science subservient to capital and 
took from the division of labour the last semblance of its natural 
character. It altogether destroyed the natural character, as far as this 
is possible with regard to labour, and resolved all natural relations 
into money relations. In the place of naturally grown towns 
it created the modern, large industrial cities which have sprung up 
overnight. It destroyed the crafts and all earlier stages of industry 
wherever it gained mastery. It completed the victory of the town 
over the country. Its [basis] is the automatic system. It produced 
a mass of productive forces, for which private property became 
just as much a fetter [52 j as the guild had been for manufacture and 
the small, rural workshop for the developing handicrafts. These 
productive forces receive under the system of private property a 
one-sided development only, and for the majority they become 
destructive forces; moreover, a great many of these forces can find 
no application at all within the system of private property. Generally 
speaking, large-scale industry created everywhere the same relations 
between the classes of society, and thus destroyed the peculiar 
features of the various nationalities. And finally, while the 
bourgeoisie of each nation still retained separate national interests, 
large-scale industry created a class which in all nations has the same 
interest and for which nationality is already dead; a class which is 
really rid of all the old world and at the same time stands pitted 




74 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



against it. For the worker it makes not only his relation to the 
capitalist, but labour itself, unbearable. 

It is evident that large-scale industry does not reach the same level 
of development in all districts of a country. This does not, however, 
retard the class movement of the proletariat, because the proletarians 
created by large-scale industry assume leadership of this movement 
and carry the whole mass along with them, and because the workers 
excluded from large-scale industry are placed by it in a still worse 
situation than the workers in large-scale industry itself. The countries 
in which large-scale industry is developed act in a similar manner 
upon the more or less non-industrial countries, insofar as the latter 
are swept by world intercourse into the universal competitive struggle. 

* * * 

These different forms [of production] are just so many forms of the 
organisation of labour, and hence of property. In each period a 
unification of the existing productive forces takes place, insofar as this 
has been rendered necessary by needs. 



[5. THE CONTRADICTION BETWEEN THE PRODUCTIVE FORCES 
AND THE FORM OF INTERCOURSE AS THE BASIS 
OF SOCIAL REVOLUTION] 

The contradiction between the productive forces and the form of 
intercourse, which, as we saw, has occurred several times in past 
history, without, however, endangering its basis, necessarily on each 
occasion burst out in a revolution, taking on at the same time various 
subsidiary forms, such as all-embracing collisions, collisions of 
various classes, contradictions of consciousness, battle of ideas, 
political struggle, etc. From a narrow point of view one may isolate 
one of these subsidiary forms and consider it as the basis of these 
revolutions; and this is all the more easy as the individuals who 
started the revolutions had illusions about their own activity 
according to their degree of culture and the stage of historical 
development. 



Thus all collisions in history have their origin, according to our 
view, in the contradiction between the productive forces and the 
form 1 53 1 of intercourse. Incidentally, to lead to collisions in a 




The German Ideology. I. Feuerbach 



75 



country, this contradiction need not necessarily have reached its 
extreme limit in that particular country. The competition with 
industrially more advanced countries, brought about by the expan- 
sion of international intercourse, is sufficient to produce a similar 
contradiction in countries with a less advanced industry (e.g., the 
latent proletariat in Germany brought into more prominence by the 
competition of English industry). 



[6. COMPETITION OK INDIVIDUALS 
AND THE FORMATION OF CLASSES. 

CONTRADICTION BETWEEN INDIVIDUALS AND THEIR CONDITIONS 
OF LIFE. THE ILLUSORY COMMUNITY 
OF INDIVIDUALS IN BOURGEOIS SOCIETY AND THE REAL UNION 
OF INDIVIDUALS UNDER COMMUNISM. 

SUBORDINATION OF THE SOCIAL CONDITIONS OF LIFE 
TO THE POWER OF THE UNITED INDIVIDUALS] 

Competition separates individuals from one another, not only the 
bourgeois but still more the workers, in spite of the fact that it brings 
them together. Hence it is a long time before these individuals can 
unite, apart from the fact that for the purpose of this union — if it is 
not to be merely local — the necessary means, the big industrial cities 
and cheap and quick communications, have first to be produced by 
large-scale industry. Hence every organised power standing over 
against these isolated individuals, who live in conditions daily 
reproducing this isolation, can only be overcome after long struggles. 
To demand the opposite would be tantamount to demanding that 
competition should not exist in this definite epoch of history, or that 
the individuals should banish from their minds conditions over 
which in their isolation they have no control. 



The building of houses. With savages each family has as a matter 
of course its own cave or hut like the separate family tent of the 
nomads. This separate domestic economy is made only the more 
necessary by the further development of private property. With the 
agricultural peoples a communal domestic economy is just as 
impossible as a communal cultivation of the soil. A great advance was 
the building of towns. In all previous periods, however, the abolition 
[ Aufhebung\ a of individual economy, which is inseparable from the 

a Aufhebung — a term used by Hegel to denote the negation of an old form while 
preserving its positive content in the new, which supersedes it. — Ed. 




76 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



abolition of private property, was impossible for the simple reason 
that the material conditions required were not present. The setting 
up of a communal domestic economy presupposes the development 
of machinery, the use of natural forces and of many other productive 
forces — e.g., of water-supplies, 1 54 1 gas-lighting, steam-heating, etc., 
the supersession [ Aufhebung ] of town and country. Without these 
conditions a communal economy would not in itself form a new 
productive force; it would lack material basis and rest on a purely 
theoretical foundation, in other words, it would be a mere freak and 
would amount to nothing more than a monastic economy. — What was 
possible can be seen in the towns brought into existence by 
concentration and in the construction of communal buildings for 
various definite purposes {prisons, barracks, etc.). That the 
supersession of individual economy is inseparable from the 
supersession of the family is self-evident. 



(The statement which frequently occurs with Saint Sancho that 
each man is all that he is through the state 3 is fundamentally the 
same as the statement that the bourgeois is only a specimen of the 
bourgeois species; a statement which presupposes that the bourgeois 
class existed before the individuals constituting it.*) 

In the Middle Ages the citizens in each town were compelled to 
unite against the landed nobility to defend themselves. The extension 
of trade, the establishment of communications, led separate towns to 
establish contacts with other towns, which had asserted the same 
interests in the struggle with the same antagonist. Out of the 
many local communities of citizens in the various towns there arose 
only gradually the middle class. The conditions of life of the individual 
citizens became — on account of their contradiction to the existing 
relations and of the mode of labour determined by this — conditions 
which were common to them all and independent of each individual. 
The citizens created these conditions insofar as they had torn 
themselves free from feudal ties, and were in their turn created by 
them insofar as they were determined by their antagonism to the 
feudal system which they found in existence. With the setting up of 
intercommunications between the individual towns, these common 
conditions developed into class conditions. The same conditions, the 
same contradiction, the same interests were bound to call forth on the 



* [Marginal note by Marx:] With the philosophers pre-existence of the class. 



Max Stirner, Der Einzige und sein Eigenthum. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. I. Feuerbach 



77 



whole similar customs everywhere. The bourgeoisie itself develops 
only gradually together with its conditions, splits according to the 
division of labour into various sections and finally absorbs all 
propertied classes it finds in existence * (while it develops the majority 
of the earlier propertyless and a part of the hitherto propertied classes 
into a new class, the proletariat) in the measure to which all property 
found in existence is transformed into industrial or commercial 
capital. 

The separate individuals form a class only insofar as [551 they have 
to carry on a common battle against another class; in other respects 
they are on hostile terms with each other as competitors. On the 
other hand, the class in its turn assumes an independent existence as 
against the individuals, so that the latter find their conditions of 
life predetermined, and have their position in life and hence 
their personal development assigned to them by their class, thus 
becoming subsumed under it. This is the same phenomenon as the 
subjection of the separate individuals to the division of labour and 
can only be removed by the abolition of private property and of 
labour* itself. We have already indicated several times that this 
subsuming of individuals under the class brings with it their 
subjection to all kinds of ideas, etc. 

If this development of individuals, which proceeds within the com- 
mon conditions of existence of estates and classes, historically follo- 
wing one another, and the general conceptions thereby forced upon 
them — if this development is considered from a philosophical point of 
view, it is certainly verv easy to imagine that in these individuals the 
species, or man, has evolved, or that they evolved man — and in this 
way one can give history some hard clouts on the ear. One can then 
conceive these various estates and classes to be specific terms of the 
general expression, subordinate varieties of the species, or evolu- 
tionary phases of man. 

This subsuming of individuals under definite classes cannot be 
abolished until a class has evolved which has no longer any particular 
class interest to assert against a ruling ciass. 



The transformation, through the division of labour, of personal 
powers (relations) into material powers, cannot be dispelled by 

* [Marginal note by Marx:] To begin with, it absorbs the branches of labour 
directly belonging to the state and then all — [more or less] ideological professions. 



a Regarding the meaning of “abolition of labour” f Aufhebung der Arbeit) see this 
volume, pp. 52-53, 80, 85-89. — Ed. 




78 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



dismissing the general idea of it from one’s mind, but can only be 
abolished by the individuals again subjecting these material powers 
to themselves and abolishing the division of labour.* This is not 
possible without the community. Only within the community has 
each individual 1 56 1 the means of cultivating his gifts in all directions; 
hence personal freedom becomes possible only within the communi- 
ty. In the previous substitutes for the community, in the state, 
etc., personal freedom has existed only for the individuals who 
developed under the conditions of the ruling class, and only inso- 
far as they were individuals of this class. The illusory commu- 
nity in which individuals have up till now combined always took 
on an independent existence in relation to them, and since it 
was the combination of one class over against another, it was at 
the same time for the oppressed class not only a completely illu- 
sory community, but a new fetter as well. In the real community 
the individuals obtain their freedom in and through their asso- 
ciation. 

Individuals have always proceeded from themselves, but of course 
from themselves within their given historical conditions and 
relations, not from the “pure” individual in the sense of the ideolo- 
gists. But in the course of historical development, and precisely 
through the fact that within the division of labour social relations 
inevitably take on an independent existence, there appears a cleavage 
in the life of each individual, insofar as it is personal and insofar 
as it is determined by some branch of labour and the conditions 
pertaining to it. (We do not mean it to be understood from this that, 
for example, the rentier, the capitalist, etc., cease to be persons; but 
their personality is conditioned and determined by quite definite 
class relations, and the cleavage appears only in their opposition 
to another class and, for themselves, only when they go bankrupt.) In 
the estate (and even more in the tribe) this is as yet concealed: for 
instance, a nobleman always remains a nobleman, a commoner 
always a commoner, a quality inseparable from his individuality 
irrespective of his other relations. The difference between the private 
individual and the class individual, the accidental nature of the 
conditions of life for the individual, appears only with the emergence 
of the class, which is itself a product of the bourgeoisie. This accidental 
character as such is only engendered and developed |57| by 
competition and the struggle of individuals among themselves. Thus, 
in imagination, individuals seem freer under the dominance of the 



* [Marginal note by Engels:] (Feuerbach: being and essence). [Cf. this volume, 
pp. 58-59.]— Ed. 




The German Ideology. I. Feuerbach 



79 



bourgeoisie than before, because their conditions of life seem 
accidental; in reality, of course, they are less free, because they are to a 
greater extent governed by material forces. The difference from the 
estate comes out particularly in the antagonism between the 
bourgeoisie and the proletariat. When the estate of the urban 
burghers, the corporations, etc., emerged in opposition to the landed 
nobility, their condition of existence — movable property and craft 
labour, which had already existed latently before their separation 
from the feudal institutions — appeared as something positive, which 
was asserted against feudal landed property, and, therefore, in its own 
way at first took on a feudal form. Certainly the fugitive serfs treated 
their previous servitude as something extraneous to their personality. 
But here they only were doing what every class that is freeing itself 
from a fetter does; and they did not free themselves as a class but 
individually. Moreover, they did not break loose from the system of 
estates, but only formed a new estate, retaining their previous 
mode of labour even in their new situation, and developing it further 
by freeing it from its earlier fetters, which no longer corresponded to 
the development alreadv attained. 

For the proletarians, on the other hand, the condition of their 
life, labour, and with it all the conditions of existence of modern 
society, have become something extraneous, something over 
which they, as separate individuals, have no control, and over 
which no social organisation can give them control. The contra- 
diction between the individuality of each separate proletarian and 
labour, the condition of life forced upon him, becomes evident to 
him, for he is sacrificed from youth onwards and, within his own 
class, has no chance of arriving at the conditions which would place 
him in the other class. — 

1 58 1 NB. It must not be forgotten that the serfs very need of 
existing and the impossibility of a large-scale economy involved the 
distribution of allotments 3 among the serfs and very soon reduced 
the services of the serfs to their lord to an average of payments in 
kind and labour-services. This made it possible for the serf to 
accumulate movable property and hence facilitated his escape from 
his lord and gave him the prospect of making his way as a townsman; 
it also created gradations among the serfs, so that the runaway serfs 
were already half burghers. It is likewise obvious that the serfs who 
were versed in a craft had the best chance of acquiring movable 
property. — 



3 This word is in English in the manuscript. — Ed. 




80 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



Thus, while the fugitive serfs only wished to have full scope to 
develop and assert those conditions of existence which were already 
there, and hence, in the end, only arrived at free labour, the 
proletarians, if they are to assert themselves as individuals, have to 
abolish the hitherto prevailing condition of their existence (which 
has, moreover, been that of all society up to then), namely, labour. 
Thus they find themselves directly opposed to the form in which, 
hitherto, the individuals, of which society consists, have given 
themselves collective expression, that is, the state; in order, 
therefore, to assert themselves as individuals, they must overthrow 
the state. 



It follows from all we have been saying up till now that* the 
communal relation into which the individuals of a class entered, 
and which was determined by their common interests as against a 
third party, was always a community to which these individuals 
belonged only as average individuals, only insofar as they lived 
within the conditions of existence of their class — a relation in 
which they participated not as individuals but as members of a class. 
With the community of revolutionary proletarians, on the other 
hand, who take their conditions 1 59 1 of existence and those of all 
members of society under their control, it is just the reverse; it is as 
individuals that the individuals participate in it. For it is the 
association of individuals (assuming the advanced stage of modern 
productive forces, of course) which puts the conditions of the free 
development and movement of individuals under their con- 
trol — conditions which were previously left to chance and had 
acquired an independent existence over against the separate 
individuals precisely because of their separation as individuals and 
because their inevitable association, which was determined by the 
division of labour, had, as a result of their separation, become for 
them an alien bond. Up till now association (by no means an arbitrary 
one, such as is expounded for example in the Contrat social* but a 
necessary one) was simply an agreement about those conditions, 
within which the individuals were free to en joy the freaks of fortune 
(compare, e.g., the formation of the North American state and the 
South American republics). This right to the undisturbed enjoyment, 

* [The following is crossed out in the manuscript:] the individuals who freed 
themselves in any historical epoch merely developed further the conditions of 
existence which were already present and which they found in existence. 

jean Jacques Rousseau, Du Contrat social. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. I. Feuerbach 



81 



within certain conditions, of fortuity and chance has up till now been 
called personal freedom. — These conditions of existence are, of 
course, only the productive forces and forms of intercourse at any 
particular time. 



Communism differs from all previous movements in that it 
overturns the basis of all earlier relations of production and 
intercourse, and for the first time consciously treats all naturally 
evolved premises as the creations of hitherto existing men, strips 
them of their natural character and subjugates them to the power of 
the united individuals. Its organisation is, therefore, essentially 
economic, the material production of the conditions of this unity; it 
turns existing conditions into conditions of unity. The reality which 
communism creates is precisely the true basis for rendering it 
impossible that anything should exist independently of individuals, 
insofar as reality is nevertheless only a product of the preceding 
intercourse of individuals. Thus the Communists in practice treat the 
conditions created up to now by production and intercourse as 
inorganic conditions, without, however, imagining that it was the 
plan or the destiny of previous generations to give them material, 
and without believing that these conditions were inorganic for the 
individuals creating them. 



[7. CONTRADICTION BETWEEN INDIVIDUALS 
AND THEIR CONDITIONS OF LIFE AS CONTRADICTION 
BETWEEN THE PRODUCTIVE FORCES AND THE FORM 
OF INTERCOURSE. DEVELOPMENT OF THE PRODUCTIVE FORCES 
AND THE CHANGING FORMS OF INTERCOURSE] 

[60] The difference between the individual as a person and what- 
ever is extraneous to him is not a conceptual difference but a histo- 
rical fact. This distinction has a different significance at different 
times — e.g., the estate as someting extraneous to the individual in the 
eighteenth century, and so too, more or less, the family. It is not a 
distinction that we have to make for each age, but one which each 
age itself makes from among the different elements which it finds in 
existence, and indeed not according to any idea, but compelled by 
material collisions in life. 

What appears accidental to a later age as opposed to an earlier — 
and this applies also to the elements handed down by an earlier 
age — is a form of intercourse which corresponded to a definite 




82 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



stage of development of the productive forces. The relation of the 
productive forces to the form of intercourse is the relation of the 
form of intercourse to the occupation or activity of the indi- 
viduals. (The fundamental form of this activity is, of course, 
material, on which depend all other forms — mental, political, 
religious, etc. The different forms of material life are, of course, in 
every case dependent on the needs which are already developed, and 
the production, as well as the satisfaction, of these needs is an 
historical process, which is not found in the case of a sheep or a dog 
(Stirner’s refractory principal argument 3 adversus hominem), al- 
though sheep and dogs in their present form certainly, but in spite of 
themselves, are products of an historical process). The conditions 
under which individual:* have intercourse with each other, so long as 
this contradiction is absent, are conditions appertaining to their 
individuality, in no way external to them; conditions under which 
alone these definite individuals, living under definite relations, 
can produce their material life and what is connected with it, are thus 
the conditions of their self-activity and are produced by this 
self-activity.* The definite condition under which they produce thus 
corresponds, as long as (61 J the contradiction has not yet appeared, 
to the reality of their conditioned nature, their one-sided existence, 
the one-sidedness of which only becomes evident when the 
contradiction enters on the scene and thus exists solely for those 
who live later. Then this condition appears as an accidental fetter, 
and the consciousness that it is a fetter is imputed to the earlier age 
as well. 

These various conditions, which appear first as conditions of 
self-activity, later as fetters upon it, form in the whole development of 
history a coherent series of forms of intercourse, the coherence of 
which consists in this: an earlier form of intercourse, which has 
become a fetter, is replaced by a new- one corresponding to the more 
developed productive forces and, hence, to the advanced mode of 
the self-activity of individuals — a form which in its turn becomes a 
fetter and is then replaced by another. Since these conditions 
correspond at every stage to the simultaneous development of the 
productive forces, their history is at the same time the history of the 
evolving productiv e forces taken over by each new generation, and is 
therefore the history of the development of the forces of the 
individuals themselves. 

* [Marginal note by Marx:] Production of the form of intercourse itself. 



a Cf. Max Stirner. “Recensenten Stirners”, and also this volume, pp. 95-96. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. I. Feuerbach 



83 



Since this development takes place spontaneously, i.e., is not 
subordinated to a general plan of freely combined individuals, it 
proceeds from various localities, tribes, nations, branches of labour, 
etc., each of which to start with develops independently of the others 
and only gradually enters into relation with the others. Furthermore, 
this development proceeds only very slowly; the various stages and 
interests are never completely overcome, but only subordinated to 
the prevailing interest and trail along beside the latter for centuries 
afterwards. It follows from this that even within a nation the 
individuals, even apart from their pecuniary circumstances, have 
quite diverse developments, and that an earlier interest, the peculiar 
form of intercourse of which has already been ousted by that 
belonging to a later interest, remains for a long time afterwards in 
possession of a traditional power in the illusory community (state, 
law), which has won an existence independent of the individuals; a 
power which in the last resort can only be broken by a revolution. 
This explains why, with reference to individual points [62] which 
allow of a more general summing-up, consciousness can sometimes 
appear further advanced than the contemporary empirical condi- 
tions, so that in the struggles of a later epoch one can refer to earlier 
theoreticians as authorities. 

On the other hand, in countries like North America, which start 
from scratch in an already advanced historical epoch, the develop- 
ment proceeds very rapidly. Such countries have no other natural 
premises than the individuals who have settled there and were led to 
do so because the forms of intercourse of the old countries did not 
correspond to their requirements. Thus they begin with the most 
advanced individuals of the old countries, and, therefore, with the 
correspondingly most advanced form of intercourse, even before 
this form of intercourse has been able to establish itself in the old 
countries. This is the case with all colonies, insofar as they are not 
mere military or trading stations. Carthage, the Greek colonies, and 
Iceland in the eleventh and twelfth centuries, provide examples of 
this. A similar relationship issues from conquest, when a form of 
intercourse which has evolved on another soil is brought over 
complete to the conquered country; whereas in its home it was still 
encumbered with interests and relations left over from earlier 
periods, here it can and must be established completely and without 
hindrance, if only to assure the conquerors’ lasting power. (England 
and Naples after the Norman conquest, 34 when they received the 
most perfect form of feudal organisation.) 




84 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



[8. THE ROLE OF VIOLENCE (CONQUEST) IN HISTORY] 

This whole conception of history appears to be contradicted by 
the fact of conquest. Up till now violence, war, pillage, murder and 
robbery, etc., have been accepted as the driving force of history. 
Here we must limit ourselves to the chief points and take, therefore, 
only the most striking example — the destruction of an old civilisation 
by a barbarous people and the resulting formation of an entirely new 
organisation of society. (Rome and the barbarians; feudalism and 
Gaul; the Byzantine Empire and the Turks.) 

163] With the conquering barbarian people war itself is still, as 
indicated above, 3 a regular form of intercourse, which is the more 
eagerly exploited as the increase in population together with the 
traditional and, for it, the only possible crude mode of production 
gives rise to the need for new means of production. In Italy, on the 
other hand, the concentration of landed property (caused not only 
by buying-up and indebtedness but also by inheritance, since loose 
living being rife and marriage rare, the old families gradually died 
out and their possessions fell into the hands of a few) and its 
conversion into grazing-land (caused not only by the usual economic 
factors still operative today but by the importation of plundered and 
tribute corn and the resultant lack of demand for Italian corn) 
brought about the almost total disappearance of the free population; 
the slaves died out again and again, and had constantly to be 
replaced by new ones. Slavery remained the basis of the entire 
production process. The plebeians, midway between freemen and 
slaves, never succeeded in becoming more than a proletarian rabble. 
Rome indeed never became more than a city; its connection with the 
provinces was almost exclusively political and could, therefore, easily 
be broken again by political events. 



Nothing is more common than the notion that in history up till 
now it has only been a question of taking. The barbarians take the 
Roman Empire, and this fact of taking is made to explain the 
transition from the old world to the feudal system. In this taking by 
barbarians, however, the question is whether the nation which is 
conquered has evolved industrial productive forces, as is the case 
with modern peoples, or whether its productive forces are based for 



3 Probably a reference to one of the missing pages of the manuscript (see this 
volume, p. 63). A similar idea is expressed in the clean copy; see this volume, 
p. 34.— Ed. 




The German Ideology. I. Feuerbach 



85 



the most part merely on their concentration and on the community. 
Taking is further determined by the object taken. A banker’s 
fortune, consisting of paper, cannot be taken at all without the 
taker’s submitting to the conditions of production and intercourse of 
the country taken. Similarly the total industrial capital of a modern 
industrial country. And finally, everywhere there is very soon an end 
to taking, and when there is nothing more to take, you have to set 
about producing. From this necessity of producing, which very soon 
asserts itself, it follows J64| that the form of community adopted by 
the settling conquerors must correspond to the stage of development 
of the productive forces they find in existence; or, if this is not the 
case from the start, it must change according to the productive 
forces. This, too, explains the fact, which people profess to have 
noticed everywhere in the period following the migration of the 
peoples, namely that the servant was master, and that the conquerors 
very soon took over language, culture and manners from the 
conquered. 

The feudal system was by no means brought complete from 
Germany, but had its origin, as far as the conquerors were 
concerned, in the martial organisation of the army during the actual 
conquest, and this evolved only after the conquest into the feudal 
system proper through the action of the productive forces found in 
the conquered countries. To what an extent this form was 
determined by the productive forces is shown by the abortive 
attempts to realise other forms derived from reminiscences of 
ancient Rome (Charlemagne, etc.). 

To be continued. — 



[9. CONTRADICTION BETWEEN THE PRODUCTIVE FORCES 
AND THE FORM OF INTERCOURSE UNDER THE CONDITIONS 
OF LARGE-SCALE INDUSTRY AND FREE COMPETITION. 

CONTRADICTION BETWEEN LABOUR AND CAPITAL] 

In large-scale industry and competition the whole mass of 
conditions of existence, limitations, biases of individuals, are fused 
together into the two simplest forms: private property and labour. 
With money every form of intercourse, and intercourse itself, 
becomes fortuitous for the individuals. Thus money implies that all 
intercourse up till now was only intercourse of individuals under 
particular conditions, not of individuals as individuals. These 
conditions are reduced to two: accumulated labour or private 




86 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



property, and actual labour. If both or one of these ceases, then 
intercourse comes to a standstill. The modern economists themselves, 
e.g., Sismondi, Cherbuliez, etc., oppose association des individus 
to association des capitaux . a On the other hand, the individuals 
themselves are entirely subordinated to the division of labour and 
hence are brought into the most complete dependence on one 
another. Private property, insofar as within labour it confronts labou r, 
evolves out of the necessity of accumulation, and is in the beginning 
still mainly a communal form, but in its further development it 
approaches more and more the modern form of private property. 
The division of labour implies from the outset the division of the 
conditionsoi labour, of tools and materials, and thus the fragmentation 
of accumulated capital among different owners, and thus, also, the 
fragmentation between capital and labour, and the different forms of 
property itself. The more the division of labour develops [65] and 
accumulation grows, the further fragmentation develops. Labour 
itself can only exist on the premise of this fragmentation. 



(Personal energy of the individuals of various nations — Germans 
and Americans — energy even as a result of miscegenation — hence 
the cretinism of the Germans; in France, England, etc,, foreign 
peoples transplanted to an already developed soil, in America to an 
entirely new soil; in Germany the indigenous population quietly 
stayed where it was.) 



Thus two facts are here revealed.* First the productive forces 
appear as a world for themselves, quite independent of and divorced 
from the individuals, alongside the individuals; the reason for this is 
that the individuals, whose forces they are, exist split up and in 
opposition to one another, whilst, on the other hand, these forces are 
only real forces in the intercourse and association of these 
individuals. Thus, on the one hand, we have a totality of productive 
forces, which have, as it were, taken on a material form and are for 
the individuals themselves no longer the forces of the individuals but 
of private property, and hence of the individuals only insofar as they 
are owners of private property. Never, in any earlier period, have 
the productive forces taken on a form so indifferent to the 

* [Marginal note by Engels:] Sismondi. 



Antoine Elvisee Cherbuliez, Riche ou Pauvre. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. I. Feuerbach 



87 



intercourse of individuals as individuals, because their intercourse 
itself was still a restricted one. On the other hand, standing against 
these productive forces, we have the majority of the individuals from 
whom these forces have been wrested away, and who, robbed thus of 
all real life-content, have become abstract individuals, who are, 
however, by this verv fact put into a position to enter into relation 
with one another as individuals. 

Labour, the only connection which still links them with the 
productive forces and with their own existence, has lost all semblance 
of self-activity and only sustains their 1 66 1 life by stunting it. While in 
the earlier periods self-activity and the production of material life 
were separated since they devolved on different persons, and while, 
on account of the narrowness of the individuals themselves, the 
production of material life was considered a subordinate mode of 
self-activity, they now diverge to such an extent that material life 
appears as the end, and what produces this material life, labour 
(which is now the only possible but, as we see, negative form of 
self-activity), as the means. 



1 10. THE NECESSITY, PRECONDITIONS AND CONSEQUENCES 
OF THE ABOLITION OF PRIVATE PROPERTY] 

Thus things have now come to such a pass that the individuals 
must appropriate the existing totality of productive forces, not only 
to achieve self-activity, but, also, merely to safeguard their very 
existence. 

This appropriation is first determined by the object to be 
appropriated, the productive forces, which have been developed to a 
totality and which only exist within a universal intercourse. Even 
from this aspect alone, therefore, this appropriation must have a 
universal character corresponding to the productive forces and the 
intercourse. The appropriation of these forces is itself nothing more 
than the development of the individual capacities corresponding to 
the material instruments of production. The appropriation of a 
totality of instruments of production is, for this very reason, the 
development of a totality of capacities in the individuals themselves. 

This appropriation is further determined by the persons appro- 
priating. Only the proletarians of the present day, who are complete- 
ly shut off from all self-activity, are in a position to achieve a com- 
plete and no longer restricted self-activity, which consists in the ap- 
propriation of a totality of productive forces and in the development 
of a totality of capacities entailed by this. All earlier revolutionary 



5 — 2086 




88 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



appropriations were restricted; individuals, whose self -activity was 
restricted by a crude instrument of production and a limited 
intercourse, appropriated this crude instrument |67| of production, 
and hence merely achieved a new state of limitation. Their 
instrument of production became their property, but they them- 
selves remained subordinate to the division of labour and their own 
instrument of production. In all appropriations up to now, a mass of 
individuals remained subservient to a single instrument of produc- 
tion; in the appropriation by the proletarians, a mass of instruments 
of production must be made subject to each individual, and property 
to all. Modern universal intercourse cannot be controlled by 
individuals, unless it is controlled by all. 

This appropriation is further determined by the manner in which 
it must be effected. It can only be effected through a union, which by 
the character of the proletariat itself can again only be a universal 
one, and through a revolution, in which, on the one hand, the power 
of the earlier mode of production and intercourse and social 
organisation is overthrown, and, on the other hand, there develops 
the universal character and the energy of the proletariat, which are 
required to accomplish the appropriation, and the proletariat 
moreover rids itself of everything that still clings to it from its 
previous position in society. 

Only at this stage does self-activity coincide with material life, 
which corresponds to the development of individuals into complete 
individuals and the casting-off of all natural limitations. The 
transformation of labour into self-activity corresponds to the 
transformation of the previously limited intercourse into the 
intercourse of individuals as such. With the appropriation of the 
total productive forces by the united individuals, private property 
comes to an end. Whilst previously in history a particular condition 
always appeared as accidental, now the isolation of individuals and 
each person’s particular way of gaining his livelihood have them- 
selves become accidental. 

The individuals, who are no longer 1 68 1 subject to the division of 
labour, have been conceived by the philosophers as an ideal, under 
the name “man”, and the whole process which we have outlined has 
been regarded by them as the evolutionary process of “man”, so that 
at every historical stage “man” was substituted for the individuals 
existing hitherto and shown as the motive force of history. The 
whole process was thus conceived as a process of the self-estrange- 
ment [ Selbstentfremdungsprozess ] of “man”,* and this was essentially 



[Marginal note by Marx:] Self-estrangement. 




The German Ideology. I. Feuerbach 



89 



due to the fact that the average individual of the later stage was al- 
ways foisted on to the earlier stage, and the consciousness of a later 
age on to the individuals of an earlier. Through this inversion, which 
from the first disregards the actual conditions, it was possible to 
transform the whole of history into an evolutionary process of con- 
sciousness. 

* * * 

Civil society embraces the whole material intercourse of individu- 
als within a definite stage of the development of productive forces. It 
embraces the whole commercial and industrial life of a given stage 
and, insofar, transcends the state and the nation, though, on the 
other hand again, it must assert itself in its external relations as 
nationality and internally must organise itself as state. The term 
“civil society” 35 emerged in the eighteenth century, when property 
relations had already extricated themselves from the ancient and 
medieval community. Civil society as such only develops with the 
bourgeoisie; the social organisation evolving directly out of produc- 
tion and intercourse, which in all ages forms the basis of the state and 
of the rest of the idealistic 3 superstructure, has, however, always been 
designated by the same name. 



[11.] THE RELATION OF STATE AND LAW TO PROPERTY 

The first form of property, in the ancient world as in the Middle 
Ages, is tribal property, determined with the Romans chiefly by war, 
with the [69] Germans by the rearing of cattle. In the case of the 
ancient peoples, since several tribes live together in one city, 
tribal property appears as state property, and the right of the 
individual to it as mere “possession” which, however, like tribal 
property as a whole, is confined to landed property only. Real 
private property began with the ancients, as with modern nations, 
with movable property. (Slavery and community) ( dominium ex jure 
Quiriturn h ). — In the case of the nations which grew out of the Middle 
Ages, tribal property evolved through various stages — feudal landed 
property, corporative movable property, capital invested in man- 
ufacture — to modern capital, determined by large-scale industry 
and universal competition, i.e., pure private property, which has cast 



3 I. e., ideal, ideological. — Ed. 

b Ownership in accordance with the law applying to full Roman citizens. — Ed. 




90 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



off all semblance of a communal institution and has shut out the state 
from any influence on the development of property. To this modern 
private property corresponds the modern state, which, purchased 
gradually by the owners of property by means of taxation, has fallen 
entirely into their hands through the national debt, and its existence 
has become wholly dependent on the commercial credit which the 
owners of property, the bourgeois, extend to it, as reflected in the 
rise and fall of government securities on the stock exchange. By the 
mere fact that it is a class and no longer an estate, the bourgeoisie 
is forced to organise itself no longer locally, but nationally, and 
to give a general form to its average interests. Through the 
emancipation of private property from the community, the state has 
become a separate entity, alongside and outside civil society; but it is 
nothing more than the form of organisation which the bourgeois are 
compelled to adopt, both for internal and external purposes, for the 
mutual guarantee of their property and interests. The independence 
of the state is only found nowadays in those countries where the 
estates have not vet completely developed into classes, where the 
estates, done away with in more advanced countries, still play a part 
and there exists a mixture, where consequently no section of the 
population can achieve dominance over the others. This is the case 
particularly m Germany. The most perfect example of the modern 
state is North 1 70 1 America. The modern French, English and 
American writers all express the opinion that the state exists only for 
the sake of private property, so that this view has also been generally 
accepted by the average man. 

Since the state is the form in which the individuals of a ruling class 
assert their common interests, and in which the whole civil society of 
an epoch is epitomised, it follows that all common institutions are set 
up with the help of the state and are given a political form. Hence the 
illusion that law is based on the will, and indeed on the will divorced 
from its real basis — on free will. Similarly, justice is in its turn reduced 
to statute law. 

Civil law develops simultaneously with private property out of the 
disintegration of the natural community. With the Romans the 
development of private property and civil law had no further 
industrial and commercial consequences, because their whole mode 
of production did not alter.* With modern peoples, where the feudal 
community was disintegrated by industry and trade, there began 
with the rise of private property and civil law a new phase, which was 
capable of further development. The very first town which carried 



* [?4arginal note by Engels:] (Usury!) 




The German Ideology. I. Feuerbach 



91 



on an extensive maritime trade in the Middle Ages, Amalfi, also 
developed maritime law. 36 As soon as industry and trade developed 
private property further, first in Italy and later in other countries, 
the highly developed Roman civil law was immediately adopted 
again and raised to authority. When later the bourgeoisie had 
acquired so much power that the princes took up its interests in 
order to overthrow the feudal nobility by means of the bourgeoisie, 
there began in all countries — in France in the sixteenth century — the 
real development of law, which in all 1 7 1 ] countries except England 
proceeded on the basis of the Roman code of laws. In England, too, 
Roman legal principles had to be introduced to further the develop- 
ment of civil law (especially in the case of movable property). (It must 
not be forgotten that law has just as little an independent history as 
religion.) 

In civil law the existing property relations are declared to be 
the result of the general will. The jus utendi et abutendi a itself asserts 
on the one hand the fact that private property has become entirely 
independent of the community, and on the other the illusion that 
private property itself is based solely on the private will, the arbitrary 
disposal of the thing. In practice, the abuti has very definite 
economic limitations for the owner of private property, if he does 
not wish to see his property and hence his jus abutendi pass into other 
hands, since actually the thing, considered merely with reference to 
his will, is not a thing at all, but only becomes a thing, true property, 
in intercourse, and independently of the law (a relationship, which 
the philosophers call an idea*). This juridical illusion, which reduces 
law to the mere will, necessarily leads, in the further development of 
property relations, to the position that a man may have a legal 
title to a thing without really having the thing. If, for instance, the 
income from a piece of land disappears owing to competition, then 
the proprietor has certainly his legal title to it along with the jus utendi 
et abutendi. But he can do nothing with it: he owns nothing as a 
landed proprietor if he has not enough capital elsewhere to cultivate 
his land. This illusion of the jurists also explains the fact that for 
them, as for every code, it is altogether fortuitous that individuals 
enter into relations among themselves (e.g., contracts); it explains why 
they consider that these relations [can] be entered into or not at will, 



* [Marginal note by Marx:] For the philosophers relationship —idea. They only know 
the relation of “Man” to himself and hence for them all real relations become ideas. 



The right of use and of disposal. — Ed. 




92 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



1 72 1 and that their content [rests] purely on the individual free will of 
the contracting parties. 

Whenever, through the development of industry and commerce, 
new forms of intercourse have been evolved (e.g., insurance 
companies, etc.), the law has always been compelled to admit them 
among the modes of acquiring property. 3 

[12. FORMS OF SOCIAL CONSCIOUSNESS] 

The influence of the division of labour on science. 

The role of repression with regard to the state, law, morality, etc. 

It is precisely because the bourgeoisie rules as a class that in the law 
it must give itself a general expression. 

Natural science and history. 

There is no history of politics, law, science, etc., of art, religion, 
etc.* 



Why the ideologists turn everything upside-down. 

Clerics, jurists, politicians. 

Jurists, politicians (statesmen in general), moralists, clerics. 

For this ideological subdivision within a class: 1) The occupation 
assumes an independent existence owing to division of labour. Everyone 
believes his craft to be the true one. Illusions regarding the 
connection between their craft and reality are the more likely to be 
cherished by them because of the very nature of the craft. In 
consciousness — in jurisprudence, politics, etc. — relations become 
concepts; since they do not go beyond these relations, the concepts of 
the relations also become fixed concepts in their mind. The judge, for 
example, applies the code, he therefore regards legislation as the 
real, active driving force. Respect for their goods, because their craft 
deals with general matters. ’ 

Idea of law. Idea of state. The matter is turned upside-down in 
ordinary consciousness. 



* [Marginal note by Marx:] To the “community” as it appears in the ancient state, 
in feudalism and in the absolute monarchy, to this bond correspond especially the 
religious conceptions. 



3 The following notes, written by Marx, were intended for further elabora- 
tion. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. I. Feuerbach 



93 



Religion is from the outset consciousness of the transcendental arising 
from actually existing forces. 

This more popularly. 



Tradition, with regard to law, religion, etc. 

* * * 

[73] a Individuals always proceeded, and always proceed, from 
themselves. Their relations are the relations of their real life-process. 
How does it happen that their relations assume an independent 
existence over against them? and that the forces of their own life 
become superior to them? 

In short: division of labour, the level of which depends on the 
development of the productive power at any particular time. 



Landed property. Communal property. Feudal. Modern. 
Estate property. Manufacturing property. Industrial capital. 



a This, the last, page is not numbered in the manuscript. It contains notes relating 
to the beginning of the authors’ exposition of the materialist conception of history. 
The ideas outlined here are set forth in the clean copy, Section 3 (see this volume, 
pp. 32-35). — Ed. 




THE LEIPZIG COUNCIL 37 



In the third volume of the Wigand’sche Vierteljahrsschrift for 1845 
the battle of the Huns, prophetically portrayed by Kaulbach, 38 
actually takes place. The spirits of the slain, whose fury is not 
appeased even in death, raise a hue and cry, which sounds like the 
thunder of battles and war-cries, the clatter of swords, shields and 
iron waggons. But it is not a battle over earthly things. The holy war 
is being waged not over protective tariffs, the constitution, potato 
blight, 39 banking affairs and railways, but in the name of the most 
sacred interests of the spirit, in the name of “substance”, “self- 
consciousness”, “criticism”, the “unique” and the “true man”. We are 
attending a council of church fathers. As these church fathers are 
the last specimens of their kind, and as here, it is to be hoped, the 
cause of the Most High, alias the Absolute, is being pleaded for the 
last time, it is worth while taking a verbatim report of the proceed- 
ings. 

Here, first of all, is Saint Bruno, who is easily recognised by his stick 
(“become sensuousness, become a stick ”, Wigand, p. 130). a His head 
is crowned with a halo of “pure criticism” and, full of contempt for the 
world, he wraps himself in his “self-consciousness”. He has 
“ smashed religion in its entirety and the state in its manifestations” 
(p. 138), by violating the concept of “substance” in the name of the 
most high self-consciousness. The ruins of the church and “debris” 
of the state lie at his feet, while his glance “strikes down” the “mass- 
es” into the dust. He is like God, he has neither father nor mother, 
he is “his own creation, his own product” (p. 136). In short, he is the 
“Napoleon” of the spirit, in spirit he is “Napoleon”. His spiritual 
exercises consist in constantly “examining himself, and in this 
self-examination he finds the impulse to self-determination” 



Bruno Bauer, “Charakterisrik Ludwig Feuerbachs”. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council 



95 



(p. 1 36); as a result of such wearisome self-recording he has obviously 
become emaciated. Besides “examining” himself — from time to time 
he “examines” also, as we shall see, the Westphalische Dampfboot . a 

Opposite him stands Saint Max, whose services to the Kingdom of 
God consist in asserting that he has established and proved — on 
approximately 600 printed pages b — his identity, that he is not just 
anyone, not some “Tom, Dick or Harry”, but precisely Saint Max 
and no other. About his halo and other marks of distinction only one 
thing can be said: that they are “his object and thereby his property”, 
that they are “unique” and “incomparable” and that they are 
“inexpressible” (p. 148). c He is simultaneously the “phrase” and the 
“owner of the phrase”, simultaneously Sancho Panza and Don 
Quixote. His ascetic exercises consist of sour thoughts about 
thoughtlessness, of considerations throughout many pages about 
inconsiderateness and of the sanctification of unholiness. Incidental- 
ly, there is no need for us to elaborate on his virtues, for concerning 
all the qualities ascribed to him — even if there were more of them 
than the names of God among the Muslims — he is in the habit of 
saying: I am all this and something more, I am the all of this nothing 
and the nothing of this all. He is favourably distinguished from his 
gloomy rival in possessing a certain solemn “ light-heartedness ” and 
from time to time he interrupts his serious ponderings with a “critical 
hurrah ”. 

These two grand masters of the Holy Inquisition summon the 
heretic Feuerbach, who has to defend himself against the grave 
charge of gnosticism. The heretic Feuerbach, “thunders” Saint 
Bruno, is in possession of hyle, d substance, and refuses to hand it over 
lest my infinite self-consciousness be reflected in it. Self-conscious- 
ness has to wander like a ghost until it has taken back into itself all 
things which arise from it and flow into it. It has already swallowed 
the whole world, except for this hyle, substance, which the gnostic 
Feuerbach keeps under lock and key and refuses to hand over. 

Saint Max accuses the gnostic of doubting the dogma revealed by 
the mouth of Saint Max himself, the dogma that “every goose, every 
dog, every horse” is “the perfect, or, if one prefers the superlative 
degree, the most perfect, man”. ( Wigand , p. 187: “The aforesaid 
does not lack a tittle of what makes man a man. Indeed, the same 
applies also to every goose, every dog, every horse.”) 



a See this volume, pp. 112-13. — Ed. 
b Max Stirner, Der Einzige und sein Eigenlhum. — Ed. 
c See Max Stirner, “Recensenten Stirners”. — Ed. 
d Matter, substance. — Ed. 




96 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



Besides the hearing of these important indictments, sentence is 
also pronounced in the case brought by the two saints against Moses 
Hess and in the case brought by Saint Bruno against the authors of 
Die heilige Familie. But as these accused have been busying 
themselves with “worldly affairs” and, therefore, have failed to 
appear before the Santa Casa , 40 they are sentenced in their absence 
to eternal banishment from the realm of the spirit for the term of 
their natural life. 

Finally, the two grand masters are again starting some strange 
intrigues among themselves and against each other.* 



* [The following passage is crossed out in the manuscript:] On the plea that he is 
an “unusually cunning and politic mind” ( Wigand, p. 192) Dottore Graziano, alias 
Arnold Ruge, appears in the background. [This seems to indicate that originally a 
chapter on Ruge was also planned (see Note 7).] 




II 

SAINT BRUNO 



1. “CAMPAIGN” AGAINST FEUERBACH 

Before turning to the solemn discussion which Bauer’s self- 
consciousness has with itself and the world, we should reveal one 
secret. Saint Bruno uttered the battle-cry and kindled the war only 
because he had to “safeguard” himself and his stale, soured criticism 
against the ungrateful forgetfulness of the public, only because he 
had to show that, in the changed conditions of 1845, criticism always 
remained itself and unchanged. He wrote the second volume of the 
“good cause and his own cause” 3 : he stands his ground, he fights pro 
arts et focis. b In the true theological manner, however, he conceals 
this aim of his by an appearance of wishing to “characterise” Feuer- 
bach. Poor Bruno was quite forgotten, as was best proved by the 
polemic between Feuerbach and Stirner, c in which no notice at all 
was taken of him. For just this reason he seized on this polemic in 
order to be able to proclaim himself, as the antithesis of the antago- 
nists, their higher unity, the Holy Spirit. 

Saint Bruno opens his “campaign” with a burst of artillery fire 
against Feuerbach, that is to say, with a revised and enlarged reprint 
of an article which had already appeared in the Norddeutsche Blatter , d 
Feuerbach is made into a knight of “ substance ” in order that Bauer’s 
“ self-consciousness ” shall stand out in stronger relief. In this tran- 



a Bruno Bauer’s article “Charakteristik Ludwig Feuerbachs” is here ironically 
called the second volume of Bauer’s book Die gute. Sache der Freiheit und meine eigene 
Angelegenheit (The Good Cause of Freedom and My Own Cause). — Ed. 

b Literally: for altars and hearths, used in the sense of: for house and home — that 
is, pleading his own cause. — Ed. 

c Feuerbach, “Ueber das ‘Wesen des Christenthums’ in Beziehung auf den 
‘Einzigen und sein Eigenthum’”. — Ed. 

d I. e., Bruno Bauer’s article “Ludwig Feuerbach”. — Ed. 




98 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



substantiation of Feuerbach, which is supposed to be proved by 
all the writings of the latter, our holy man jumps at once from 
Feuerbach’s writings on Leibniz and Bayle 3 to the Wesen des 
Christenthums, leaving out the article against the “positive phi- 
losophers” 41 in the Hallische Jahrbucher. b This “oversight” is “in 
place”. For there Feuerbach revealed the whole wisdom of “self- 
consciousness” as against the positive representatives of “sub- 
stance”, at a time when Saint Bruno was still indulging in specula- 
tion on the immaculate conception. 

It is hardly necessary to mention that Saint Bruno still continues to 
prance about on his old-Hegelian war horse. Listen to the first 
passage in his latest revelations from the Kingdom of God: 

“Hegel combined into one Spinoza’s substance and Fichte’s ego; the unity of 
both, the combination of these opposing spheres, etc., constitutes the peculiar interest 
but, at the same time, the weakness of Hegel’s philosophy. [...] This contradiction in 
which Hegel’s system was entangled had to be resolved and destroyed. But he could 
only do this by making it impossible for all time to put the question: what is the 
relation of self-consciousness to the absolute spirit.... This was possible in two ways. Either 
self-consciousness had to be burned again in the flames of substance, i.e., the pure 
substantiality relation had to be firmly established and maintained, or it had to be 
shown that personality is the creator of its own attributes and essence, that it belongs to 
the concept of personality in general to posit itself” (the “concept” or the 
“personality”?) “as limited, and again to abolish this limitation which it posits by its 
universal essence , for precisely this essence is only the result of its inner self-distinction, of its 
activity” ( Wigand, pp. 86, 87, 88). c 

In Die heilige Familie (p. 220) d Hegelian philosophy was 
represented as a union of Spinoza and Fichte and at the same time the 
contradiction involved in this was emphasised. The specific 
peculiarity of Saint Bruno is that, unlike the authors of Die heilige 
Familie, he does not regard the question of the relation of self- 
consciousness to substance as “a point of controversy within 
Hegelian speculation”, but as a world-historic, even an absolute 
question. This is the sole form in which he is capable of expressing the 
conflicts of the present day. He really believes that the triumph of self- 
consciousness over substance has a most essential influence not only 
on European equilibrium but also on the whole future development 
of the Oregon problem. As to the extent to which the abolition of the 
Corn Laws in England depends on it, very little has so far transpired , 42 



a The reference is to the following works of Feuerbach: Geschichte der neuern 
Philosophic. Darstellung, Entwicklung und Kritih der Leibnitz’schen Philosophic and Pierre 
Bayle. — Ed. 

b Ludwig Feuerbach, “Zur Kritik der ‘positiven Philosophic’ ”. — Ed. 
c Bruno Bauer, “Charakteristik Ludwig Feuerbachs”. — Ed. 

See present edition, Vol. 4, p. 139. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. II. Saint Bruno 



99 



The abstract and nebulous expression into which a real collision is 
distorted by Hegel is held by this “critical” mind to be the real 
collision itself. Bruno accepts the speculative contradiction and 
upholds one part of it against the other. A philosophical phrase about 
a real question is for him the real question itself. Consequently, on 
the one hand, instead of real people and their real consciousness of 
their social relations, which apparently confront them as something 
independent, he has the mere abstract expression: self-consciousness, 
just as, instead of real production, he has the activity of this 
self-consciousness, which has become independent. On the other hand, 
instead of real nature and the actually existing social relations, he has 
the philosophical summing-up of all the philosophical categories or 
names of these relations in the expression: substance; for Bruno, 
along with all philosophers and ideologists, erroneously regards 
thoughts and ideas — the independent intellectual expression of the 
existing world — as the basis of this existing world. It is obvious that 
with these two abstractions, which have become senseless and empty, 
he can perform all kinds of tricks without knowing anything at all 
about real people and their relations. (See, in addition, what is 
said about substance in connection with Feuerbach and concerning 
“humane liberalism” 3 and the “holy” in connection with Saint Max.) 
Hence, he does not forsake the speculative basis in order to solve the 
contradictions of speculation; he manoeuvres while remaining on 
that basis, and he himself still stands so much on the specifically 
Hegelian basis that the relation of “self-consciousness” to the 
“absolute spirit” still gives him no peace. In short, we are confronted 
with the philosophy of self-consciousness th at was announced in the Kritik 
der Synoptiker , carried out in Das entdeckte Chrislenthum and which, 
unfortunately, was long ago anticipated in Hegel’s Phdnornenologie. 
This new philosophy of Bauer’s was completely disposed of in Die 
heilige Familie on page 220 et seq. and on pages 304-0 7. b Here, 
however, Saint Bruno even contrives to caricature himself by 
smuggling in “personality”, in order to be able, with Stirner, to 
portray the single individual as “his own product”, and Stirner as 
Bruno's product. This step forward deserves a brief notice. 

First of all, let the reader compare this caricature with the original, 
the explanation given of self-consciousness in Das entdeckte Christen- 
thum, page 113, and then let him compare this explanation with its 
prototype, with Hegel’s Phdnornenologie, pages 575, 583 and so on. 
(Both these passages are reproduced in Die heilige Familie, pages 



3 See this volume, pp. 40, 54, 232-39, 282-301. — Ed. 
b See present edition, Vol. 4, pp. 139 et seq. and 191-93. — Ed. 




100 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



221, 223, 224. a ) But now let us turn to the caricature! “Personality in 
general”! “Concept”! “Universal essence”! “To posit itself as limited 
and again to abolish the limitation”! “Inner self-distinction”! What 
tremendous “results”! “Personality in general” is either nonsense 
“in general” or the abstract concept of personality. Therefore, it is 
part of the “concept” of the concept of personality to “posit itself as 
limited”. This limitation, which belongs to the “concept” of its 
concept, personality directly afterwards posits “by its universal 
essence”. And after it has again abolished this limitation, it turns out 
that “precisely this essence” is “the result of its inner self-distinction”. 
The entire grandiose result of this intricate tautology amounts, 
therefore, to Hegel’s familiar trick of the self-distinction of man in 
thought, a self-distinction which the unfortunate Bruno stubbornly 
proclaims to be the sole activity of “personality in general”. A fairly 
long time ago it was pointed out to Saint Bruno that there is nothing 
to be got from a “personality” whose activity is restricted to these, by 
now trivial, logical leaps. At the same time the passage quoted 
contains the naive admission that the essence of Bauer’s “personali- 
ty” is the concept of a concept, the abstraction of an abstraction. 

Bruno’s criticism of Feuerbach, insofar as it is new, is restricted to 
hypocritically representing Stirner’s reproaches against Feuerbach 
and Bauer as Bauer’s reproaches against Feuerbach. Thus, for 
example, the assertions that the “essence of man is essence in general 
and something holy”, that “man is the God of man”, that the 
human species is “the Absolute 1 ’, that Feuerbach splits man “into an 
essential and an inessential ego” (although Bruno always declares 
that the abstract is the essential and, in his antithesis of criticism and 
the mass, conceives this split as far more monstrous than Feuerbach 
does), that a struggle must be waged against the “predicates of 
God”, etc. On the question of selfish and selfless love, Bruno, 
polemising with Feuerbach, copies Stirner almost word for word for 
three pages (pp. 133-35) just as he very clumsily copies Stirner’s 
phrases: “every man is his own creation”, “truth is a ghost”, and so 
on. In addition, in Bruno the “creation” is transformed into a 
“product”. We shall return to this exploitation of Stirner by Saint 
Bruno. 

Thus, the first thing that we discovered in Saint Bruno was his 
continual dependence on Hegel. We shall not, of course, dwell 
further on the remarks he has copied from Hegel, but shall only put 
together a few more passages which show how firmly he believes in 
the power of the philosophers and how he shares their illusion that a 

a See present edition, Vol. 4, pp. 139-41. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. II. Saint Bruno 



101 



modified consciousness, a new turn given to the interpretation of 
existing relations, could overturn the whole hitherto existing world. 
Imbued with this faith, Saint Bruno also has one of his pupils 
certify — in issue IV of Wigand’s quarterly, p. 327 — that his phrases 
on personality given above, which were proclaimed by him in 
issue III, were “world-shattering ideas”. 3 

Saint Bruno says ( Wigand, p. 95) b : 

“Philosophy has never been anything but theology reduced to its most general 
form and given its most rational expression.” 

This passage, aimed against Feuerbach, is copied almost word for 
word from Feuerbach’s Philosophie der Zukunft (p. 2): 

“Speculative philosophy is true, consistent, rational theology.” 

Bruno continues: 

“Philosophy, in alliance with religion, has always striven for the absolute 
dependence of the individual and has actually achieved this by demanding and causing 
the absorption of the individual life in universal life, of the accident in substance, of 
man in the absolute spirit.” 

As if Bruno’s “philosophy”, “in alliance with” Hegel’s, and his still 
continuing forbidden association with theology, did not “demand”, 
if not “cause”, the “absorption of man” in the idea of one of his 
“accidents”, that of self-consciousness, as “substance”! Moreover, 
one sees from this whole passage with what joy the church father 
with his “pulpit eloquence” continues to proclaim his “world- 
shattering” faith in the mysterious power of the holy theologians 
and philosophers. Of course, in the interests of the “good cause of 
freedom and his own cause”. c 

On page 105 our godfearing man has the insolence to reproach 
Feuerbach: 

“Feuerbach made of the individual, of the depersonalised man of Christianity, not 
a man, not a true” (!) “real” (!!) “personal” (!!!) “man” (these predicates owe their 
origin to Die heilige Familie and Stirner), “but an emasculated man, a slave” — 

and thereby utters, inter alia, the nonsense that he, Saint Bruno, can 
make people by means of the mind. 

Further on in the same passage he says: 

“According to Feuerbach the individual has to subordinate himself to the species, 
serve it. The species of which Feuerbach speaks is Hegel’s Absolute, and it, too, exists 
nowhere.” 



a “Ueber das Recht des Freigesprochenen...”. — Ed. 
b Bruno Bauer, “Charakteristik Ludwig Feuerbachs”. — Ed. 

c An ironical allusion to Bauer’s book Die gute Sache der Freiheit und meine eigene 
A ngelegenheit. — Ed. 




102 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



Here, as in all the other passages, Saint Bruno does not deprive 
himself of the glory of making the actual relations of individuals 
dependent on the philosophical interpretation of these relations. He 
has not the slightest inkling of the correlation which exists between 
the concepts of Hegel’s “absolute spirit” and Feuerbach’s “species” 
on the one hand and the existing world on the other. 

On page 104 the holy father is mightily shocked by the heresy with 
which Feuerbach transforms the holy trinity of reason, love and will 
into something that “is in individuals and over individuals”, as 
though, in our day, every inclination, every impulse, every need did 
not assert itself as a force “in the individual and over the individual”, 
whenever circumstances hinder their satisfaction. If the holy father 
Bruno experiences hunger, for example, without the means of 
appeasing it, then even his stomach will become a force “in him and 
over him”. Feuerbach’s mistake is not that he stated this fact but that 
in idealistic fashion he endowed it with independence instead of 
regarding it as the product of a definite and surmountable stage of 
historical development. 

Page 111: “Feuerbach is a slave and his servile nature does not allow him to fulfil 
the work of a man , to recognise the essence of religion” (what a fine “work of a 
man”!).... “He does not perceive the essence of religion because he does not know the 
biidge over which he can make his way to the source of religion.” 

Saint Bruno still seriously believes that religion has its own “es- 
sence”. As for the “bridge”, “ over which ” one makes one’s way to the 
“ source of religion”, this asses’ bridge 3 must certainly be an aqueduct. 
At the same time Saint Bruno establishes himself as a curiously 
modernised Charon who has been retired owing to the building of 
the bridge, becoming a tollkeeper b who demands a halfpenny 13 from 
every person crossing the bridge to the spectral realm of religion. 

On page 120 the saint remarks: 

“How could Feuerbach exist if there were no truth and truth were onlv a spectre’’ 
(Stirner, help! 1 ) “of which hitherto man has been afraid?” 



The “man” who fears the “spectre” of “truth” is no other than the 
worthy Bruno himself. Ten pages earlier, on p. 1 10, he had already 
let out the following world-shattering cry of terror at the sight of the 
“spectre” of truth: 

a A pun in the original: Eselsbriicke (asses’ bridge) — an expedient used by dull 
or lazy people to understand a difficult problem. — Ed. 

This word is in English in the manuscript. — Ed. 
c A paraphrase of the expression “Samuel, hilf!” (Samuel, help!) from Carl Maria 
von Weber’s opera Der Freischutz (libretto by Friedrich Kind), Act II, Scene 6. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. II. Saint Bruno 



103 



‘‘Truth which is never of itself encountered as a ready-made object and which 
develops itself and reaches unity only in the unfolding of personality.” 

Thus, we have here not only truth, this spectre, transformed into a 
person which develops itself and reaches unity, but in addition this 
trick is accomplished in a third personality outside it, after the 
manner of the tapeworm. Concerning the holy man’s former love 
affair with truth, when he was still young and the lusts of the flesh 
still strong in him — see Die heilige Familie, p. 115 et seq. a 

How purified of all fleshly lusts and earthly desires our holy man 
now appears is shown by his vehement polemic against Feuerbach’s 
sensuousness. Bruno by no means attacks the highly restricted way in 
which Feuerbach recognises sensuousness. He regards Feuerbach’s 
unsuccessful attempt, since it is an attempt to escape ideology, as — a 
sin. Of course! Sensuousness is lust of the eye, lust of the flesh and 
arrogance b — horror and abomination c in the eyes of the Lord! Do 
you not know that to be fleshlv minded is death, but to be spiritually 
minded is life and peace; for to be fleshly minded is hostility to 
criticism, and everything of the flesh is of this world. And do you 
not know that it is written: the works of the flesh are manifest, they 
are adultery, fornication, uncleanness, obscenity, idolatry, witch- 
craft, enmity, strife, envy, anger, quarrelsomeness, discord, sinful 
gangs, hatred, murder, drunkenness, gluttony and the like. d I pro- 
phesy to you, as I prophesied before, that those who do such works 
will not inherit the kingdom of criticism; but woe to them for in their 
thirst for delights they are following the path of Cain and are falling 
into the error of Balaam, and will perish in a rebellion, like that of 
Korah. These lewd ones feast shamelessly on your alms, and fatten 
themselves. They are clouds without water driven by the wind; bare, 
barren trees, twice dead and uprooted; wild ocean waves frothing 
their own shame; errant stars condemned to the gloom of darkness 
for ever. 4 For we have read that in the last days there will be terrible 
times, people will appear who think much of themselves, lewd vilifiers 
who love voluptuousness f more than criticism, makers of sinful 
gangs, in short, slaves of the flesh. Such people are shunned by Saint 
Bruno, who is spiritually minded and loathes the stained covering of 
the flesh g and for this reason he condemns Feuerbach, whom he re- 



a See present edition, Vol. 4, p. 79 et seq. — Ed. 
b Cf. 1 John 2 : 16.— Ed. 
c Cf. Ezekiel 11 : 18.— Ed. 
d Cf. Galatians 5:19-21. — Ed. 
e Cf. Jude 11-13.— Ed. 
f Cf. 2 Timothy 3 : 1-4.— Ed. 

B Cf. Jude 23.— Ed. 




104 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



gards as the Korah of the gang, to remain outside together with the 
dogs, the magicians, the debauched and the assassins. 3 “Sensuous- 
ness” — ugh! Not only does it throw the saintly church father into the 
most violent convulsions, but it even makes him sing, and on page 
121 he chants the “song of the end and the end of the song”. Sensu- 
ousness — do you know, unfortunate one, what sensuousness is? Sen- 
suousness is — a “stick” (p. 130). Seized with convulsions, Saint Bruno 
even wrestles on one occasion with one of his own theses, just as Jacob 
of blessed memory wrestled with God, with the one difference that 
God twisted Jacob’s thigh, while our saintly epileptic twists all the 
limbs and ties of his own thesis, and so, by a number of striking 
examples, makes clear the identity of subject and object: 

“Feuerbach may say what he likes ... all the same he destroys ” (!) “man... for he trans- 
forms the word man into a mere phrase ... for he does not wholly make” (!) “ and create ” (!) 
“man, but raises the whole of mankind to the Absolute, for in addition he declares not 
mankind, but rather the senses to be the organ of the Absolute, and stamps the sensu- 
ous — the object of the senses, of perception, of sensation — as the Absolute, the indu- 
bitable and the immediately certain. Whereby Feuerbach — such is Saint Bruno’s 
opinion — “can undoubtedly shake layers of the air, but he cannot smash the phenomena 
of human essence, because his innermost” (!) “essence and his vitalising spirit [...] 
already destroys the external” (!) “sound and makes it empty and jarring” (p. 121). 

Saint Bruno himself gives us mysterious but decisive disclosures 
about the causes of his nonsensical attitude: 

“As though my ego does not also possess just this particular sex, un ique, compared 
with all others, and these particular, unique sex organs.” (Besides his “unique sex or- 
gans”, this noble-minded man also possesses a special “unique sex”!) 

This unique sex is explained on page 121 in the sense that: 

“sensuousness, like a vampire, sucks all the marrow and blood from the lifeoi man; it 
is the insurmountable barrier against which man has to deal himself a mortal blow”. 

But even the saintliest man is not pure! They are all sinners and 
lack the glory that they should have before “self-consciousness”. 
Saint Bruno, who in his lonely cell at midnight struggles with 
“substance”, has his attention drawn by the frivolous writings of the 
heretic Feuerbach to women and female beauty. Suddenly his sight 
becomes less keen; his pure self-consciousness is besmirched, and a 
reprehensible, sensuous fantasy plays about the frightened critic 
with lascivious images. The spirit is willing but the flesh is weak. b 
Bruno stumbles, he falls, he forgets that he is the power that “with its 
strength binds, frees and dominates the world ”, c he forgets that 
these products of his imagination are “spirit of his spirit”, he loses all 



a Cf. Revelation 22:15.— Ed. 
b Cf. Matthew 26:41.— Ed. 
c Cf. ibid. 16: 19. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. II. Saint Bruno 



105 



“self-control” and, intoxicated, stammers a dithyramb to female 
beauty, to its “tenderness, softness, womanliness”, to the “full and 
rounded limbs” and the “surging, undulating, seething, rushing and 
hissing, wave-like structure of the body” 3 of woman. Innocence, 
however, always reveals itself — even where it sins. Who does not 
know that a “ surging , undulating, wave-like structure of the body” 
is something that no eye has ever seen, or ear heard? There- 
fore — hush, sweet soul, the spirit will soon prevail over the rebellious 
flesh and set an insurmountable “barrier” to the overflowing, 
seething lusts, “against which” they will soon deal themselves a 
“mortal blow”. 

“Feuerbach” — the saint finally arrives at this through a critical understanding of 
Die heilige Familie — “is a materialist tempered with and corrupted by humanism, i.e., a 
materialist who is unable to endure the earth and its being” (Saint Bruno knows the 
being of the earth as distinct from the earth itself, and knows how one should behave 
in order to “ endure the being of the earth”!) “but wants to spiritualise himself and rise 
into heaven; and at the same time he is a humanist who cannot think and build a 
spiritual world, but one who is impregnated with materialism”, and so on (p. 123). 

Just as for Saint Bruno humanism, according to this, consists in 
“thinking” and in “building a spiritual world”, so materialism 
consists in the following: 

“The materialist recognises only the existing, actual being, matter" (as though man 
with all his attributes, including thought, were not an ‘‘existing, actual being"), “and 
recognises it as actively extending and realising itself in multiplicity, nature" (p. 123). 

First, matter is an existing, actual being, but only in itself, 
concealed; only when it “actively extends and realises itself in mul- 
tiplicity” (an “existing, actual being” “realises itself”!!), only then does 
it become nature. First there exists the concept of matter, an abstrac- 
tion, an idea, and this latter realises itself in actual nature. Word 
for word the Hegelian theory of the pre-existence of the creative 
categories. From this point of view it is understandable that Saint 
Bruno mistakes the philosophical phrases of the materialists con- 
cerning matter for the actual kernel and content of their world out- 

Io ° k ‘ 2. SAINT BRUNO’S VIEWS ON THE STRUGGLE 

BETWEEN FEUERBACH AND STIRNER 

Having thus admonished Feuerbach with a few weighty words, 
Saint Bruno takes a look at the struggle between Feuerbach and the 
unique. The first evidence of his interest in this struggle is a 
methodical, triple smile. 

a Marx and Engels have inserted the words “seething, rushing and hissing” — 
which occur in Schiller’s poem Der Taucher (“The Diver”) — into the passage they 
quote from Bruno Bauer’s article “Charakteristik Ludwig Feuerbachs”. — Ed. 




106 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



“The critic pursues his path irresistibly, confident of victory, and victorious. He is 
slandered — he smiles. He is called a heretic — he smiles. The old world starts a crusade 
against him — he smiles.” 

Saint Bruno — this is thus established — -pursues his path but he 
does not pursue it like other people, he follows a critical course, he 
accomplishes this important action with a smile. 

“He does smile his face into more lines than are in the new map, with the 
augmentation of the Indies. I know my lady will strike him: if she do, he’ll smile and 
take’t for a great art” a — like Shakespeare’s Malvolio. 

Saint Bruno himself does not lift a finger to refute his two 
opponents, he knows a better way of ridding himself of them, he 
leaves them — divide et impera — to their own quarrel. He confronts 
Stirner with Feuerbach’s man (p. 124), and Feuerbach with Stirner’s 
unique (p. 126 et seq.); he knows that they are as incensed against 
each other as the two Kilkenny cats in Ireland, which so completely 
devoured each other that finally only their tails remained. 43 And 
Saint Bruno passes sentence on these tails, declaring that they are 
“ substance ” and, consequently, condemned to eternal damnation. 

In confronting Feuerbach with Stirner he repeats what Hegel said 
of Spinoza and Fichte, where, as we know, the punctiform ego is 
represented as one, and moreover the most stable, aspect of 
substance. However much Bruno formerly raged against egoism, 
which he even considered the odor specificus of the masses, on page 
1 29 he accepts egoism from Stirner — only this should be “not that of 
Max Stirner”, but, of course, that of Bruno Bauer. He brands 
Stirner’s egoism as having the moral defect “that his ego for the 
support of its egoism requites hypocrisy, deception, external 
violence”. For the rest, he believes (see p. 124) in the critical miracles 
of Saint Max and sees in the latter’s struggle (p. 126) “a real effort to 
radically destroy substance”. Instead of dealing with Stirner’s 
criticism of Bauer’s “pure criticism”, he asserts on p. 124 that 
Stirner’s criticism could affect him just as little as any other, “beca- 
use he himself is the critic” . 

Finally Saint Bruno refutes both of them, Saint Max and 
Feuerbach, applying almost literally to Feuerbach and Stirner the 
antithesis drawn by Stirner between the critic Bruno Bauer and the 
dogmatist. 

Wigand, p. 1 38: “Feuerbach puts himself in opposition to, and thereby ” (!) “ stands in 
opposition to, the unique. He is a communist and wants to be one. The unique is an egoist 



d Shakespeare, Twelfth Night, Act III, Scene 2. Marx and Engels quote these lines 
from the German translation by August Wilhelm von Schlegel. But they have 
substituted the word Kunst (art) for the word Gunst (favour). — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. II. Saint Bruno 



107 



and has to be one; he is the holy one, the other the profane one, he is the good one, the 
other the evil one, he is God, the other is man. Both are dogmatists .” 

The point is, therefore, that he accuses both of dogmatism. 

Der Einzige und sein Eigenthum, p. 194: “The critic is afraid of becoming dogmatic 
or of putting forward dogmas. Obviously, he would then become the opposite of a 
critic, a dogmatist; he who as a critic was good, would now become evil, or from being 
unselfish ” (a Communist) “would become an egoist, etc. Not a single dogma! — that is his 
dogma.” 



3. SAINT BRUNO VERSUS THE AUTHORS 
OF DIE HEILIGE FAMILIE 

Saint Bruno, who has disposed of Feuerbach and Stirner in the 
manner indicated and who has “cut the unique off from all 
progress”, now turns against the apparent “consequences of 
Feuerbach”, the German Communists and, especially, the authors of 
Die heilige Familie. The expression “real humanism”, which he 
found in the preface to this polemic treatise, 3 provides the main basis 
of his hypothesis. He will recall a passage from the Bible: 

“And I, brethren, could not speak unto you as unto spiritual, but as unto carnal” 
(in our case it was just the opposite), “even as unto babes in Christ. I have fed you with 
milk, and not with meat: for hitherto ye were not able to bear it” (1 Corinthians, 
3:1-2). 

The first impression that Die heilige Familie made on the worthy 
church father was one of profound distress and serious, respectable 
sorrow. The one good side of the book is that it 

“showed what Feuerbach had to become, and the position his philosophy can adopt, if 
it desires to fight against criticism” (p. 138), 

that, consequently, it combined in an easy-going way “desiring” with 
“what can be” and “what must be”, but this good side does not out- 
weigh its many distressing sides. Feuerbach’s philosophy, which 
strangely enough is presupposed here, 

“dare not and cannot understand the critic, dare not and cannot know and perceive criti- 
cism in its development, dare not and cannot know that, in relation to all that is 
transcendental, criticism is a constant struggle and victory, a continual destruction and 
creation, the sole ” (!) “creative and productive principle. It dare not and cannot know 
how the critic has worked, and still works, to posit and to make” (!) “the transcendental 
forces, which up to now have suppressed mankind and not allowed it to breathe and 
live, into what they really are, the spirit of the spirit, the innermost of the innermost, a 
native thing” (!) “out of and in the native soil, products and creations of 
self-consciousness. It dare not and cannot know that the critic and only the critic has 
smashed religion in its entirety, and the state in its various manifestations, etc.” 
(pp. 138, 139). 



See present edition, Vol. 4, p. 7. — Ed. 




108 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



Is this not an exact copy of the ancient Jehovah, who runs after his 
errant people who found greater delight in the cheerful pagan gods, 
and cries out: 

“Hear me, Israel, and close not your ear, Judah! Am I not the Lord your God, who 
led you out of the land of Egypt into the land flowing with milk and honey, and 
behold, from your earliest youth you have done evil in my sight and angered me with 
the work of my hands and turned your back unto me and not your face towards me, 
though I invariably tutored you; and you have brought abominations into my house 
to defile it, and built the high places of Baal in the valley of the son of Himmon, which 
I did not command, and it never entered my head that you should do such 
abominations; and I have sent to you my servant Jeremiah, to whom I did address my 
word, beginning with the thirteenth year of the reign of King Josiah, son of Amon, 
unto this day — and for twenty-three years now he has been zealously preaching to 
you, but ye have not harkened. Therefore says the Lord God: Who has ever 
heard the like of the virgin of Israel doing such an abomination. For rain water does 
not disappear so quickly as my people forgets me. O earth, earth, earth, hear the word 
of the Lord!” 3 

Thus, in a lengthy speech on “to dare” and “to be able”, Saint 
Bruno asserts that his communist opponents have misunderstood 
him. The way in which he describes criticism in this recent speech, 
the way in which he transforms the former forces that suppressed 
“the life of mankind” into “transcendental forces”, and these 
transcendental forces into the “spirit of the spirit”, and the way in 
which he presents “criticism” as the sole branch of production 
proves that the apparent misconception is nothing but a disagreeable 
conception. We proved that Bauer’s criticism is beneath all criticism, 
owing to which we have inevitably become dogmatists. He even in all 
seriousness reproaches us for our insolent disbelief in his ancient 
phrases. The whole mythology of independent concepts, with Zeus 
the Thunderer — self-consciousness — at the head, is paraded here 
once again to the “jingling of hackneyed phrases of a whole janissary 
band of current categories”. (Liter atur-Zeitung, cf. Die heilige Familie, 
p. 234 b ). First of all, of course, the myth of the creation of the world, 
i.e., of the hard “ labour ” of the critic, which is “the sole creative and 
productive principle, a constant struggle and victory, a continual de- 
struction and creation”, “working” and “having worked”. Indeed, 
the reverend father even reproaches Die heilige Familie for under- 
standing “criticism” in the same way as he understands it himself in 
the present rejoinder. After taking back “substance” “into the land 
of its birth, self-consciousness, the criticising and” (since Die heilige 



3 Cf. Jeremiah 2 : 6, 32 : 22, 30, 33-35, 25 : 3, 19 : 3, 18 : 13, 14, 22 : 29 .— Ed. 
The passage from “Correspondenz aus der Provinz” published in the Allgemeine 
Literatur-Zeitung was quoted in The Holy Family (see present edition, Vol. 4, p. 148). — 
Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. II. Saint Bruno 



109 



Familie also) “the criticised man, and discarding it” (self-conscious- 
ness here seems to take the place of an ideological lumber-room), 
he continues: 

“It” (the alleged philosophy of Feuerbach) “dare not know that criticism and the 
critics, as long as they have existed” (!)“have guided and made history, that even their 
opponents and all the movements and agitations of the present time are their creation, 
that it is they alone who hold power in their hands, because strength is in their consciousness, 
and because they derive power from themselves, from their deeds, from criticism, from 
their opponents, from their creations: that only by the act of criticism is man freed, 
and thereby men also, and man is created” (!) “and thereby mankind as well”. 

Thus, criticism and the critics are first of all two wholly different 
subjects, existing aqd operating apart from each other. The critic is a 
subject different from criticism, and criticism is a subject different 
from the critic. This personified criticism, criticism as a subject, is 
precisely that “critical criticism” against which Die heilige Familie was 
directed. “Criticism and the critics, as long as they have existed, have 
guided and made history.” It is clear that they could not do so “as 
long as they” did not “exist”, and it is equally clear that “as long as 
they have existed” they “made history” in their own fashion. Finally, 
Saint Bruno goes so far as to “dare and be able” to give us one of the 
most profound explanations about the state-shattering power of 
criticism, namely, that “criticism and the critics hold power in their 
hands, because” (a fine “because”!) “ strength is in their consciousness” , 
and, secondly, that these great manufacturers of history “hold power 
in their hands”, because they “derive power from themselves and 
from criticism” (i.e., again from themselves) — whereby it is still, 
unfortunately, not proven that it is possible to “derive” anything at 
all from there, from “themselves”, from “criticism”. On the basis of 
criticism’s own words, one should at least believe that it must be 
difficult to “derive” from there anything more than the category of 
“substance” “discarded” there. Finally, criticism also “derives” “from 
criticism” “power” for a highly monstrous oracular dictum. For it 
reveals to us a secret that was hidden 3 from our fathers and unknown 
to our grandfathers, the secret that “only by the act of criticism is 
man created, and thereby mankind as well” — whereas, up to now, 
criticism was erroneously regarded as an act of people who existed 
prior to it owing to quite different acts. Hence it seems that Saint 
Bruno himself came “into the world, from the world, and to the 
world” through “criticism”, i.e., by generatio aequivoca. b All this is, 
perhaps, merely another interpretation of the following passage 

a Cf. Colossians 1 : 26. — Ed. 

b Spontaneous generation. — Ed. 




110 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



from the Book of Genesis: And Adam knew, i.e., criticised, Eve his 
wife: and she conceived, 3 etc. 

Thus we see here the whole familiar critical criticism, which was 
already sufficiently characterised in Die heilige Familie, confronting 
us again with all its trickery as though nothing had happened. There 
is no need to be surprised at this, for the saint himself complains, on 
page 140, that Die heilige Familie “cuts criticism off from all 
progress”. With the greatest indignation Saint Bruno reproaches the 
authors of Die heilige Familie because, by means of a chemical 
process, they evaporated Bauer’s criticism from its “fluid” state into a 
“ crystalline ” state. 

It follows that “institutions of mendicancy”, the “baptismal 
certificate of adulthood”, the “regions of pathos and thunder-like 
aspects”, the “Mussulman conceptual affliction” (Die heilige Familie, 
pp. 2, 3, 4 b according to the critical Literatur-Zeitung ) — all this is 
nonsense only if it is understood in the “crystalline” manner. And 
the twenty-eight historical howlers of which criticism was proved 
guilty in its excursion on “Englische Tagesfragen” c — are they not 
errors when looked at from the “fluid” point of view? Does criticism 
insist that ; from the fluid point of view, it prophesied a priori the 
Nauwerck conflict 44 — long after this had taken place before its 
eyes — and did not construct it post festum? d Does it still insist that the 
word marechal could mean “farrier” from the “crystalline” point of 
view, but from the “fluid” point of view at any rate must mean 
“marshal”? Or that although in the “crystalline” conception “ un fait 
physique” may mean “a physical fact”, the true “fluid” translation 
should be “a fact of physics”? Or that “la malveillance de nos bourgeois 
juste-milieux” e in the “fluid” state still means “the carefreeness of our 
good burghers”? Does it insist that, from the “fluid” point of view, 
“a child that does not, in its turn, become a father or mother is 
essentially a daughter ”? That someone can have the task “of 
representing, as it were, the last tear of grief shed by the past”? That 
the various concierges, lions, grisettes, marquises, scoundrels and 
wooden doors in Paris in their “fluid” form are nothing but phases 

3 Cf. Genesis 4 : I . — Ed. 

The expressions quoted are from Carl Reichardt’s reviews, published in the 
Allgerneine Literatur-Zeitung, of the following books: Karl Heinrich Briiggemann, 
Preussens Beruf in der deutschen Staats-Entwicklung..., and Daniel Benda, Katechismus fur 
ivahlberechtigte Burger in Preussen. They are also quoted in The Holy Family (see present 
edition, Vol. 4, p. 10). — Ed. 

c An article by Julius Faucher. — Ed. 

d An allusion to the article by [E.j J[ungnitz] “Herr Nauwerk und die 
philosophische Facultat” published in Allgerneine Literatur-Zeitung. — Ed. 

e The ill will of our middle-of-the-road bourgeois. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. II. Saint Bruno 



111 



of the mystery “in whose concept in general it belongs to posit itself 
as limited and again to abolish this limitation which is posited- by its 
universal essence, for precisely this essence is only the result of its 
inner self-distinction, its activity” 3 ? That critical criticism in the 
“fluid” sense “pursues its path irresistibly, victorious and confident 
of victory”, when in dealing with a question it first asserts that it has 
revealed its “true and general significance” and then admits that it 
“had neither the will nor the right to go beyond criticism”, and 
finally admits that “it had still to take one step but that step was 
impossible because — it was impossible” (Die heilige Familie, p. 184 b )? 
That from the “fluid” point of view “the future is still the work” of 
criticism, although “fate may decide as it will” c ? That from the fluid 
point of view criticism achieved nothing superhuman when it “came 
into contradiction with its true elements — a contradiction which had 
already found its solution in these same elements ” d ? 

The authors of Die heilige Familie have indeed committed the 
frivolity of conceiving these and hundreds of other statements as 
statements expressing firm, “crystalline” nonsense — but the synoptic 
gospels should be read in a “fluid” way, i.e., according to the sense of 
their authors, and on no account in a “crystalline” way, i.e., accord- 
ing to their actual nonsense, in order to arrive at true faith and to 
admire the harmony of the critical household. 

“Engels and Marx, therefore, know only the criticism of the Literatur-Zeitung” e 

— a deliberate lie, proving how “fluidly” our saint has read a book 
in which his latest works are depicted merely as the culmination of all 
the “work he has done”. But the church father lacked the calm to 
read in a crystalline way, for he fears his opponents as rivals who 
contest his canonisation and “want to deprive him of his sanctity, in 
order to make themselves sanctified”. 

Let us, incidentally, note the fact that, according to Saint Bruno’s 
present statement, his Literatur-Zeitung by no means aimed at 
founding “social society” or at “representing, as it were, the last tear 
of grief” shed by German ideology, nor did it aim at putting mind in 
the sharpest opposition to the mass and developing critical criticism 
in all its purity, but only — at “depicting the liberalism and radicalism 
of 1 842 and their echoes in their half-heartedness and phrase-mon- 
gering”, hence at combating the “echoes” of what has long disap- 

a Bruno Bauer, “Charakteristik Ludwig Feuerbachs”. — Ed. 
b See present edition, Vol. 4, p. 118. — Ed. 
c B. Bauer, “Neueste Schriften fiber die Judenfrage”.— Ed. 
d B. Bauer, “Was ist jetzt der Gegenstand der Kritik?” — Ed. 
e Bruno Bauer, “Charakteristik Ludwig Feuerbachs”. — Ed. 




112 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



peared. Tant de bruit pour une omelette / a Incidentally, it is just here 
that the conception of history peculiar to German theory is again 
shown in its “purest” light. The year 1842 is held to be the period of 
the greatest brilliance of German liberalism, because at that time 
philosophy took part in politics. Liberalism vanishes for the critic 
with the cessation of the Deutsche Jahrbiicher and the Rheinische Zei- 
tung, the organs of liberal and radical theory. After that, apparently, 
there remain only the “echoes” — whereas in actual fact only now, 
when the German bourgeoisie feels a real need for political power, 
a need produced by economic relations, and is striving to satisfy it, 
has liberalism in Germany an actual existence and thereby the 
chance of some success. 

Saint Bruno’s profound distress over Die heilige Familie did not 
allow him to criticise this work “out of himself, through himself and 
with himself”. To be able to master his pain he had first to obtain the 
work in a “fluid” form. He found this fluid form in a confused 
review, teeming with misunderstandings, in the Westphalische 
Dampfboot, May issue, pp. 206-14. b All his quotations are taken from 
passages quoted in the Westphalische Dampfboot and he quotes 
nothing that is not quoted there. 

The language of the saintly critic is likewise determined by the 
language of the Westphalian critic. In the first place, all the 
statements from the Foreword which are quoted by the Westphalian 
( Dampfboot , p. 206) are transferred to the Wigand’sche Viertel- 
jahrsschrift (pp. 140, 141). This transference forms the chief part of 
Bauer’s criticism, according to the old principle already recom- 
mended by Hegel: 

“To trust common sense and, moreover, in order to keep up with the times and 
advance with philosophy, to read reviews of philosophical works, perhaps even their 
prefaces and introductory paragraphs; for the latter give the general principles on 
which everything turns, while the former give, along with the historical information, 
also an appraisal which, because it is an appraisal, even goes beyond Lhat which is 
appraised This beaten track can be followed in one’s dressing-gown; but the elevated 
feeling of the eternal, the sacred, the infinite, pursues its path in the vestments of a 
high priest, a path” which, as we have seen. Saint Bruno also knows how to “pursue” 
while “striking down” (Hegel, Phanomenologie, p. 54). 

The Westphalian critic, after giving a few quotations from the 
- preface, continues: 

“Thus the preface itself leads to the battlefield of the book”, etc. (p. 206). 



a Much ado about an omelette! An exclamation which Jacques Vallee, Sieur des 
Barreaux, is supposed to have made when a thunderstorm occurred while he was 
eating an omelette on a fast-day. — Ed. 
b See this volume, p. 15. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. II. Saint Bruno 



113 



The saintly critic, having transferred these quotations into the 
Wigand’sche Vierteljahrsschrift, makes a more subtle distinction and 
says: 

“Such is the terrain and the enemy which Engels and Marx have created for battle." 

From the discussion of the critical proposition: “the worker 
creates nothing”, the Westphalian critic gives only the summarising 
conclusion. 

The saintly critic actually believes that this is all that was said about 
the proposition, copies out the Westphalian quotation on page 141 
and rejoices at the discovery that only “assertions” have been put 
forward in opposition to criticism. 

Of the examination of the critical outpourings about love, the 
Westphalian critic on page 209 first writes out the corpus delicti in part 
and then a few disconnected sentences from the refutation, which he 
desires to use as an authority for his nebulous, sickly-sweet 
sentimentality. 

On pages 141-42 the saintly critic copies him out word for word, 
sentence by sentence, in the same order as his predecessor quotes. 

The Westphalian critic exclaims over the corpse of Herr Julius 
Faucher: “Such is the fate of the beautiful on earth!” 3 

The saintly critic cannot finish his “hard work” without ap- 
propriating this exclamation to use irrelevantly on page 142. 

The Westphalian critic on page 212 gives a would-be summary of 
the arguments which are aimed against Saint Bruno himself in Die 
heilige Familie. 

The saintly critic cheerfully and literally copies out all this stuff 
together with all the Westphalian exclamations. He has not the 
slightest idea that nowhere in the whole of this polemic discourse does 
anyone reproach him for “transforming the problem of political 
emancipation into that of human emancipation”, for “wanting to kill 
the Jews”, for “transforming the Jews into theologians”, for 
“transforming Hegel into Herr Hinrichs”, etc. Credulously, the 
saintly critic repeats the Westphalian critic’s allegation that in Die 
heilige Familie Marx volunteers to provide some sort of little schola- 
stic treatise “in reply to Bauer’s silly self-apotheosis” . Yet the words 
“silly self-apotheosis”, which Saint Bruno gives as a quotation, are 
nowhere to be found in the whole of Die heilige Familie, but they do 
occur with the Westphalian critic. Nor is the little treatise offered as a 
reply to the “self -apology” of criticism on pages 150-63 of Die heilige 
Familie, but only in the following section on page 165, b in 



a Schiller, Wallenstein's Tod, Act IV, Scene 12. — Ed. 
b See present edition, Vol. 4, pp. 99-106 and 107. — Ed. 




114 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



connection with the world-historic question: “Why did Herr Bauer 
have to engage in politics?” 

Finally on page 143 Saint Bruno presents Marx as an “ amusing 
comedian ”, here again following his Westphalian model, who 
resolved the “world-historic drama of critical criticism”, on page 
213, into a “most amusing comedy ”, 

Thus one sees how the opponents of critical criticism “dare and 
can” “know how the critic has worked, and still works”! 

4. OBITUARY FOR “M. HESS” 

“What Engels and Marx could not yet do, M. Hess has accomplished.” 

Such is the great, divine transition which — owing to the relative 
“can” and “cannot” be done of the evangelists — has taken so firm a 
hold of the holy man’s fingers that it has to find a place, relevantly or 
irrelevantly, in every article of the church father. 

“What Engels and Marx could not yet do, M. Hess has 
accomplished.” But what is this “what” that “Engels and Marx could 
not yet do”? Nothing more nor less, indeed, than — to criticise 
Stirner. And why was it that Engels and Marx “could not yet” criticise 
Stirner? For the sufficient reason that — Stirner’s book had not yet 
appeared when they wrote Die heilige Familie. 

This speculative trick — of joining together everything and bring- 
ing the most diverse things into an apparent causal relation — has 
truly taken possession not only of the head of our saint but also of his 
fingers. With him it has become devoid of any contents and 
degenerates into a burlesque manner of uttering tautologies with an 
important mien. For example, already in the Allgemeine Literatur- 
Zeitung (I, 5) we read: 

“The difference between my work and the pages which, for example, a Philippson 
covers with writing” (that is, the empty pages on which, “for example, a Philippson” 
writes) “must, therefore, be so constituted as in fact it is” ! ! ! a 

“M. Hess”, for whose writings Engels and Marx take absolutely no 
responsibility, seems such a strange phenomenon to the saintly critic 
that he is only capable of copying long excerpts from Die letzten 
Philosophen and passing the judgment that “on some points this 
criticism has not understood Feuerbach or also” (O theology!) “the 
vessel wishes to rebel against the potter”. Cf. Epistle to the Romans, 
9 : 20-21. Having once more performed the “hard work” of quoting, 
our saintly critic finally arrives at the conclusion that Hess copies 



a B. Bauer, “Neueste Schriften fiber die Judenfrage”. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. II. Saint Bruno 



115 



from Hegel, since he uses the two words “united” and “develop- 
ment”. Saint Bruno, of course, had in a round-about way to try to 
turn against Feuerbach the proof given in Die heilige Familie of his 
own complete dependence on Hegel. 

“See, that is how Bauer had to end! He fought as best he could 
against all the Hegelian categories”, with the exception of self- 
consciousness — particularly in the glorious struggle of the Literatur- 
Zeitung against Herr Hinrichs. How he fought and conquered them 
we have already seen. For good measure, let us quote Wigand, 
page 110, where he asserts that 

the “true” (1) “ solution ” (2) “of contradictions ” (3) “in nature and history” (4), the 
“ true unity ” (5) “of separate relations” (6), the “genuine” (7) “basis” (8) “and abyss” 
(9) “of religion, the truly infinite ” (10), “irresistible, self-creative” (11) “personality” 
(12) “has not yet been found”. 

These three lines contain not two doubtful Hegelian categories, 
as in the case of Hess, but a round dozen of “true, infinite, 
irresistible” Hegelian categories which reveal themselves as such by 
“the true unity of separate relations” — “see, that is how Bauer had to 
end”! And if the holy man thinks that in Hess he has discovered a 
Christian believer, not because Hess “hopes” — as Bruno says — but 
because he does not hope and because he talks of the “resurrection”, 
then our great church father enables us, on the basis of this same 
page 110, to demonstrate his very pronounced Judaism. He declares 
there 

“that the true, living man in the flesh has not yet been bom”!!! (a new elucidation about 
the determination of the “unique sex”) “and the mongrel produced” (Bruno Bauer?!?) 
“is not yet able to master all dogmatic formulas” , etc. 

That is to say, the Messiah is not yet born, the son of man has 
first to come into the world and this world, being the world of the 
Old Testament, is still under the rod of the law, of “dogmatic 
formulas”. 

Just as Saint Bruno, as shown above, made use of “Engels and 
Marx” for a transition to Hess, so now the latter serves him to bring 
Feuerbach finally into causal connection with his excursions on 
Stirner, Die heilige Familie and Die letzten Philosophen. 

“See, that is how Feuerbach had to end!” “Philosophy had to end piously ”, etc. 

( Wigand , p. 145.) 

The true causal connection, however, is that this exclamation is 
an imitation of a passage from Hess’ Die letzten Philosophen aimed 
against Bauer, among others (Preface, p. 4): 

“Thus [...] and in no other way had the last offspring of the Christian ascetics [...] 
to take farewell of the world.” 




116 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



Saint Bruno ends his speech for the prosecution against Feuerbach 
and his alleged accomplices with the reproach to Feuerbach that all 
he can do is to “trumpet”, to “blow blasts on a trumpet”, whereas 
Monsieur B. Bauer or Madame la critique, the “mongrel produced”, 
to say nothing of the continual “destruction”, “ drives forth in his 
triumphal chariot and gathers new triumphs ” (p. 125), “hurls down from 
the throne” (p. 119), “slays” (p. Ill), “strikes down like thunder” 
(p. 115), “destroys once and for all” (p. 120), “shatters” (p. 121), 
allows nature merely to “vegetate” (p. 120), builds “stricter” (!) 
“prisons” (p. 104) and, finally, with “crushing” pulpit eloquence 
expatiates, on p. 105, in a brisk, pious, cheerful and free 3 fashion on 
the “stably-strongly-firmly-existing”, hurling “rock-like matter and 
rocks” at Feuerbach’s head (p. 1 10) and, in conclusion, by a side 
thrust vanquishes Saint Max as well, by adding “the most abstract 
abstractness” and “the hardest hardness” (on p. 124) to “critical 
criticism”, “social society” and “rock-like matter and rocks”. 

All this Saint Bruno accomplished “through himself, in himself 
and with himself”, because he is “He himself”; indeed, he is “him- 
self always the greatest and can always be the greatest” (is and can 
be!) “through himself, in himself and with himself” (p. 136). That’s 
that. 

Saint Bruno would undoubtedly be dangerous to the female sex, 
for he is an “irresistible personality”, if “in the same measure on 
the other hand” he did not fear “sensuousness as the barrier 
against which man has to deal himself a mortal blow”. Therefore, 
“through himself, in himself and with himself” he will hardly pluck 
any flowers but rather allow them to wither in infinite longing and 
hysterical yearning for the “irresistible personality”, who “possesses 
this unique sex and these unique, particular sex organs”.* 



* [The following passage is crossed out in the manuscript:] 

5. Saint Bruno in His “Triumphal Chariot” 

Before leaving our church father “victorious and confident of victory”, let us for a 
moment mingle with the gaping crowd that comes up running just as eagerly when he 
“drives forth in his triumphal chariot and gathers new triumphs” as when General 
Tom Thumb with his four ponies provides a diversion. It is not surprising that we 
hear the humming of street-songs, for to be welcomed with street-songs “belongs after 
all to the concept” of triumph “in general”. 



a “Brisk, pious, cheerful and free” (“ frisch , fromm, frohlich und frei ”) — the initial 
words of a students’ saying, which were turned by Ludwig Jahn into the motto of the 
sport movement he initiated. — Ed. 




Ill 

SAINT MAX 45 

“Was jehen mir die jrinen Beeme an ?” 3 

Saint Max exploits, “employs” or “uses” the Council to deliver a 
long apologetic commentary on “ the book” , which is none other than 
“the book”, the book as such, the book pure and simple, i.e., the 
perfect book, the Holy Book, the book as something holy, the book as 
the holy of holies, the book in heaven, viz., Der Einzige und sein 
Eigenthum. “The book”, as we know, fell from the heavens towards 
the end of 1844 and took on the shape of a servant with O. Wigand 
in Leipzig. 46 It was, therefore, at the mercy of the vicissitudes of 
terrestrial life and was attacked by three “unique ones”, viz., the 
mysterious personality of Szeliga, the gnostic Feuerbach and Hess. h 
However much at every moment Saint Max as creator towers over 
himself as a creation, as he does over his other creations, he 
nevertheless took pity on his weakly offspring and, in order to 
defend it and ensure its safety, let out a loud “critical hurrah”. In 
order to fathom in all their significance both this “critical hurrah” 
and Szeligds mysterious personality, we must here, to some extent, 
deal with church history and look more closely at “the book”. Or, to 
use the language of Saint Max: we “shall episodically put” “into this 
passage” a church-historical “meditation” on Der Einzige und sein 
Eigenthum “simply because” “it seems to us that it could contribute to 
the elucidation of the rest”. 

3 “What are the green trees to me?” — a paraphrase (in the Berlin dialect) of a 
sentence from Heine’s work Reisebilder, Dritter Teil “Die Bader von Lucca”, Kapitel 
IV.— Ed. 

b Szeliga, “Der Einzige und sein Eigenthum”; Feuerbach, “Uber das ‘Wesen des 
Ch risten thums’ in Beziehung auf den ‘Einzigen und sein Eigenthum’”; Hess, 
Die letzten Philosophen. — Ed. 




118 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



“Lift up your heads, O ye gates; and be ye lift up, ye everlasting doors; and the 
King of Glory shall come in. 

“Who is this King of Glory? The War-Lord strong and mighty, the War-Lord 
mighty in battle. 

“Lift up your heads, O ye gates; even lift them up, ye everlasting doors; and the 
King of Glory shall come in. 

“Who is this King of Glory? The Lord Unique/ he is the King of Glory,” (Psalms, 

24 : 7 - 10 ). 



In the Bible “The Lord of Hosts” 



Ed. 




1. THE UNIQUE AND HIS PROPERTY 

The man who “has based his cause on nothing” 3 begins his 
lengthy “critical hurrah” like a good German, straightway with a 
jeremiad: “Is there anything that is not to be my cause?” (p. 5 of the 
“book”). And he continues lamenting heart-rendingly that “every- 
thing is to be his cause”, that “God’s cause, the cause of mankind, of 
truth and freedom, and in addition the cause of his people, of his 
lord”, and thousands of other good causes, are imposed on him. 
Poor fellow! The French and English bourgeois complain about lack 
of markets, trade crises, panic on the stock exchange, the political 
situation prevailing at the moment, etc.; the German petty 
bourgeois, whose active participation in the bourgeois movement has 
been merely an ideal one, and who for the rest exposed only himself 
to risk, sees his own cause simply as the “good cause”, the “cause of 
freedom, truth, mankind”, etc. 

Our German school-teacher simply believes this illusion of the 
German petty bourgeois and on three pages he provisionally 
discusses all these good causes. 

He investigates “God’s cause”, “the cause of mankind” (pp. 6 
and 7) and finds these are “purely egoistical causes”, that both 
“God” and “mankind” worry only about what is theirs, that “truth, 
freedom, humanity, justice” are “only interested in themselves and 
not in us, only in their own well-being and not in ours” — from which 



3 Here and below Marx and Engels paraphrase the first lines of Goethe’s poem 
Vanitas! Vanitatum vanitas !: “Ich hab’ mein’ Sach’ auf Nichts gestellt.” (“I have 
based my cause on nothing.”) “Ich hab’ mein’ Sach’ auf Nichts gestellt” is the heading 
of Stirner’s preface to his book. — Ed. 



6—2086 




120 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



he concludes that all these persons “are thereby exceptionally well- 
off”. He goes so far as to transform these idealistic phrases — God, 
truth, etc. — into prosperous burghers who “are exceptionally well- 
off” and enjoy a “ profitable egoism”. But this vexes the holy egoist: 
“And I?” he exclaims. 

“I, for my part, draw the lesson from this and, instead of continuing to serve 
these great egoists, I should rather be an egoist myself!” (p. 7) 

Thus we see what holy motives guide Saint Max in his transition 
to egoism. It is not the good things of this world, not treasures which 
moth and rust corrupt, not the capital belonging to his fellow unique 
ones, but heavenly treasure, the capital which belongs to God, truth, 
freedom, mankind, etc., that gives him no peace. 

If it had not been expected of him that he should serve numerous 
good causes, he would never have made the discovery that he also 
has his “own” cause, and therefore he would never have based this 
cause of his “on nothing” (i.e., the “book”). 

If Saint Max had looked a little more closely at these various 
“causes” and the “owners” of these causes, e.g., God, mankind, 
truth, he would have arrived at the opposite conclusion: that egoism 
based on the egoistic mode of action of these persons must be just as 
imaginary as these persons themselves. 

Instead of this, our saint decides to enter into competition with 
“God” and “truth” and to base his cause on himself — 

“on myself, on the I that is, just as much as God, the nothing of everything else, the I 
that is everything for me, the I that is the unique.... I am nothing in the sense of void, 
but the creative nothing, the nothing from which I myself, as creator, create 
everything.” 



The holy church father could also have expressed this last 
proposition as follows: I am everything in the void of nonsense, “6ut” 
I am the nugatory creator, the all, from which I myself, as creator, 
create nothing. 

Which of these two readings is the correct one will become evident 
later. So much for the preface. 

The “book” itself is divided like the book “of old”, into the Old 
and New Testament — namely, into the unique history of man (the 
Law and the Prophets) and the inhuman history of the unique (the 
Gospel of the Kingdom of God). The former is history in the 
framework of logic, the logos confined in the past; the latter is logic 
in history, the emancipated logos, which struggles against the 
present and triumphantly overcomes it. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



121 



THE OLD TESTAMENT: MAN 47 
1. The Book of Genesis, i.e., A Man’s Life 

Saint Max pretends here that he is writing the biography of his 
mortal enemy, “man”, and not of a “ unique ” or “real individual”. 
This ties him up in delightful contradictions. 

As becomes every normal genesis “a man’s life” begins ab ovo, 
with the “child”. As revealed to us on page 13, the child 

“from the outset lives a life of struggle against the entire world, it resists everything 
and everything resists it”. “Both remain enemies” but “with awe and respect” and 
“are constantly on the watch, looking for each other’s weaknesses ” . 

This is further amplified, on page 14: 

“we”, as children, “try to find out the basis of things or what lies behind them; there- 
fore ” (so no longer out of enmity) “we are trying to discover everybody’s weaknesses” . 
(Here the finger of Szeliga, the mystery-monger, is evident. 3 ) 

Thus, the child immediately becomes a metaphysician, trying to 
find out the “ basis of things”. 

This speculating child, for whom “the nature of things” lies closer 
to his heart than his toys, “sometimes” in the long run, succeeds in 
coping with the “world of things”, conquers it and then enters a new 
phase, the age of youth, when he has to face a new “arduous struggle 
of life”, the struggle against reason, for the “ spirit means the first 
self-discovery” and: “We are above the world, we are spirit” (p. 15). 
The point of view of the youth is a “heavenly one”; the child merely 
“learned”, “he did not dwell on purely logical or theological 
problems” — just as (the child) “Pilate” hurriedly passed over the 
question: “What is truth?” b (p. 17). The youth “tries to master 
thoughts”, he “understands ideas, the spirit ” and “seeks ideas”; he 
“is engrossed in thought” (p. 16), he has “absolute thoughts, i.e., 
nothing but thoughts, logical thoughts”. The youth who thus “deports 
himself”, instead of chasing after young women and other earthly 
things, is no other than the young “Stirner”, the studious Berlin 
youth, busy with Hegel’s logic and gazing with amazement at the 
great Michelet. Of this youth it is rightly said on page 17: 

“to bring to light pure thought, to devote oneself to it — in this is the joy of youth, and 
all the bright images of the world of thought — truth, freedom, mankind, Man, 
etc. — illumine and inspire the youthful soul.” 

This youth then “throws aside” the “object” as well and “occupies 
himself” exclusively “with his thoughts”; 



a An allusion to Szeliga’s article “Eugen Sue: Die Geheimnisse von Paris. 
Kritik”. Cf. present edition, Vol. 4, p. 55. — Ed. 
b John 18 : 38. — Ed. 



6 * 




122 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



“he includes all that is not spiritual under the contemptuous name of external things, 
and if, all the same, he does cling to such external things as, for example, students’ 
customs, etc., it happens only when and because he discovers spirit in them, i.e., when 
they become symbols for him’’. (Who will not “discover” “Szeliga” here?) 

Virtuous Berlin youth! The beer-drinking ritual of the students’ 
association was for him only a “symbol” and only for the sake of the 
“symbol” was he after a drinking bout many a time found under the 
table, where he probably also wished to “discover spirit”! — How 
virtuous is this good youth, whom old Ewald, who wrote two volumes 
on the “virtuous youth”, 3 could have taken as a model, is seen also 
from the fact that it was “made known” to him (p. 15): “Father and 
mother should be abandoned, all natural authority should be 
considered broken.” For him, “the rational man, the family as a 
natural authority does not exist; there follows a renunciation of 
parents, brothers and sisters, etc.” — But they are all “re-born as 
spiritual, rational authority”, thanks to which the good youth 
reconciles obedience and fear of one’s parents with his speculating 
conscience, and everything remains as before. Likewise “it is said” 
(p. 15): “We ought to obey God rather than men.” b Indeed, the 
good youth reaches the highest peak of morality on page 16, where 
“it is said”: “One should obey one’s conscience rather than God.” 
This moral exultation raises him even above the “revengeful 
Eumenides” and even above the “anger of Poseidon” — he is afraid 
of nothing so much as his “conscience”. 

Having discovered that “the spirit is the essential” he no longer 
even fears the following perilous conclusions: 

“If, however, the spirit is recognised as the essential, nevertheless it makes a 
difference whether the spirit is poor or rich, and therefore” (!) “ one strives to become rich 
in spirit; the spirit wishes to expand, to establish its realm, a realm not of this world, 
which has just been overcome. In this way, the spirit strives to become all in all” c (what 
way is this?), “i.e., although I am spirit, nevertheless I am not perfect spirit and must” (?) 
“first seek the perfect spirit” (p. 17). 

“Nevertheless it makes a difference.” — “It”, what is this? What is 
the “It” that makes the difference? We shall very often come across 
this mysterious “It” in our holy man, and it will then turn out that it 
is the unique from the standpoint of substance, the beginning of 
“unique” logic, and as such the true identity of Hegel’s “being” and 
“nothing”. Hence, for everything that this “It” does, says or 



a Johann Ludwig Ewald, Der gute Jungling, gute Gatte und Vater, oder Mittel, um es zu 
werden. — Ed. 

b The Acts of the Apostles 5 : 29. — Ed. 
c 1 Corinthians 15:28. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



123 



performs, we shall lay the responsibility on our saint, whose relation 
to it is that of its creator. First of all, this “It”, as we have seen, makes 
a difference between poor and rich. And why? Because “the spirit is 
recognised as the essential”. Poor “It”, which without this recogni- 
tion would never have arrived at the difference between poor and 
rich! “And therefore one strives”, etc. “ One /” We have here the 
second impersonal person which, together with the “It”, is in 
Stirner’s service and must perform the heaviest menial work for him. 
How these two are accustomed to support each other is clearly seen 
here. Since “It” makes a difference whether the spirit is poor or rich, 
“one” (could anyone but Stirner’s faithful servant 3 have had this 
idea!) — “one, therefore, strives to become rich in spirit”. “It” gives the 
signal and immediately “one” joins in at the top of its voice. The 
division of labour is classically carried out. 

Since “one strives to become rich in spirit, the spirit wishes to 
expand, to establish its realm" , etc. “If however” a connection is 
present here “it still makes a difference” whether “one” wants to 
become “ rich in spirit ” or whether “ the spirit wants to establish its 
realm”. Up to now “the spirit" has not wanted anything, “the spirit" has 
not yet figured as a person — it was only a matter of the spirit of the 
“youth”, and not of “the spirit" as such, of the spirit as subject. But our 
holy writer now needs a spirit different from that of the youth, in 
order to place it in opposition to the latter as a foreign, and in the last 
resort, as a holy spirit. Conjuring trick No. 1. 

‘.‘In this way the spirit strives to become all in all”, a somewhat 
obscure statement, which is then explained as follows: 

“Although I am spirit, nevertheless I am not perfect spirit and must first seek the 
perfect spirit . J 

But if Saint Max is the “imperfect spirit”, “nevertheless it makes a 
difference” whether he has to “ perfect ” his spirit or seek “ the perfect 
spirit”. A few lines earlier he was in fact dealing only with the “poor" 
and “rich” spirit — a quantitative, profane distinction — and now 
there suddenly appears the “imperfect” and “ perfect ” spirit — a 
qualitative, mysterious distinction. The striving towards the deve- 
lopment of one’s own spirit can now be transformed into the hunt of 
the “imperfect spirit” for “ the perfect spirit”. The holy spirit 
wanders about like a ghost. Conjuring trick No. 2. 

The holy author continues: 

“But thereby” (i.e., by the transformation of the striving towards “perfection” 
of my spirit into the search for “the perfect spirit”) “I, who have only just found myself 



a An ironical allusion to F. Szeliga. See this volume, p. 149. — Ed. 




124 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



as spirit, at once lose myself again, in that I bow down before the perfect spirit, as a 
spirit which is not my own, but a spirit of the beyond, and I feel my emptiness ” (p. 18). 

This is nothing but a further development of conjuring trick 
No. 2. After the “perfect spirit” has been assumed as an existing being 
and opposed to the “imperfect spirit”, it becomes obvious that the 
“imperfect spirit”, the youth, painfully feels his “emptiness” to the 
depths of his soul. Let us go on! 

“True, it is all a matter of spirit, but is every spirit the right spirit? The right and 
true spirit is the ideal of the spirit, the ‘holy spirit’. It is not my or your spirit but 
precisely ” (!) — “an ideal spirit, a spirit of the beyond — ‘God’. ‘God is spirit’” (p. 18). 

Here the “perfect spirit” has been suddenly transformed into 
the “right” spirit, and immediately afterwards into the “right and 
true spirit”. The latter is more closely defined as the “ideal of the 
spirit, the holy spirit” and this is proved by the fact that it is “not my 
or your spirit but precisely, a spirit of the beyond, an ideal 
spirit — God”. The true spirit is the ideal of the spirit, “precisely” 
because it is ideall It is the holy spirit “precisely” because it is — God! 
What “virtuosity of thought”! We note also in passing that up to now 
nothing was said about “your” spirit. Conjuring trick No. 3. 

Thus, if I seek to train myself as a mathematician, or, as Saint Max 
puts it, to “perfect” myself as a mathematician, then I am seeking the 
“perfect” mathematician, i.e., the “right and true” mathematician, 
the “ideal” of the mathematician, the “holy” mathematician, who is 
distinct from me and you (although in my eyes you may be a perfect 
mathematician, just as for the Berlin youth his professor of 
philosophy is the perfect spirit); but a mathematician who is 
“precisely ideal, of the beyond”, the mathematician in the heavens, 
“God”. God is a mathematician. 

Saint Max arrives at all these great results because “it makes a 
difference whether the spirit is rich or poor”; i.e., in plain language, 
it makes a difference whether anyone is rich or poor in spirit, and 
because his “youth” has discovered this remarkable fact. 

On page 18 Saint Max continues: 

“ It divides the man from the youth that the former takes the world as it is”, etc. 

Consequently, we do not learn how the youth arrives at the point 
where he suddenly takes the world “as it is”, nor do we see our holy 
dialectician making the transition from youth to man, we merely 
learn that “It” has to perform this service and “ divide ” the youth 
from the man. But even this “It” by itself does not suffice to bring 
the cumbersome waggonload of unique thoughts into motion. For 



John 4 : 24.— Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



125 



after “/l” has “divided the man from the youth”, the man all the 
same relapses again into the youth, begins to occupy himself afresh 
“exclusively with the spirit” and does not get going until “one” 
hurries to his assistance with a change of horses. “Only when one has 
grown fond of oneself corporeally, etc.” (p. 18), “only then” 
everything goes forward smoothly again, the man discovers that he 
has a personal interest, and arrives at “the second self-discovery ” , in 
that he not only “finds himself as spirit”, like the youth, “and then at 
once loses himself again in the universal spirit”, but finds himself “as 
corporeal spirit” (p. 19). This “corporeal spirit” finally arrives at 
having an “interest not only in its own spirit” (like the youth), “but in 
total satisfaction, in the satisfaction of the whole fellow” (an interest 
in the satisfaction of the whole fellow!) — he arrives at the point 
where “he is pleased with himself exactly as he is”. Being a German, 
Stirner’s “man” arrives at everything very late. He could see, 
sauntering along the Paris boulevards or in London’s Regent Street, 
hundreds of “young men”, fops and dandies who have not yet found 
themselves as “corporeal spirits” and are nevertheless “pleased with 
themselves exactly as they are”, and whose main interest lies in the 
“satisfaction of the whole fellow!’ 

This second “self-discovery” fills our holy dialectician with such 
enthusiasm that he suddenly forgets his role and begins to speak not 
of the man, but of himself, and reveals that he himself, he the unique, 
is “the man”, and that “the man” = “the unique”. A new conjuring 
trick. 

“How I find myself” (it should read: “how the youth finds himself”) “behind the 
things, and indeed as spirit, so subsequently, too, I must find myself” (it should read: 
“the man must find himself”) “behind the thoughts, i.e., as their creator and owner. In 
the period of spirits, thoughts outgrew me” (the youth), “although they were the 
offspring of my brain; like delirious fantasies they floated around me and agitated me 
greatly, a dreadful power. The thoughts became themselves corporeal, they were 
spectres like God, the Emperor, the Pope, the Fatherland, etc.; by destroying their 
corporeality, I take them back into my own corporeality and announce : I alone am 
corporeal. And now I take the world as it is for me, as my world, as my property: I 
relate everything to myself.” 

Thus, the man, identified here with the “unique”, having first 
given thoughts corporeality, i.e., having transformed them into 
spectres, now destroys this corporeality again, by taking them back 
into his own body, which he thus makes into a body of spectres. The 
fact that he arrives at his own corporeality only through the negation 
of the spectres, shows the nature of this constructed corporeality of 
the man, which he has first to “announce” to “himself”, in order to 
believe in it. But what he “announces to himself” he does not even 
“announce” correctly. The fact that apart from his “unique” body 




126 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



there are not also to be found in his head all kinds of independent 
bodies, spermatozoa, he transforms into the “fable”*: I alone am 
corporeal. Another conjuring trick. 

Further, the man who, as a youth, stuffed his head with all kinds of 
nonsense about existing powers and relations such as the Emperor, 
the Fatherland, the State, etc., and knew them only as his own 
“delirious fantasies”, in the form of his conceptions — this man, 
according to Saint Max, actually destroys all these powers by getting out of 
his head his false opinion of them. On the contrary: now that he no 
longer looks at the world through the spectacles of his fantasy, he has 
to think of the practical interrelations of the world, to get to know 
them and to act in accordance with them. By destroying the fantastic 
corporeality which the world had for him, he finds its real 
corporeality outside his fantasy. With the disappearance of the 
spectral corporeality of the Emperor, what disappears for him is not 
the corporeality, but the spectral character of the Emperor, the 
actual power of whom he can now at last appreciate in all its scope. 
Conjuring trick No. 3 [a]. 

The youth as a man does not even react critically towards ideas 
which are valid also for others and are current as categories, but is 
critical only of those ideas that are the “mere offspring of his brain”, 
i.e., general concepts about existing conditions reproduced in his 
brain. Thus, for example, he does not even resolve the category 
“Fatherland”, but only his personal opinion of this category, after 
which the generally valid category still remains, and even in the 
sphere of “philosophical thought” the work is only just beginning. 
Fie wants, however, to make us believe that he has destroyed the 
category itself because he has destroyed his emotional personal 
relation to it — exactly as he has wanted to make us believe that he 
has destroyed the power of the Emperor by giving up his fantastic 
conception of the Emperor. Conjuring trick No. 4. 

“ And now,” continues Saint Max, “I take the world as it is for me, as my world, 
as my property.” 

He takes the world as it is for him, i.e., as he is compelled to take it, 
and thereby he has appropriated the world for himself, has made it his 
property — a mode of acquisition which, indeed, is not mentioned by 
any of the economists, but the method and success of which will be 
the more brilliantly disclosed in “the book”. Basically, however, he 
“takes” not the “world”, but only his “delirious fantasy” about the 
world as his own, and makes it his property. He takes the world as his 



a In German a play on words: Ich sage — I say, I announce and die Sage — 
fable, myth, saga. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



127 



conception of the world, and the world as his conception is his 
imagined property, the property of his .conception, his conception as 
property, his property as conception, his own peculiar conception, 
or his conception of property; and all this he expresses in the 
incomparable phrase: “I relate everything to myself.” 

After the man has recognised, as the saint himself admits, that the 
world was only populated by spectres, because the youth saw 
spectres, after the illusory world of the youth has disappeared for the 
man, the latter finds himself in a real world, independent of youthful 
fancies. 

And so, it should therefore read, I take the world as it is 
independently of myself, in the form in which it belongs to itself (“the 
man takes” — see page 18 — “the world as it is”, and not as he 
would like it to be), in the first place as my non-property (hitherto it 
was my property only as a spectre); I relate myself to everything and 
only to that extent do I relate everything to myself. 

“If I as spirit rejected the world with the deepest contempt for it, then I as 
proprietor reject the spectres or ideas into their emptiness. They no longer have 
power over me, just as no ‘earthly force’ has power over the spirit” (p. 20). 

We see here that the proprietor, Stirner’s man, at once enters 
into possession, sine beneficio deliberandi atque inventarii , a of the 
inheritance of the youth which, according to his own statement, 
consists only of “delirious fantasies” and “spectres”. He believes that 
in the process of changing from a child into a youth he had truly 
coped with the world of things, and in the process of changing from 
a youth into a man he had truly coped with the world of the spirit, 
that now, as a man, he has the whole world in his pocket and has 
nothing more to trouble him. If, according to the words of the youth 
which he repeats, no earthly force outside him has any power over 
the spirit, and hence the spirit is the supreme power on earth — and 
he, the man, has forced this omnipotent spirit into subjection to 
himself — is he not then completely omnipotent? He forgets that he 
has only destroyed the fantastic and spectral form assumed by the 
idea of “Fatherland”, etc., in the brain of the “youth”, but that he 
has still not touched these ideas, insofar as they express actual relations. 
Far from having become the master of ideas — he is only now 
capable of arriving at “ideas”. 

“Now, let us say in conclusion, it can be clearly seen” (p. 199) that 
the holy man has brought his interpretation of the different stages of 



a Without the advantage of deliberation and inventory — the right of deliberation 
and inventory is an old principle of the law of inheritance, which grants the heir time 
to decide whether he wants to accept or to reject a legacy. — Ed. 




128 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



life to the desired and predestined goal. He informs us of the result 
achieved in a thesis that is a spectral shade which we shall now 
confront with its lost body. 



Unique thesis, p. 20. 

“The child was realistic, in thrall to the 
things of this world, until little by little he 
succeeded in penetrating behind these very 
things. The youth was idealistic, inspired 
by thoughts, until he worked his way up 
to become a man, the egoistic man, who 
deals with things and thoughts as he 
pleases and puts his personal interest 
above everything. Finally, the old man? 
It will be time enough to speak of this 
when I become one.” 



Owner of the accompanying liberated 
shade. 

The child was actually in thrall to the 
world of his things, until little by little (a bor- 
rowed conjuring trick standing for de- 
velopment) he succeeded in leaving these 
very things behind him. The youth was 
fanciful and was made thoughtless by his 
enthusiasm, until he was brought down 
by the man, the egoistic burgher, with 
whom things and thoughts deal as they 
please, because his personal interest puts 
everything above him. Finally, the old 
man? — “Woman, what have I to do with 
thee?” a 



The entire history of “a man’s life” amounts, therefore, “let us 
say in conclusion”, to the following: 

1. Stirner regards the various stages of life only as “self-discov- 
eries” of the individual, and these “self-discoveries” are moreover 
always reduced to a definite relation of consciousness. Thus the 
variety of consciousness is here the life of the individual. The physical 
and social changes which take place in the individuals and produce 
an altered consciousness are, of course, of no concern to Stirner. In 
Stirner’s work, therefore, child, youth and man always find the world 
ready-made, just as they merely “find” “themselves”; absolutely 
nothing is done to ensure that there should be something which can 
in fact be found. But even the relation of consciousness is not correctly 
understood either, but only in its speculative distortion. Hence, too, 
all these figures have a philosophical attitude to the world — “the 
child is realistic ”, “the youth is idealistic ”, the man is the negative 
unity of the two, absolute negativity, as is evident from the 
above-quoted final proposition. Here the secret of “a man’s life” 
is revealed, here it becomes clear that the “child” was only a 
disguise of “realism”, the “youth” a disguise of “idealism”, the “man” 
of an attempted solution of this philosophical antithesis. This solution, 
this “absolute negativity” , is arrived at — it is now seen — only thanks 
to the man blindly taking on trust the illusions both of the child and 



John 2 : 4. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



129 



of the youth, believing thus to have overcome the world of things and 
the world of the spirit. 

2. Since Saint Max pays no attention to the physical and social 
“life” of the individual, and says nothing at all about “life”, he quite 
consistently abstracts from historical epochs, nationalities, classes, 
etc., or, which is the same thing, he inflates the consciousness 
predominant in the class nearest to him in his immediate environ- 
ment into the normal consciousness of “a man’s life”. In order to rise 
above this local and pedantic narrow-mindedness he has only to 
confront “his” youth with the first young clerk he encounters, a 
young English factory worker or young Yankee, not to mention the 
young Kirghiz-Kazakhs. 

3. Our saint’s enormous gullibility — the true spirit of his 
book — is not content with causing his youth to believe in his child, 
and his man to believe in his youth. The illusions which some 
“youths”, “men”, etc., have or claim to have about themselves, are 
without any examination accepted by Stirner himself and confused 
with the “ life ”, with the reality, of these highly ambiguous youths and 
men. 

4. The prototype of the entire structure of the stages of life has 
already been depicted in the third part of Hegel’s Encyclopddie a and 
“in various transformations” in other passages in Hegel as well. Saint 
Max, pursuing “his own” purposes, had, of course, to undertake 
certain “transformations” here also. Whereas Hegel, for example, is 
still to such an extent guided by the empirical world that he portrays 
the German burgher as the servant of the world around him, Stirner 
has to make him the master of this world, which he is not even in 
imagination. Similarly, Saint Max pretends that he does not speak of 
the old man for empirical reasons; he wishes to wait until he becomes 
one himself (here, therefore, “a man’s life” = his unique life). Hegel 
briskly sets about constructing the four stages of the human life 
because, in the real world, the negation is posited twice, i.e., as moon 
and as comet (cf. Hegel’s Naturphilosophie b ), and therefore the 
quaternity here takes the place of the trinity. Stirner finds his own 
uniqueness in making moon and comet coincide and so abolishes the 
unfortunate old man from “a man’s life”. The reason for this 
conjuring trick becomes evident as soon as we examine the 
construction of the unique history of man. 



a G. W. F. Hegel, Encyclopddie der philosophischen Wissenschaften im Grundrisse. 
C. Die Philosophic des Geistes. — Ed. 

b G. W. F. Hegel, Vorlesungen iiber die Naturphilosophie. — Ed. 




130 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



2. The Economy of the Old Testament 

We must here, for a moment, jump from the “Law” to the 
“Prophets”, since at this point already we reveal the secret of unique 
domestic economy in heaven and on earth. In the Old Testament, 
too — where the law, man, still is a school-master of the unique 
(Galatians 3:24) — the history of the kingdom of the unique follows 
a wise plan fixed from eternity. Everything has been foreseen 
and preordained in order that the unique could appear in the 
world, when the time had come 3 to redeem holy people from their 
holiness. 

The first book, “A Man’s Life”, is also called the “Book of 
Genesis”, because it contains in embryo the entire domestic economy 
of the unique, because it gives us a prototype of the whole 
subsequent development up to the moment when the time comes for 
the end of the world. The entire unique history revolves round 
three stages: child, youth and man, who return “in various 
transformations” and in ever widening circles until, finally, the 
entire history of the world of things and the world of the spirit is 
reduced to “child, youth and man”. Everywhere we shall find 
nothing but disguised “child, youth and man”, just as we already 
discovered in them three disguised categories. 

We spoke above of the German philosophical conception of 
history. Here, in Saint Max, we find a brilliant example of it. The 
speculative idea, the abstract conception, is made the driving force of 
history, and history is thereby turned into the mere history of 
philosophy. But even the latter is not conceived as, according to 
existing sources, it actually took place — not to mention how it 
evolved under the influence of real historical relations — but as it was 
understood and described by recent German philosophers, in 
particular Hegel and Feuerbach. And from these descriptions again 
only that was selected which could be adapted to the given end, and 
which came into the hands of our saint by tradition. Thus, history 
becomes a mere history of illusory ideas, a history of spirits and 
ghosts, while the real, empirical history that forms the basis of this 
ghostly history is only utilised to provide bodies for these ghosts; 
from it are borrowed the names required to clothe these ghosts 
with the appearance of reality. In making this experiment our 
saint frequently forgets his role and writes an undisguised ghost- 
story. 

In his case we find this method of making history in its most naive, 
most classic simplicity. Three simple categories — realism, idealism 



Galatians 4 : 4. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



131 



and absolute negativity (here named “egoism”) as the unity of the 
two— which we have already encountered in the shape of the child, 
youth and man, are made the basis of all history and are embellished 
with various historical signboards; together with their modest suite 
of auxiliary categories they form the content of all the allegedly 
historical phases which are trotted out. Saint Max once again reveals 
here his boundless faith by pushing to greater extremes than any of 
his predecessors faith in the speculative content of history dished up 
by German philosophers. In this solemn and tedious construction of 
history, therefore, all that matters is to find a pompous series 
of resounding names for three categories that are so hackneyed 
that they no longer dare to show themselves publicly under their 
own names. Our anointed author could perfectly well have 
passed from the “man” (p. 20) immediately to the “ego” (p. 201) or 
better still to the “unique” (p. 485); but that would have been 
too simple. Moreover, the strong competition among the Ger- 
man speculative philosophers makes it the duty of each new com- 
petitor to offer an ear-splitting historical advertisement for his 
commodity. 

“The force of true development”, to use Dottore Graziano’s words, 
“proceeds most forcibly” in the following “transformations”: 

Basis: 

I. Realism. 

II. Idealism. 

III. The negative unity of the two. “One” (p. 485), 

First nomenclature: 

I. Child, dependent on things (realism). 

II. Youth, dependent on ideas (idealism). 

III. Man — (as the negative unity) 

expressed positively: 

the owner of ideas and things 
expressed negatively: 

free from ideas and things 
Second , historical nomenclature: 

I. Negro (realism, child). 

II. Mongol (idealism, youth). 

III. Caucasian (negative unity of realism and idealism, man). 
Third, most general nomenclature: 

I. Realistic egoist (egoist in the ordinary sense) — child, Negro. 

II. Idealist egoist (devotee) — youth, Mongol. 

III. True egoist (the unique) — man, Caucasian. 

Fourth, historical nomenclature. Repetition of the preceding stages 
within the category of the Caucasian. 



► (egoism) 




132 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



I. The Ancients. Negroid Caucasians — childish men — pagans — 
dependent on things — realists — the world. 

Transition (child penetrating behind the “things of this world”): 
Sophists, Sceptics, etc. 

II. The Modems. Mongoloid Caucasians — youthful men — Chris- 
tians — dependent on ideas — idealists — spirit. 

1 . Pure history of spirits, 3 Christianity as spirit. “The spirit.” 

2. Impure history of spirits. Spirit in relation to others. “The 
Possessed”. 

A. Purely impure history of spirits. 

a) The apparition, the ghost, the spirit in the Negroid 
state, as thing-like spirit and spiritual thing — objec- 
tive being for the Christian, spirit as child. 

b) The whimsy, the fixed idea, the spirit in the Mongolian 
condition, as spiritual in the spirit, determination 
in consciousness, conceptual being in the Christian — 
spirit as youth. 

B. Impurely impure (historical) history of spirits. 

a) Catholicism — Middle Ages (the Negro, child, real- 

ism, etc.). 

b) Protestantism — modern times in modern times — 
(Mongol, youth, idealism, etc.). 

Within Protestantism it is possible to make further 
subdivisions, for example: 

a) English philosophy — realism, child, Negro. 

[3) German philosophy — idealism, youth, Mongol. 

3. The Hierarchy — negative unity of the two within the Mon- 
goloid-Caucasian point of view. Such unity appears where 
historical relations are changed into actually existing rela- 
tions or where opposites are presented as existing side 
by side. Here, therefore, we have two co-existing stages: 

A. The “ uneducated ,b (evil ones, bourgeois, egoists in the 
ordinary sense) = Negroes, children, Catholics, realists, 
etc. 

B. The “ educated ’ (good ones, citoyens, devotees, priests, 
etc.) = Mongols, youths, Protestants, idealists. 



a In the German original Geistergeschichte, that is, “ghost-story” ( Geister — ghosts 
or spirits; Geschichte — story or history). In this volume, however, it has usually been 
rendered as “history of spirits” to bring out more clearly the connection with the 
words that precede or follow it. — Ed. 

Here and later the authors ironically use Berlin dialect words for uneducated 
( Unjebildete ) and educated (Jebildete ). — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



133 



These two stages exist side by side and hence it follows 
“easily” that the “educated” rule over the “uneducated” — this 
is the hierarchy. In the further course of historical development 
there arises then 

the non-Hegelian from the “uneducated”, 
the Hegelian from the “educated”,* 
from which it follows that the Hegelians rule over the non- 
Hegelians. In this way Stirner converts the speculative notion 
of the domination of the speculative idea in history into the 
notion of the domination of the speculative philosophers 
themselves. The view of history hitherto held by him — the 
domination of the idea — becomes in the hierarchy a relation 
actually existing at present; it becomes the world domination of 
ideologists. This shows how deeply Stirner has plunged into 
speculation. This domination of the speculative philosophers 
and ideologists is finally developing, “for the time has come” 
for it, into the following, concluding nomenclature: 

a) Political liberalism, dependent on things, independent of 
persons — realism, child, Negro, the ancient, apparition, 
Catholicism, the “uneducated”, masterless. 

b) Social liberalism, independent of things, dependent on the 
spirit, without object — idealism, youth, Mongol, the mod- 
ern, whimsy, Protestantism, the “educated”, propertyless. 

c) Humane liberalism, masterless and propertyless, that is 
godless, for God is simultaneously the supreme master and 
the supreme possession, hierarchy — negative unity in the 
sphere of liberalism and, as such, domination over the 
world of things and thoughts; at the same time the perfect 
egoist in the abolition of egoism — the perfect hierarchy. At 
the same time, it forms the 

Transition (youth penetrating behind the world of thoughts) to 

III. the ‘ "ego” — i.e., the perfect Christian, the perfect man, the 
Caucasian Caucasian and true egoist, who — -just as the 
Christian became spirit through the supersession of the 
ancient world — becomes a corporeal being 3 through the 
dissolution of the realm of spirits, by entering, sine beneficio 
deliberandi et inventarii, into the inheritance of idealism, the 

* “The shaman and the speculative philosopher denote the lowest and the highest 
point in the scale of the inner man, the Mongol” (p. 453). 



a In German a pun on der Leibhaftige, which can mean corporeal being or the 
devil. — Ed. 




134 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



youth, the Mongol, the modern, the Christian, the possessed, 
the whimsical, the Protestant, the “educated”, the Hegelian 
and the humane liberal. 

NB. 1. “At times” Feuerbachian and other categories, such as 
reason, the heart, etc., may be also “included episodically”, should a 
suitable occasion arise, to heighten the colour of the picture and to 
produce new effects. It goes without saying that these, too, are only 
new disguises of the ever present idealism and realism. 

2. The very pious Saint Max, Jacques le bonhomme, has nothing 
real and mundane to say about real mundane history, except that 
under the name of “nature”, the “world of things”, the “world of 
the child”, etc., he always opposes it to consciousness, as an object of 
speculation of the latter, as a world which, in spite of its continual 
annihilation, continues to exist in a mystical darkness, in order to 
reappear on every convenient occasion — probably because children 
and Negroes continue to exist, and hence also their world, the 
so-called world of things, “easily” continues to exist. Concerning 
such historical and non-historical constructions, good old Hegel 
wrote with regard to Schelling — the model for all constructors — that 
one can say the following in this context: 

“It is no more difficult to handle the instrument of this monotonous formalism 
than a painter’s palette which has only two colours, say black” (realistic, childish, 
Negroid, etc.) “and yellow” 3 (idealist, youthful, Mongolian, etc.), “in order to use the 
former to paint a surface when something historical” (the “world of things”) “is 
required, and the latter when a landscape” (“heaven”, spirit, holiness, etc.) “is 
needed” ( Phanomenologie , p. 39). 

“Ordinary consciousness” has even more pointedly ridiculed 
constructions of this kind in the following song: 

The master sent out John 

And told him to cut the hay; 

But John did not cut the hay 
Nor did he come back home. 

Then the master sent out the dog 
And told him to bite John; 

But the dog did not bite John, 

John did not cut the hay 

And they did not come back home. 

Then the master sent out the stick 
And told it to beat the dog; 

But the stick did not beat the dog, 

The dog did not bite John, 

John did not cut the hay 

And they did not come back home. 



a Hegel mentions red and green as examples. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



135 



Then the master sent out fire 
And told it to burn the stick; 

But the fire did not burn the stick, 

The stick did not beat the dog, 

The dog did not bite John, 

John did not cut the hay 

And they did not come back home. 

Then the master sent out water 
And told it to put out the fire; 

But the water did not put out the fire, 
The fire did not burn the stick. 

The stick did not beat the dog, 

The dog did not bite John, 

John did not cut the hay 

And they did not come back home. 

Then the master sent out the ox 
And told it to drink the water; 

But the ox did not drink the water, 

The water did not put out the fire, 

The fire did not burn the stick. 

The stick did not beat the dog, 

The dog did not bite John, 

John did not cut the hay 

And they did not come back home. 

Then the master sent out the butcher 
And told him to slaughter the ox; 

But the butcher did not slaughter the ox, 
The ox did not drink the water, 

The water did not put out the fire, 

The fire did not burn the stick, 

The stick did not beat the dog, 

The dog did not bite John, 

John did not cut the hay 

And they did not come back home. 

Then the master sent out the hangman 
And told him to hang the butcher; 

The hangman did hang the butcher, 

The butcher slaughtered the ox, 

The ox drank the water , 

The water put out the fire. 

The fire burnt the stick. 

The stick beat the dog. 

The dog bit John, 

John cut the hay. 

And they all came back home. 3 



A German nursery rhyme. — Ed. 




136 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



We shall now see with what “virtuosity of thought” and with what 
schoolboy ish material Jacques le bonhomme elaborates on this 
scheme. 



3. The Ancients 

Properly speaking we ought to begin here with the Negroes; but 
Saint Max, who undoubtedly sits in the “Council of Guardians”, in 
his unfathomable wisdom introduces the Negroes only later, and 
even then “without any claim to thoroughness and authenticity”. If, 
therefore, we make Greek philosophy precede the Negro era, i.e., 
the campaigns of Sesostris and Napoleon’s expedition to Egypt, 48 it is 
because we are confident that our holy author has arranged 
everything wisely. 

“Let us, therefore, take a look at the activities which tempt” 
Stirner’s ancients. 

‘“For the ancients, the world was a truth,’ says Feuerbach; but he forgets to make the 
important addition: a truth, the untruth of which they sought to penetrateand, finally, 
did indeed penetrate” (p. 22). 

“For the ancients”, their “world” (not the world) “was a 
truth” — whereby, of course, no truth about the ancient world is 
stated, but only that the ancients did not have a Christian attitude to 
their world. As soon as untruth penetrated their world (i.e., as soon as 
this world itself disintegrated in consequence of practical con- 
flicts — and to demonstrate this materialistic development empirically 
would be the only thing of interest), the ancient philosophers sought 
to penetrate the world of truth or the truth of their world and then, 
of course, they found that it had become untrue. Their very search 
was itself a symptom of the internal collapse of this world. Jacques le 
bonhomme transforms the idealist symptom into the material cause 
of the collapse and, as a German church father, makes antiquity itself 
seek its own negation, Christianity. For him this position of antiquity 
is inevitable because the ancients are “ children ’ who seek to 
penetrate the “world of things”. “And that is fairly easy too”: by 
transforming the ancient world into the later consciousness regard- 
ing the ancient world, Jacques le bonhomme can, of course, jump 
in a single leap from the materialistic ancient world to the world of 
religion, to Christianity. Now the “word of God” immediately 
emerges in opposition to the real world of antiquity; the Christian 
conceived as the modern sceptic emerges in opposition to the ancient 
man conceived as philosopher. His Christian “is never convinced of 
the vanity of the word of God” and, in consequence of this lack of 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



137 



conviction, he “believes” “in its eternal and invincible truth” (p. 22). 
Just as Stirner’s ancient is ancient because he is a non-Christian, not 
yet a Christian or a hidden Christian, so his primitive Christian is a 
Christian because he is a non-atheist, not yet an atheist or a hidden 
atheist. Stirner, therefore, causes Christianity to be negated by the 
ancients and modern atheism by the primitive Christians, instead of 
the reverse. Jacques le bonhomme, like all other speculative 
philosophers, seizes everything by its philosophical tail. A few more 
examples of this child-like gullibility immediately follow. 

“The Christian must consider himself a ‘stranger on the earth’ (Epistle to the 
Hebrews 11 : 13)” (p. 23). 

On the contrary, the strangers on earth (arising from extremely 
natural causes e.g., the colossal concentration of wealth in the whole 
Roman world, etc., etc.) had to consider themselves Christians. It was 
not their Christianity that made them vagrants, but their vagrancy 
that made them Christians. 

On the same page the holy father jumps straight from Sophocles’ 
Antigone and the sacredness of the burial ceremonial connected with 
it to the Gospel of Matthew, 8:22 (let the dead bury their dead), while 
Hegel, at any rate in the Phanomenologie, gradually passes from 
the Antigone, etc., to the Romans. With equal right Saint Max 
could have passed at once to the Middle Ages and, together with 
Hegel, have advanced this biblical statement against the Crusaders or 
even, in order to be quite original, have contrasted the burial of 
Polynices by Antigone with the transfer of the ashes of Napoleon 
from St. Helena to Paris. It is stated further: 

“In Christianity the inviolable truth of family ties” (which on page 22 is noted as 
one of the “truths” of the ancients) “is depicted as an untruth which should be got rid 
of as quickly as possible (Mark, 10 : 29) and so in everything” (p. 23). 

This proposition, in which reality is again turned upside-down, 
should be put the right way up as follows: the actual untruth of 
family ties (concerning which, inter alia, the still existing documents 
of pre-Christian Roman legislation should be examined) is depicted 
in Christianity as an inviolable truth, “and so in everything”. 

From these examples, therefore, it is superabundantly evident 
how Jacques le bonhomme, who strives to “get rid as quickly as 
possible” of empirical history, stands facts on their heads, causes 
material history to be produced by ideal history, “and so in 
everything”. At the outset we learn only the alleged attitude of the 
ancients to their world; as dogmatists they are put in opposition to 
the ancient world, their own world, instead of appearing as its 
creators; it is a question only of the relation of consciousness to the 




138 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



object, to truth; it is a question, therefore, only of the philosophical 
relation of the ancients to their world — ancient history is replaced by 
the history of ancient philosophy, and this only in the form in which 
Saint Max imagines it according to Hegel and Feuerbach. 

Thus the history of Greece, from the time of Pericles inclusively, is 
reduced to a struggle of abstractions: reason, spirit, heart, worldli- 
ness, etc. These are the Greek parties. In this ghostly world, which is 
presented as the Greek world, allegorical persons such as Madame 
Purity of Heart “machinate” and mythical figures like Pilate (who 
must never be missing where there are children) find a place quite 
seriously side by side with Timon of Phlius. 

After presenting us with some astounding revelations about the 
Sophists and Socrates, Saint Max immediately jumps to the Sceptics. 
He discovers that they completed the work which Socrates began. 
Hence the positive philosophy of the Greeks that followed im- 
mediately after the Sophists and Socrates, especially Aristotle’s 
encyclopaedic learning, does not exist at all for Jacques le 
bonhomme. He strives “to get rid as quickly as possible” of the past 
and hurries to the transition to the “moderns”, finding this 
transition in the Sceptics, Stoics and Epicureans. Let us see what our 
holy father has to reveal about them. 

“The Stoics wish to realise the ideal of the wise man ... the man who knows how to 
live ... they find this ideal in contempt for the world, in a life without living 
development [...] without friendly intercourse with the world, i.e., in a life of isolation 
[...] not in a life in common with others; the Stoic alone lives, for him everything else is 
dead. The Epicureans, on the other hand, demand an active life” (p. 30). 

We refer Jacques le bonhomme — the man who wants to realise 
himself and who knows how to live — to, inter alia, Diogenes Laertius: 
there he will discover that the wise man, the sophos, is nothing but the 
idealised Stoic, not the Stoic the realised wise man; he will discover 
that the sophos is by no means only a Stoic but is met with just as much 
among the Epicureans, the Neo-academists and the Sceptics. 
Incidentally, the sophos is the first form in which the Greek philosophos 
confronts us; he appears mythologically in the seven wise men, in 
practice in Socrates, and as an ideal among the Stoics, Epicureans, 
Neo-academists 49 and Sceptics. Each of these schools, of course, has 
its own ffotpog , a just as Saint Bruno has his own “unique sex”. Indeed, 
Saint Max can find “le sage ” again in the eighteenth century in the 
philosophy of Enlightenment, and even in Jean Paul in the shape of 
the “wise men” like Emanuel, b etc. The Stoical wise man by no means 



a Wise man. — Ed. 

b Jean Paul, Hesperus oder 45 Hundsposttage . — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



139 



has in mind “life without living development”, but an absolutely active 
life, as is evident even from his concept of nature, which is 
Heraclitean, dynamic, developing and living, while for the 
Epicureans the principle of the concept of nature is the mors 
immortalise as Lucretius says, the atom, and, in opposition to 
Aristotle’s divine energy, divine leisure is put forward as the ideal of 
life instead of “active life”. 

“The ethics of the Stoics (their only science, for they were unable to say anything 
about the spirit except what its relation to the world should be; and about 
nature — physics — they could say only that the wise man has to assert himself against it) 
is not a doctrine of the spirit, but merely a doctrine of rejection of the world and of 
self-assertion against the world” (p. 31). 

The Stoics were able to “say about nature” that physics is one of 
the most important sciences for the philosopher and consequently 
they even went to the trouble of further developing the physics of 
Heraclitus; they were “further able to say” that the wpa , masculine 
beauty, is the highest that the individual could represent, and 
glorified life in tune with nature, although they fell into contradic- 
tions in so doing. According to the Stoics, philosophy is divided into 
three doctrines: “physics, ethics, logic”. 

“They compare philosophy to the animal and to the egg, logic — to the bones and 
sinews of the animal, and to the outer shell of the egg, ethics — to the flesh of the 
animal and to the albumen of the egg, and physics — to the soul of the animal and to the 
yolk of the egg” (Diogenes Laertius, Zeno). 

From this alone it is evident how little true it is to say that “ethics is 
the only science of the Stoics”. It should be added also that, apart 
from Aristotle, they were the chief founders of formal logic and 
systematics in general. 

That the “Stoics were unable to say anything about the spirit” is so 
little true that even seeing spirits originated from them, on account of 
which Epicurus opposes them, as an Enlightener, and ridicules them 
as “old women”, b while precisely the Neo-Platonists borrowed part 
of their tales about spirits from the Stoics. This spirit-seeing of the 
Stoics arises, on the one hand, from the impossibility of achieving a 
dynamic concept of nature without the material furnished by 
empirical natural science, and, on the other hand, from their effort 
to interpret the ancient Greek world and even religion in a 
speculative manner and make them analogous to the thinking spirit. 

The “ethics of the Stoics” is so much a “doctrine of world rejection 
and of self-assertion against the world” that, for example, it was 



a Immortal death. Lucretius, De rerum natura libri sex. Book 3, Verse 882. — Ed. 
b See present edition, Vol. 1, p. 43. — Ed. 




140 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



counted a Stoical virtue to “have a sound fatherland, a worthy 
friend”, that “the beautiful alone” is declared to be “the good”, and 
that the Stoical wise man is allowed to mingle with the world in every 
way, for example, to commit incest, etc., etc. The Stoical wise man is 
to such an extent caught up “in a life of isolation and not in a life in 
common with others” that it is said of him in Zeno: 

“Let not the wise man wonder at anything that seems wonderful — but neither will 
the worthy man live in solitude, for he is social by nature and active in practice ” 
(Diogenes Laertius, Book VII, 1). 

Incidentally, it would be asking too much to demand that, for the 
sake of refuting this schoolboyish wisdom of Jacques le bonhomme, 
one should set forth the very complicated and contradictory ethics of 
the Stoics. 

In connection with the Stoics, Jacques le bonhomme has to note the 
existence of the Romans also (p. 31), of whom, of course, he is unable 
to say anything, since they have no philosophy. The only thing we 
hear of them is that Horace (!) “did not go beyond the Stoics’ worldly 
wisdom” (p. 32). Integer vitae, scelerisque purus / a 

In connection with the Stoics, Democritus is also mentioned in the 
following way: a muddled passage of Diogenes Laertius ( Democritus , 
Book IX, 7, 45), which in addition has been inaccurately translated, is 
copied out from some textbook, and made the basis for a lengthy 
diatribe about Democritus. This diatribe has the distinguishing 
feature of being in direct contradiction to its basis, i.e., to the 
above-mentioned muddled and inaccurately translated passage, and 
converts “peace of mind” (Stirner’s translation of evJ'dufiia. , in Low 
German Wellmuth ) into “rejection of the world”. The fact is that 
Stirner imagines that Democritus was a Stoic, and indeed of the sort 
that the unique and the ordinary schoolboyish consciousness 
conceive a Stoic to be. Stirner thinks that “his whole activity amounts 
to an endeavour to detach himself from the world”, “hence to a 
rejection of the world”, and that in the person of Democritus he can 
refute the Stoics. That the eventful life of Democritus, who had 
wandered through the world a great deal, flagrantly contradicts this 
notion of Saint Max’s; that the real source from which to learn about 
the philosophy of Democritus is Aristotle and not a couple of 
anecdotes from Diogenes Laertius; that Democritus, far from 
rejecting the world, was, on the contrary, an empirical natural 
scientist and the first encyclopaedic mind among the Greeks; that his 
almost unknown ethics was limited to a few remarks which he is 



a He of life without flaw, pure from sin. Horace, The Odes, Book 1 — Ode XXII. 
Verse 1. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



141 



alleged to have made when he was an old, much-travelled man; that 
his writings on natural science can be called philosophy only per 
abusum , a because for him, in contrast to Epicurus, the atom was only 
a physical hypothesis, an expedient for explaining facts, just as it is in 
the proportional combinations of modern chemistry (Dalton and 
others) — all this does not suit the purpose of Jacques le bonhomme. 
Democritus must be understood in the “unique” fashion, Demo- 
critus speaks of euthymia, hence of peace of mind, hence of 
withdrawal into oneself, hence of rejection of the world. Democritus 
is a Stoic, and he differs from the Indian fakir mumbling “Brahma” 
(the word should have been “Om”), 50 only as the comparative differs 
from the superlative, i.e., “only in degree 

Of the Epicureans our friend knows exactly as much as he does of 
the Stoics, viz., the unavoidable schoolboy’s minimum. He contrasts 
the Epicurean “hedone” b with the “ataraxia” c of the Stoics and 
Sceptics, not knowing that this “ataraxia” is also to be found in 
Epicurus and, moreover, as something placed higher than the 
“hedone” — in consequence of which his whole contrast falls to the 
ground. He tells us that the Epicureans “teach only a different attitude 
to the world” from that of the Stoics; but let him show us the 
(non-Stoic) philosopher of “ancient or modern times” who does not 
do “only” the same. Finally, Saint Max enriches us with a new dictum 
of the Epicureans: “the world must be deceived, for it is my enemy”. 
Hitherto it was only known that the Epicureans made statements in 
the sense that the world must be disillusioned, and especially freed 
from fear of gods, for the world is my friend. 

To give our saint some indication of the real base on which the 
philosophy of Epicurus rests, it is sufficient to mention that the idea 
that the state rests on the mutual agreement of people, on a contrat 
social (au\>-&fxrj d ), is found for the first time in Epicurus. 

The extent to which Saint Max’s disclosures about the Sceptics 
follow the same line is already evident from the fact that he considers 
their philosophy more radical than that of Epicurus. The Sceptics 
reduced the theoretical relation of people to things to appearance, 
and in practice they left everything as of old, being guided by this 
appearance just as much as others are guided by actuality; they 
merely gave it another name. Epicurus, on the other hand, was the 
true radical Enlightener of antiquity; he openly attacked the ancient 
religion, and it was from him, too, that the atheism of the Romans, 

a By abuse, i. e., improperly, wrongly. — Ed. 
b Pleasure. — Ed. 

L Equanimity, imperturbability, intrepidity. — Ed. 
d Contract (see present edition, Vol. 1, pp. 409-10). — Ed. 




142 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



insofar as it existed, was derived. For this reason, too, Lucretius 
praised Epicurus as the hero who was the first to overthrow the gods 
and trample religion underfoot; for this reason among all church 
fathers, from Plutarch to Luther, Epicurus has always had the 
reputation of being the atheist philosopher par excellence , and was 
called a swine; for which reason, too, Clement of Alexandria says 
that when Paul takes up arms against philosophy he has in mind 
Epicurean philosophy alone. ( Stromatum , Book I [chap. XI], p. 295, 
Cologne edition, 1688. a ) Hence we see how “cunning, perfidious” 
and “clever” was the attitude of this open atheist to the world in 
directly attacking its religion, while the Stoics adapted the ancient 
religion in their own speculative fashion, and the Sceptics used their 
concept of “appearance” as the excuse for being able to accompany 
all their judgments with a reservatio mentalis. 

Thus, according to Stirner, the Stoics finally arrive at “contempt 
for the world” (p. 30), the Epicureans at “the same worldly wisdom 
as the Stoics” (p. 32), and the Sceptics at the point where they “let the 
world alone and do not worry about it at all”. Hence, according to 
Stirner, all three end in an attitude of indifference to the world, of 
“contempt for the world” (p. 485). Long before him, Hegel 
expressed it in this way: Stoicism, Scepticism, Epicureanism “aimed 
at making the mind indifferent towards everything that actuality has 
to offer” ( Philosophie der Geschichte, b p. 327). 

“The ancients,” writes Saint Max, summing up his criticism of the ancient world of 
ideas, “it is true, had ideas, but they did not know the idea ” (p. 30). In this connection, 
“one should recall what was said earlier about our childhood ideas” (ibid.). 

The history of ancient philosophy has to conform to Stirner’s 
design. In order that the Greeks should retain their role of children, 
Aristotle ought not to have lived and his thought in and for itself 
(t ) vo7jatC xafLaoTTjv), his self-thinking reason (aoxov Vos To vovO 

and his self-thinking intellect (t), vorjtKC vot) aewc) should never 
have occurred; and in general his Metaphysics and the third book of 
his Psychology c ought not to have existed. 

With just as much right as Saint Max here recalls “what was said 
earlier about our childhood”, when he discussed “our childhood” 
he could have said: let the reader look up what will be said below 
about the ancients and the Negroes and will not be said about 
Aristotle. 



a See present edition, Vol. 1, p. 488. — Ed. 

b G.W.F. Hegel, Vorlesungen iiber die Philosophie der Geschichte. — Ed. 
c Aristoteles, De anima. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



143 



In order to appreciate the true meaning of the last ancient 
philosophies during the dissolution of the ancient world, Jacques le 
bonhomme had only to look at the real situation in life of their 
adherents under the world dominion of Rome. He could have 
found, inter alia, in Lucian a detailed description of how the people 
regarded them as public buffoons, and how the Roman capitalists, 
proconsuls, etc., hired them as court jesters for their entertainment, 
so that after squabbling at the table with slaves for a few bones and a 
crust of bread and after being given a special sour wine, they would 
amuse the master of the house and his guests with delightful words 
like “ataraxia”, “aphasia”, 3 “hedone”, etc.* 

Incidentally, if our good man wanted to make the history of 
ancient philosophy into a history of antiquity, then as a matter of 
course he ought to have merged the Stoics, Epicureans and Sceptics 
in the Neo-Plat onists, whose philosophy is nothing but a fantastic 
combination of the Stoic, Epicurean and Sceptical doctrine with the 
content of the philosophy of Plato and Aristotle. Instead of that, he 
merges these doctrines directly in Christianity.** 

It is not “Stirner” that has left Greek philosophy “behind him”, 
but Greek philosophy that has “Stirner” behind it (cf. Wigand, 
p. 186 b ). Instead of telling us how “antiquity” arrives at a world of 
things and “copes” with it, this ignorant school-master causes 
antiquity blissfully to vanish by means of a quotation from Timon; 
whereby antiquity the more naturally “arrives at its final goal” since, 
according to Saint Max, the ancients “found themselves placed by 
nature” in the ancient “communality”, which, “let us say in 
conclusion”, “can be understood” the more easily because this 
communality, the family, etc., are dubbed “the so-called natural ties” 
(p. 33). By means of nature the ancient “world of things” is created, 
and by means of Timon and Pilate (p. 32) it is destroyed. Instead of 
describing the “world of things” which provides the material basis of 

* [The following passage is crossed out in the manuscript:] ... just as after the 
Revolution the French aristocrats became the dancing instructors of the whole of 
Europe, and the English lords will soon find their true place in the civilised world as 
stable-hands and kennel-men. 

** [The following passage is crossed out in the manuscript:] On the contrary, 
Stirner should have shown us that Hellenism even after its disintegration still 
continued to exist for a long time; that next to it the Romans gained world 
domination, what they really did in the world, how the Roman world developed and 
declined, and finally how the Hellenic and Roman world perished, spiritually in 
Christianity and materially in the migration of the peoples. 



a Refusal to express any definite opinion. — Ed. 
b Max Stirner, “Recensenten Stirners”. — Ed. 




144 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



Christianity, he causes this “world of things” to be annihilated in the 
world of the spirit, in Christianity. 

The German philosophers are accustomed to counterpose antiqui- 
ty, as the epoch of realism, to Christianity and modern times, as the 
epoch of idealism, whereas the French and English economists, 
historians and scientists are accustomed to regard antiquity as the 
period of idealism in contrast to the materialism and empiricism of 
modern times. In the same way antiquity can be considered to be 
idealistic insofar as in history the ancients represent the “ citoyen ”, the 
idealist politician, while in the final analysis the moderns turn into 
the “bourgeois”, the realist ami du commerce a — or again it can be 
considered to be realistic, because for the ancients the communality 
was a “truth”, whereas for the moderns it is an idealist “lie”. All 
these abstract counterposings and historical constructions are of very 
little use. 

The “unique thing” we learn from this whole portrayal of the 
ancients is that, whereas Stirner “knows” very few “things” about 
the ancient world, he has all the “better seen through” them (cf. 
Wigand, p. 191). 

Stirner is truly that same “man child” of whom it is prophesied in 
the Revelation of St. John, 12:5, that he “was to rule all nations with 
a rod of iron”. We have seen how he sets about the unfortunate 
heathen with the iron rod of his ignorance. The “moderns” will fare 
no better. 



4. The Moderns 

“Therefore if any man be in Christ, he is a new creature; old things are passed 
away; behold, all things are become new” (2 Corinthians 5:17) (p. 33). 

By means of this biblical saying the ancient world has now indeed 
“passed away” or, as Saint Max really wanted to say, “all gone”, b and 
with one leap c we have jumped over to the new, Christian, youthful, 
Mongoloid “world of the spirit”. We shall see that this, too, will have 
“all gone” in a very short space of time. 

“Whereas it was stated above ‘for the ancients, the world was a truth’, we must say 
here ‘for the moderns the spirit was a truth', but in neither case should we forget the 
important addition; a truth, the untruth of which they sought to penetrate and, 
finally, did indeed penetrate’” (p. 33). 



a An expression of Fourier (see Ch. Fourier, Des trois unites extemes). — Ed. 
b Here the authors ironically use the Berlin dialect words alle jeworden. — Ed. 

In German a pun on the word Satz, which means a leap, a jump and also a 
sentence, a proposition. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



145 



While we do not wish to devise any Stirner-like constructions, “we 
must say here”: for the moderns truth was a spirit, namely the holy 
spirit. Jacques le bonhomme again takes the moderns not in their 
actual historical connection with the “world of things” — which, 
despite being “all gone”, nevertheless continues to exist — but in their 
theoretical, and indeed religious, attitude. For him the history of the 
Middle Ages and modern times again exists only as the history of 
religion and philosophy; he devoutly believes all the illusions of these 
epochs and the philosophical illusions about these illusions. Thus, 
having given the history of the moderns the same turn as he gave 
that of the ancients, Saint Max can then easily “demonstrate” in it a 
“similar course to that taken by antiquity”, and pass from the 
Christian religion to modern German philosophy as rapidly as he 
passed from ancient philosophy to the Christian religion. On page 37 
he himself gives a characterisation of his historical illusions, by 
making the discovery that “the ancients have nothing to offer but 
worldly wisdom ” and that “the moderns have never gone, and do not 
go, beyond theology ”, and he solemnly asks: “What did the moderns 
seek to penetrate?” The ancients and moderns alike do nothing else 
in history but “seek to penetrate something” — the ancients try to 
find out what is behind the world of things, the moderns behind the 
world of the spirit. In the end the ancients are left “without a world” 
and the moderns “without a spirit”; the ancients wanted to become 
idealists, the moderns to become realists (p. 485), but both of them 
were only occupied with the divine (p. 488) — “history up to now” is 
only the “history of the spiritual man” (what faith!) (p. 442) — in 
short we have again the child and the youth, the Negro and the 
Mongol, and all the rest of the terminology of the “various 
transformations” . 

At the same time we see a faithful imitation of the speculative 
manner, by which children beget their father, and what is earlier is 
brought about by what is later. From the very outset Christians must 
“seek to penetrate the untruthfulness of their truth”, they must 
immediately be hidden atheists and critics, as was already indicated 
concerning the ancients. But not satisfied with this, Saint Max gives 
one more brilliant example of his “virtuosity in” (speculative) 
“thought” (p. 230): 

“Now, after liberalism has acclaimed man, one can state that thereby only the last 
consequence of Christianity has been drawn and that Christianity originally set itself no other 
task than that of ... realising man.” 



Since allegedly the last consequence of Christianity has been 
drawn, “one” can state that it has been drawn. As soon as the later 




146 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



ones have transformed what was earlier “ one can state” that the 
earlier ones “originally”, namely “in truth”, in essence, in heaven, as 
hidden Jews, “set themselves no other task” than that of being 
transformed by the later ones. Christianity, for Jacques le bonhomme, 
is a self-positing subject, the absolute spirit, which “originally” 
posits its end as its beginning. Cf. Hegel’s Encyclopadie, etc. 

“Hence” (namely because one can attribute an imaginary task to Christianity) 
“there follows the delusion” (of course, before Feuerbach it was impossible to know 
what task Christianity “had originally set itself”) “that Christianity attaches infinite 
value to the ego, as revealed, for example, in the theory of immortality and pastoral 
work. No, it attaches this value to man alone, man alone is immortal, and only because I 
am a man, am I also immortal.” 

If, then, from the whole of Stirner’s scheme and formulation of 
tasks it emerges, already sufficiently clearly, that Christianity can 
lend immortality only to Feuerbach’s “man”, we learn here in 
addition that this comes about also because Christianity does not 
ascribe this immortality — to animals as well. 

Let us now also draw up a scheme a la Saint Max. 

“Now, after” modern large-scale landownership, which has arisen 
from the process of parcellation, has actually “ proclaimed ” primogen- 
iture, “ one can state that thereby only the last consequence” of the 
parcellation of landed property “ has been drawn” “ and that” 
parcellation “in truth originally set itself no other task than that of 
realising ” primogeniture, true primogeniture. “ Hence there follows the 
delusion” that parcellation “ attaches infinite value ” to equal rights of 
members of the family, “as revealed, for example”, in the laws of 
inheritance of the Code Napoleon. “No, it .attaches this value solely” 
to the eldest son; “only” the eldest son, the future owner of the 
entailed estate, will become a large landowner, “and only because I 
am” the eldest son “I will also be” a large landowner. 

In this way it is infinitely easv to give history “unique” turns, as 
one has only to describe its very latest result as the “task” which “in 
truth originally it set itself”. Thereby earlier times acquire a bizarre 
and hitherto unprecedented appearance. It produces a striking 
impression, and does not require great production costs. As, for 
instance, if one says that the real “task” which the institution of 
landed property “originally set itself” was to replace people by 
sheep — a consequence which has recently become manifest in 
Scotland, etc., or that the proclamation of the Capet dynasty 51 
“originally in truth set itself the task” of sending Louis XVI to the 
guillotine and M. Guizot into the Government. The important thing 
is to do it in a solemn, pious, priestly way, to draw a deep breath, and 
then suddenly to burst out: “Now, at last, one can state it.” 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



147 



What Saint Max says about the moderns in the above section 
(pp. 33-37) is only the prologue to the spirit history which is in store 
for us. Here, too, we see how he tries “to rid himself as quickly as 
possible” of empirical facts and parades before us the same 
categories as in the case of the ancients — reason, heart, spirit, 
etc. — only they are given different names. The Sophists become 
sophistical scholastics, “humanists, Machiavellism (the art of 
printing, the New World”, etc.; cf. Hegel’s Geschichte der Philosophies 
III, p. 128) who represent reason; Socrates is transformed into 
Luther, who extols the heart (Hegel, l.c., p. 227), and of the post- 
Reformation period we learn that during that time it was a matter of 
“empty cordiality” (which in the section about the ancients was called 
“purity of heart”, cf. Hegel, l.c., p. 241). All this on page 34. 
In this way Saint Max “proves” that “Christianity takes a course 
similar to that of antiquity”. After Luther he no longer even troubles 
to provide names for his categories; he hurries in seven-league boots 
to modern German philosophy. Four appositions (“until nothing 
remains but empty cordiality, all the universal love of mankind, love 
of man, consciousness of freedom, ‘self-consciousness’”, p. 34; 
Hegel, l.c., pp. 228, 229), four words fill the gulf between Luther and 
Hegel and “only thus is Christianity completed”. This whole 
argument is achieved in one masterly sentence, with the help of such 
levers as “at last” — “and from that time” — “since one” — “also” — 
“from day to day” — “until finally”, etc., a sentence which the reader 
can verify for himself on the classic page 34 already mentioned. 

Finally Saint Max gives us a few more examples of his faith, 
showing that he is so little ashamed of the Gospel that he asserts: “We 
really are nothing but spirit”, and maintains that at the end of the 
ancient world “after long efforts” the “spirit” has really “rid itself of 
the world”. And immediately afterwards he once more betrays the 
secret of his scheme, by declaring of the Christian spirit that “ like a 
youth it entertains plans for improving or saving the world”. All this 
on page 36. 

“So he carried me away in the spirit into the wilderness: and I saw a woman sit 
upon a scarlet-coloured beast, full of names of blasphemy.... And upon her forehead 
was a name written, Mystery, Babylon the Great ... and I saw the woman drunken with 
the blood of the saints”, etc. (Revelation of St. John, 17, Verses 3, 5, 6). 

The apocalyptic prophet did not prophesy accurately this time. 
Now at last, after Stirner has acclaimed man, one can state that he 
ought to have said: So he carried me into the wilderness of the spirit. 
And I saw a man sit upon a scarlet-coloured beast, full of blasphemy 



G.W.F. Hegel, Vorlesungen fiber die Geschichte der Philosophic . — Ed. 




148 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



of names ... and upon his forehead was a name written, Mystery, the 
unique ... and I saw the man drunken with the blood of holy, etc. 
So we now enter the wilderness of the spirit. 



A. The Spirit (Pure History of Spirits) 

The first thing we learn about the “spirit” is that it is not the spirit 
but “the realm, of spirits” that “is immensely large”. Saint Max has 
nothing to say immediately of the spirit except that “an immensely 
large realm of spirits” exists — just as all he knows of the Middle Ages 
is that this period lasted for “a long time”. Having presupposed that 
this “realm of spirits” exists, he subsequently proves its existence 
with the help of ten theses. 

1 . The spirit is not a free spirit until it is not occupied with itself alone, until it is not 
“solely concerned” with its own world, the “spiritual” world (first with itself alone and 
then with its own world). 

2. “It is a free spirit only in a world of its own.” 

3. “Only by means of a spiritual world is the spirit really spirit.” 

4. “Before the spirit has created its world of spirits, it is not spirit.” 

5. “Its creations make it spirit.”... 

6. ’’Its creations are its world.” ... 

7. “The spirit is the creator of a spiritual world.” ... 

8. “The spirit exists only when it creates the spiritual.” ... 

9. “Only together with the spiritual, which is its creation, is it real.”... 

10. “B u t the works or offspring of the spirit are nothing but — spirits” (pp. 38-39). 

In thesis 1 the “spiritual world” is again immediately presupposed 
as existing, instead of being deduced, and this thesis 1 is again 
preached to us in theses 2-9 in eight new transformations. At the end 
of thesis 9 we find ourselves exactly where we were at the end of 
thesis 1 — and then in thesis 10 a “but” suddenly introduces us to 
“ spirits ”, about whom so far nothing has been said. 

“Since the spirit exists only by creating the spiritual, we look around for its first 
creations” (p. 41). 

According to theses 3, 4, 5, 8, and 9, however, the spirit is its own 
creation. This is now expressed thus, the spirit, i.e., the first creation 
of the spirit, 

“must arise out of nothing” ... “it must first create itself” ... “its first creation is itself, 
the spirit” (ibid.). “When it has accomplished this creative act there follows from then 
on a natural reproduction of creations just as, according to the myth, only the first human 
beings had to be created and the rest of the human race was reproduced of itself” 
(ibid.). 

“However mystical this may sound, we nevertheless experience this daily. Are you 
a thinking person before you think? In creating your first thought, you create yourself. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



149 



the thinker, for you do not think until you think, i.e.” — i.e ., — “have some thought. Is it 
not your singing alone that makes you a singer, your speech that makes you a speaking 
person? Well, in the same way only the creation of the spiritual makes you spirit.” 

Our saintly conjurer assumes that the spirit creates the spiritual in 
order to draw the conclusion that the spirit creates itself as spirit; on 
the other hand, he assumes it as spirit in order to allow it to arrive at 
its spiritual creations (which, “according to the myth, are reproduced 
of themselves” and become spirits). So far we have the long-familiar 
orthodox-Hegelian phrases. The genuinely “unique” exposition of 
what Saint Max wants to say only begins with the example he gives. 
That is to say, if Jacques le bonhomme cannot get any further, if even 
“One” and “It” are unable to float his stranded ship, “Stirner” calls 
his third serf to his assistance, the “You”, who never leaves him in the 
lurch and on whom he can rely in extremity. This “You” is an 
individual whom we are not encountering for the first time, a pious 
and faithful servant, 3 whom we have seen going through fire and 
water, a worker in the vineyard of his lord, a man who does not allow 
anything to terrify him, in a word he is: Szeliga.* When “Stirner” is 
in the utmost plight in his exposition he cries out: Szeliga, 
help! — and trusty Eckart Szeliga immediately puts his shoulder to 
the wheel to get the cart out of the mire. We shall have more to say 
later about Saint Max’s relation to Szeliga. 

It is a question of spirit which creates itself out of nothing, hence it is 
a question of nothing, which out of nothing makes itself spirit. From 
this Saint Max derives the creation of Szeliga’s spirit from Szeliga. 
And who else if not Szeliga could “Stirner” count on allowing 
himself to be put in the place of nothing in the manner indicated 
above? Who could be taken in by such a trick but Szeliga, who feels 
highly flattered at being allowed to appear at all as one of the 
dramatis personae ? What Saint Max had to prove was not that a given 
“you”, i.e., the given Szeliga, becomes a thinker, speaker, singer 
from the moment when he begins to think, speak, sing — but that the 
thinker creates himself out of nothing by beginning to think, that the 
singer creates himself out of nothing by beginning to sing, etc., and it is 
not even the thinker and the singer, but the thought and the singing as 
subjects that create themselves out of nothing by beginning to think and 
to sing. For the rest, “Stirner makes only the extremely simple 

* Cf. Die heilige Familie, oder Kritik der kritischen Kritik, where the earlier exploits of 
this man of God have already been set forth. b 



3 Matthew 25:21.— Ed. 

b See present edition, Vol. 4, pp. 55-77. Ed. 




150 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



reflection” and states only the “extremely popular” proposition (cf. 
Wigand, p. 156) that Szeliga develops one of his qualities by 
developing it. There is, of course, absolutely nothing “to be 
wondered at” in the fact that Saint Max does not even “make” 
correctly “such simple reflections”, but expresses them incorrectly in 
order thereby to prove a still much more incorrect proposition with 
the aid of the most incorrect logic in the world. 

Far from it being true that “out of nothing” I make myself, for 
example, a “speaker”, the nothing which forms the basis here is a 
very manifold something, the real individual, his speech organs, a 
definite stage of physical development, an existing language and 
dialects, ears capable of hearing and a human environment from 
which it is possible to hear something, etc., etc. Therefore, in the 
development of a property something is created by something out of 
something, and by no means comes, as in Hegel’s Logik, from 
nothing, through nothing to nothing. 3 

Now that Saint Max has his faithful Szeliga close at hand, 
everything goes forward smoothly again. We shall see how, by means 
of his “you”, he again transforms the spirit into the youth, exactly as 
he earlier transformed the youth into the spirit; here we shall again 
find the whole history of the youth repeated almost word for word, 
only with a few camouflaging alterations — just as the “immensely 
large realm of spirits” mentioned on page 37 was nothing but the 
“realm of the spirit”, to found and enlarge which was the “aim” of 
the spirit of the youth (p. 17). 

“Just as you, however, distinguish yourself from the thinker, singer, speaker, so you 
distinguish yourself no less from the spirit and are well aware that you are something 
else as well as spirit. However, just as in the enthusiasm of thinking it may easily happen 
that sight and hearing fail the thinking ego, so the enthusiasm of the spirit has seized 
you too, and you now aspire with all your might to become wholly spirit and merged in 
spirit. The spirit is your ideal, something unattained, something of the beyond: spirit 
means your — God, ‘God is spirit’ 13 .... You inveigh against yourself, you who cannot get 
rid of a relic of the non-spiritual. Instead of saying: I am more than spirit, you say 
contritely: I am less than spirit, and I can only envisage spirit, pure spirit, or the spirit 
which is nothing but spirit, but I am not it, and since I am not it, then it is an other, it exists 
as an other, whom I call ‘God’.” 

After previously for a long time occupying ourselves with the trick 
of making something out of nothing, we now suddenly, perfectly 
“naturally”, come to an individual who is something else as well as 
spirit, consequently is something, and wants to become pure spirit. 



3 Cf. G.W.F. Hegel, Wissenschaft der Logik, Th. I, Abt. 2. — Ed. 
b John 4:24. — Ed. 




The German Ideoiogv. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 151 



i.e., nothing. This much easier problem, i.e.. to turn something into 
nothing, once again poses the whole story of the vouth, who “has ve: 
to seek the pertect soiri*’ ', and one needs merely to repeat the old 
phrases irom pages 17-18 to oe extricated from all difficulties. 
Particulariy, when one has such an obedient and gullible servant as 
Szeliga, on whom “Surne~ can impose the idea that just as “in the 
enthusiasm of tiimking it mav easily' (!) “happen that sight and 
nearing fail” him “Stimer”. so he, Szeliga. has also oeen “seized with 
the enthusiasm of the spirit’ and he, Szeliga. is now aspiring with all 
nis mignt to become spirit’ , instead oi acciuinng spirit, that is to sa\ , 
ne now has to piav the roie or the vouth as presented on page 1 6. 
Szeliga beiieves it and in iear and trembling he obeys: he obevs when 
Saint Max thunders at him: The spirit is vour ideal — vour God You 
do this for me, vou do that for me. Nov von ‘ inveigh”, now ‘ \ on 
sav”, now “vou can envisage’ , etc. When “Stirner” imposes on him 
the idea that “the pure spirit is an other, for he” (Szeliga) “is noth' 
then in truth, it is oniv Szeliga who is capable of believing him and 
wno gabbles the entire nonsense after him. word for word. Inci 
dentally, the method by which Jacques ie bonhomme makes up this 
nonsense was already exhaustiveiv anaivsed when dealing with the 
vouth Since vou are well aware that vou are something else as well 
as a mathematician, vou aspire to become wholly a mathematician, 
to become merged in mathematics, the mathematician is your ideal, 
mathematician means vour — God. You sav contritelv: I am less than 
a mathematician and 1 can oniv envisage the mathematician, and 
since I am not him, then he is an other he exists as an other, whom 
l call “God” . Someone else in Szeliga s place would say — Arago. 

“Now. at Iasi afte^’ we have proved Stirner’s thesis to be a 
repetition of the vouth”, “one can state’ that he “in truth originate 
set himself no other task” than to identify the spirit of Christian 
asceticism with spirit in general, and to identify the frivolous esprit, 
for example, of the eighteenth century with Christian spiritlessness. 

It follows, therefore that the necessity of spirit dwelling in the 
bevonu, i.e,, being God, is not to be explained, as Stirner 
asserts, “because ego and spirit are difierent names for different 
things, because ego is not spirit and spirit is not ego” (p. 42). The 
explanation lies in the “enthusiasm of the spirit” which is ascribed 
without any grounds to Szeliga and which makes him an ascetic, i.e., 
a man who wishes to become God (pure spirit), and because he is not 
able to do this posits God outside himself. But it was a matter of the 
spirit having first to create itself out of nothing and then having to 
create spirits out of itself. Instead of this, Szeliga now produces God 
(the unique spirit that makes its appearance here) not because he, 



7—2086 




152 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



Szeliga, is the spirit, but because he is Szeliga, i.e., imperfect spirit, 
unspiritual spirit, and therefore at the same time non-spirit. But 
Saint Max does not say a word about how the Christian conception of 
spirit as God arises, although this is now no longer such a clever feat; 
he assumes the existence of this conception in order to explain it. 

The history of the creation of the spirit “has in truth originally set 
itself no other task” than to put Stirner’s stomach among the stars. 

“Precisely because we are not the Precisely because we are not the 

spirit which dwells within us, for that stomach which dwells within us, for that 
very reason we had to very reason we had to 

put it outside of ourselves; it was not us, and therefore we could not conceive it as 
existing except outside of ourselves, beyond us, in the beyond” (p. 43). 

It was a matter of the spirit having first to create itself and then 
having to create something other than itself out of itself; the ques- 
tion was: What is this something else? No answer is given to this ques- 
tion, but after the above-mentioned “various transformations” and 
twists, it becomes distorted into the following new question: 

“The spirit is something other than the ego. But what is this something other?” 
(p. 45). 

Now, therefore, the question arises: What is the spirit other than 
the ego? whereas the original question was: What is the spirit, owing 
to its creation out of nothing, other than itself? With this Saint Max 
jumps to the next “transformation”. 



B. The Possessed ( Impure History of Spirits) 

Without realising it, Saint Max has so far done no more than give 
instruction in the art of spirit-seeing, by regarding the ancient and 
modern world only as the “pseudo-body of a spirit”, as a spectral 
phenomenon, and peeing in it only struggles of spirits. Now, 
however, he consciously and ex professo gives instruction in the art of 
ghost-seeing. 

Instructions in the art of seeing spirits. First of all one must become 
transformed into a complete fool, i.e., imagine oneself to be Szeliga, 
and then say to oneself, as Saint Max does to this Szeliga: “Look 
around you in the world and say for yourself whether a spirit is not 
looking at you from everywhere!” If one can bring oneself to 
imagine this, then the spirits will come “easily”, of themselves; in a 
“flower” one sees only the “creator”, in the mountains — a^spirit of 
loftiness”, in water — a “spirit of longing” or the longing of the spirit, 
and one hears “millions of spirits speak through the mouths of 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



153 



people”. If one has achieved this level, if one can exclaim with Stir- 
ner: “ Yes, ghosts are teeming in the whole world,” then “it is not 
difficult to advance to the point” (p. 93) where one makes the 
further exclamation: “Only in it? No, the world itself is an 
apparition” (let your communication be, Yea, yea; Nay, nay: for 
whatsoever is more than these cometh of evil, 3 i.e., a logical 
transition), “it is the wandering pseudo-body of a spirit, it is an 
apparition.” Then cheerfully “look near at hand or into the distance, 
you are surrounded by a ghostly world.... You see spirits”. If you are 
an ordinary person you can be satisfied with that, but if you are 
thinking of ranking yourself with Szeliga, then you can also look into 
yourself and then “you should not be surprised” if, in these 
circumstances and from the heights of Szeligality, you discover also 
that “your spirit is a ghost haunting your body”, that you yourself 
are a ghost which “awaits salvation, that is, a spirit”. Thereby you will 
have arrived at the point where you are capable of seeing “spirits” 
and “ghosts” in “all” people, and therewith spirit-seeing “reaches its 
final goal” (pp. 46, 47). 

The basis of this instruction, only much more correctly expressed, 
is to be found in Hegel, inter alia, in the Geschichte der Philosophic, III, 
pp. 124, 125. 

Saint Max has such faith in his own instruction that as a result he 
himself becomes Szeliga and asserts that 

“ever since the word was made flesh, b the world is spiritualised, bewitched, a ghost” 
(p- 47). 

“Stirner” “sees spirits”. 

Saint Max intends to give us a phenomenology of the Christian 
spirit and in his usual way seizes on only one aspect. For the Christian 
the world was not only spiritualised but equally ^spiritualised as, 
for example, Hegel quite correctly admits in the passage mentioned, 
where he brings the two aspects into relation with each other, which 
Saint Max should also have done if he wanted to proceed historically. 
As against the world’s despiritualisation in the Christian conscious- 
ness, the ancients, “who saw gods everywhere”, can with equal 
justification be regarded as the spiritualisers of the world — a con- 
ception which our saintly dialectician rejects with the well-meaning 
warning: “Gods, my dear modern man, are not spirits” (p. 47). 
Pious Max recognises only the holy spirit as spirit. 

But even if he had given us this phenomenology (which after 
Hegel is moreover superfluous), he would all the same have given us 



Matthew 5 : 37.— Ed. 
b John 1 : 14. — Ed. 




154 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



nothing. The standpoint at which people are content with such 
tales about spirits is itself a religious one, because for people who 
adopt it religion is a satisfactory answer, they regard religion as causa 
sui a (for both “self-consciousness” and “man” are still religious) 
instead of explaining it from the empirical conditions and showing 
how definite relations of industry and intercourse are necessarily 
connected with a definite form of society, hence, with a definite form 
of state and hence with a definite form of religious consciousness. If 
Stirner had looked at the real history of the Middle Ages, he could 
have found why the Christian’s notion of the world took precisely 
this form in the Middle Ages, and how it happened that it 
subsequently passed into a different one; he could have found that 
“ Christianity ” has no history whatever and that all the different forms in 
which it was visualised at various times were not “self-determina- 
tions” and “further developments” “of the religious spirit”, but 
were brought about by wholly empirical causes in no way dependent 
on any influence of the religious spirit. 

Since Stirner “does not stick to the rules” (p. 45), it is possible, 
before dealing in more detail with spirit-seeing, to say here and now 
that the various “transformations” of Stirner’s people and their 
world consist merely in the transformation of the entire history of 
the world into the body of Hegei’s philosophy; into ghosts, which 
only apparently are an “other being” of the thoughts of the Berlin 
professor. In the Phanomenologie, the Hegelian bible, “the book”, 
individuals are first of all transformed into “consciousness” [and the] 
world into “object”, whereby the manifold variety of forms of life 
and history is reduced to a different attitude of “consciousness” to 
the “object”. This different attitude is reduced, in turn, to three 
cardinal relations: 1) the relation of consciousness to the object as to 
truth, or to truth as mere object (for example, sensual consciousness, 
natural religion, Ionic philosophy, Catholicism, the authoritarian 
state, etc.); 2) the relation of consciousness as the true to the object 
(reason, spiritual religion, Socrates, Protestantism, the French 
Revolution); 3) the true relation of consciousness to truth as object, 
or to the object as truth (logical thinking, speculative philosophy, the 
spirit as existing for the spirit). In Hegel, too, the first relation is 
defined as God the Father, the second as Christ, the third as the Holy 
Spirit, etc. Stirner already used these transformations when speaking 
of child and youth, of ancient and modern, and he repeats them later 
in regard to Catholicism and Protestantism, the Negro and the 
Mongol, etc., and then accepts this series of camouflages of a thought 



Its own cause. — Ed. 




155 



The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



in all good faith as the world against which he has to assert and 
maintain himself as a ‘ corporeal individual”. 

Second set of instructions in spirit-seeing. How to transform the world 
into the spectre of truth, and oneself into something made hoiv or 
spectral. A conversation between Saint Max and his servant Szeiiga 
(pp. 47, 48). 

Saint Max: “You have spirit, tor you have thoughts. What are your thoughts'” 
Szeiiga: “Spiritual entities.’ 

Saint Max: “Hence thev are not things 0 ” 

Szeiiga: “No, but thev are the spirit of things, tne important element in all tilings, 
their innermost essence, their idea.” 

Saint Max: “Wnat vou think is, therefore, not mereiv your thought 0 ” 

Szeiiga: “On the contrarv, it is the most real, genuineiv true thing in the world: it is 
truth itself: when I but truly think, I think the truth. I can admittedlv be mistaken 
about the rruth and fail to perceive it, but when I truly perceive, then the object of mv 
perception is the rruth ” 

Saint Max: “Thus, you endeavour all the time to perceive the truth 0 ” 

Szeiiga: ‘Tor me the truth is sacred 1 .... The truth I cannot abolish; in the truth : 
believe, and therefore I investigate into its nature: there is nothing higher than it, 
it is eternal. Tne truth is sacred, eternal, it is the hoiv, the eternal.” 

Saint Max (indignantly): “But you, by allowing yourself to become filled with this 
holiness, become yourself hoiv.” 

Thus, when Szeiiga truly perceives some object, the object ceases 
to be an object and becomes “the truth”. This is the first manu- 
facture of spectres on a iarge scaie. — It is now no longer a matter 
of perceiving objects, but of perceiving the truth; first he per- 
ceives objects truiy, which ne defines as the truth of perception, 
and he transforms this into perception of the truth. But after Szeiiga 
has thus allowed truth as a spectre to be imposed on him by the 
threatening saint, his stern master strikes home with a question o' 
conscience, whether he is filled “all the time” with longing for the 
truth whereupon the thoroughly confused Szeiiga blurts out 
somewhat prematurely: “For me the truth is sacred.” Bui hr 
mi mediately notices his error and tries to correct it, by shamefaced U 
transforming objects no longer into the truth, out into a number oi 
truths, and abstracting “the truth” as the trutn of these truths, “the 
truth” which he can now no longer abolish after he has distinguished 
it from truths which are capable of being abolished. Therebv it 
becomes “eternal”. But not satisfied w’ith giving it predicates such as 
“sacred, eternal”, he transforms it into the holy, the eternal, as 
subject. Alter this, of course. Saint Max can explain to him tha 



a Here and in the following passages the German word heilig and its derivatives 
are used, which can mean: holy, pious, sacred, sacredness, saintly, saint, to consecrate, 
etc. — Ed. 




156 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



having become “filled” with this holiness, he “himself becomes holy” 
and “should not be surprised” if he now “finds nothing but a 
spectre” in himself. Then our saint begins a sermon: 

“The holy, moreover, is not for your senses” and quite consistently appends by 
means of the conjunction “and’: “never will you, as a sensuous being, discover its 
traces”; that is to say, after sensuous objects are “all gone” and “the truth”, “the 
sacred truth”, “the holy” has taken their place. “But” — obviously! — “for your faith or 
more exactly for your spirit” (for your lack of spirit), “for it is itself som^/imgspiritual” 

( per appositioneni a ), “a spirit ” (again per appos.), “is spirit for the spirit’ . 

Such is the art of transforming the ordinary world, “objects”, by 
means of an arithmetical series of appositions, into “spirit for the 
spirit”. Here we can only admire this dialectical method of 
appositions — later we shall have occasion to explore it and present it 
in all its classical beauty . b 

The method of appositions can also be reversed — for example 
here, after we have once produced “the holy”, it does not receive 
further appositions, but is made the apposition of a new definition; 
this is combining progression with equation. Thus, as a result of 
some dialectical process “there remains the idea of another entity” 
which “I should serve more than myself” ( per appos.), “which for 
me should be more important than everything else” ( per appos.), “in 
short — a something in which I should seek my true salvation ” (and 
finally per appos. the return to the first series), and which becomes 
“something ‘holy’” (p. 48). We have here two progressions which are 
equated to each other and can thus provide the opportunity for a 
great variety of equations. We shall deal with this later. By this 
method too, “the sacred”, which hitherto we have been acquainted 
with only as a purely theoretical designation of purely theoretical 
relations, has acquired a new practical meaning as “something in 
which I should seek my true salvation”, which makes it possible to 
make the holy the opposite of the egoist. Incidentally we need hardly 
mention that this entire dialogue with the sermon that follows is 
nothing but another repetition of the story of the youth already met 
with three or four times before. 

Here, having arrived at the “egoist”, we need not stick to Stirner’s 
“rules” either, because, firstly, we have to present his argument in 
all its purity, free from any intervening intermezzos, and, secondly, 
because in any case these intermezzi (on the analogy of “a Laza- 
roni” — Wigand, p. 159, the word should be Lazzarone — Sancho 
would say intermezzi’s) will occur again in other parts of the book, 



a By means of an apposition. — Ed. 
b See this volume, p. 274 et seq. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



157 



for Stirner, far from obeying his own requirement “always to 
draw back into himself”, on the contrary expresses himself again 
and again. We shall only just mention that the question raised on 
page 45: What is this something distinct from the “ego” that is 
the spirit? is now answered to the effect that it is the holy, 
i.e., that which is foreign to the “ego”, and that everything that 
is foreign to the “ego” is — thanks to some unstated appositions, 
appositions “in themselves” — accordingly without more ado re- 
garded as spirit. Spirit, the holy, the foreign are identical ideas, on 
which he declares war, in the same way almost word for word as he 
did at the very outset in regard to the youth and the man. We have, 
therefore, still not advanced a step further than we had on page 20. 

a) The Apparition 

Saint Max now begins to deal seriously with the “spirits” that are 
“offspring of the spirit” (p. 39), with the ghostliness of everything 
(p. 47). At any rate, he imagines so. Actually, however, he only sub- 
stitutes a new name for his former conception of history according to 
which people were from the outset the representatives of general 
concepts. These general concepts appear here first of all in the 
Negroid form as objective spirits having for people the character of 
objects, and at this level are called spectres or — apparitions. The chief 
spectre is, of course, “man” himself, because, according to what has 
been previously said, people only exist for one another as represen- 
tatives of a universal — essence, concept, the holy, the foreign, 
the spirit — i.e., only as spectral persons, spectres, and because, 
according to Hegel’s Phanomenologie, page 255 and elsewhere, the 
spirit, insofar as for man it has the “form of thinghood”, is another 
man (see below about “the man”). 

Thus, we see here the skies opening and the various kinds of 
spectres passing before us one after the other. Jacques le bonhomme 
forgets only that he has already caused ancient and modern times to 
parade before us like gigantic spectres, compared with which ail the 
harmless fancies about God, etc., are sheer trifles. 

Spectre No. 1: the supreme being, God (p. 53). As was to be 
expected from what has preceded, Jacques le bonhomme, whose 
faith moves all the mountains 3 of world history, believes that “for 
thousands of years people have set themselves the task ”, “have tired 
themselves out struggling with the awful impossibility, the endless 
Danaidean labour” — “to prove the existence of God”. We need not 
waste any more words on this incredible belief. 



a Of. 1 Corinthians 13 : 2. — Ed 




158 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



Spectre No. 2: essence. What our good man says about essence is 
limited — apart from what has been copied out of Hegel — to 
“pompous words and miserable thoughts” (p. 53). “The advance 
from” essence “to” world essence “is not difficult”, and this world 
essence is, of course, 

Spectre No. 3: the vanity of the world. There is nothing to say about 
this except that from it “easily” arises 

Spec tre No. 4: good and evil beings. Something, indeed, could be 
said about this but is not said — and one passes at once to the next: 
Spectre No. 5: the essence and its realm. We should not be at all 
surprised that we find here essence for the second time in our 
honest author, for he is fully aware of his “clumsiness” ( Wigand , 
p. 166), and therefore repeats everything several times in order 
not to be misunderstood. Essence is here in the first place 
defined as the proprietor of a “realm” and then it is said of it 
that it is “essence” (p. 54), after which it is swiftly transformed into 
Spectre No. 6: “essences”. To perceive and to recognise them, and 
them alone, is religion. “Their realm” (of essences) “is — a realm of 
essences” (p. 54). Here there suddenly appears for no apparent 
reason 

Spectre No. 7: the God-Man, Christ. Of him Stirner is able to say 
that he was “corpulent” . If Saint Max does not believe in Christ, he at 
least believes in his “actual corpus”. According to Stirner, Christ 
introduced great distress into history, and our sentimental saint 
relates with tears in his eyes “how the strongest Christians have 
racked their brains in order to comprehend him” — indeed, 

“there has never been a spectre that caused such mental anguish, and no shaman, 
spurring himself into wild frenzy and nerve-racking convulsions, can have suffered 
such agony as Christians have suffered on account of this most incomprehensible 
spectre”. 

Saint Max sheds a sympathetic tear at the grave of the victims of 
Christ and then passes on to the “horrible being”. 

Spectre No. 8, man. Here our bold writer is seized with 
immediate “horror” — “he is terrified of himself”, he sees in every 
man a “frightful spectre”, a “sinister spectre.” in which something 
“stalks” (pp. 55, 56). He feels highly uncomfortable. The split 
between phenomenon and essence gives him no peace. He is like 
Nabal, Abigail’s husband, of whom it is written that his essence too 
was separated from his phenomenal appearance: “And there was a 
man in Maon, whose possessions^ were in Carmel” . (1 Samuel 25 : 2.) But 



a In German a pun on the word Wesen (essence) — in Luther’s Bible translation 
Wesen is used in its old meaning: “possession”. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



159 



in the nick of time, before the “mental anguish” causes Saint Max in 
desperation to put a bullet through his head, he suddenly 
remembers the ancients who “took no notice of anything of the kind 
in their slaves”. This leads him to 

Spectre No. 9, the national spirit (p. 56), about which too Saint Max, 
who can no longer be restrained, indulges in “frightful” fantasies, in 
order to transform 

Spectre No. 10, “ everything ”, into an apparition and, finally, where 
all enumeration ends, to hurl together in the class of spectres the 
“holy spirit”, truth, justice, law, the good cause (which he still cannot 
forget) and half a dozen other things completely foreign to one an- 
other. 

Apart from this there is nothing remarkable in the whole chapter 
except that Saint Max’s faith moves an historical mountain. That is to 
say, he utters the opinion (p. 56): 

“Only for the sake of a supreme being has anyone ever been worshipped, only as a 
spectre has he been regarded as a sanctified, i.e.” (that is!) “protected and recognised 
person.” 

If we shift this mountain, moved by faith alone, back into its prop- 
er place, then “it will read”: Only for the sake of persons who are 
protected, i.e., who protect themselves, and who are privileged, i.e., 
who seize privileges for themselves, have supreme beings been 
worshipped and spectres sanctified. Saint Max imagines, for 
example, that in antiquity, when each people was held together by 
material relations and interests, e.g., by the hostility of the various 
tribes, etc., when owing to a shortage of productive forces each had 
either to be a slave or to possess slaves, etc., etc., when, therefore, 
belonging to a particular people was a matter of “the most natural 
interest” ( Wigand , p. [162]) — that then it was only the concept peo- 
ple, or “nationality” that gave birth to these interests from itself; he 
imagines also that in modern times, when free competition and 
world trade gave birth to hypocritical, bourgeois cosmopolitanism 
and the notion of man— that here, on the contrary, the later 
philosophical construction of man brought about those relations as 
its “revelations” (p. 51). It is the same with religion, with the realm of 
essences, which he considers the unique realm, but concerning the 
essence of which he knows nothing, for otherwise he must have 
known that religion as such has neither essence, nor realm. In 
religion people make their empirical world into an entity that is only 
conceived, imagined, that confronts them as something foreign. This 
again is by no means to be explained from other concepts, from 
“self-consciousness” and similar nonsense, but from the entire 
hitherto existing mode of production and intercourse, which is just 




\ 



160 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



as independent of the pure concept as the invention of the self-acting 
mule 3 and the use of railways are independent of Hegelian 
philosophy. If he wants to speak of an “essence” of religion, i.e., of a 
material basis of this inessentiality , b then he should look for it neither 
in the “essence of man”, nor in the predicates of God, but in 
the material world which each stage of religious development finds 
in existence (cf. above Feuerbach ). c 

All the “spectres” which have filed before us were concepts. These 
concepts — leaving aside their real basis (which Stirner in any case 
leaves aside) — understood as concepts inside consciousness, as 
thoughts in people’s heads, transferred from their objectivity back 
into the subject, elevated from substance into self-consciousness, 
are — whimsies or fixed ideas. 

Concerning the origin of Saint Max’s history of ghosts, see 
Feuerbach in Anekdota II, p. 66. d where it is stated: 

“Theology is belief in ghosts. Ordinary theology, however, has its ghosts in the 
sensuous imagination, speculative theology has them in non-sensuous abstraction.” 

And since Saint Max shares the belief of all critical speculative 
philosophers of modern times that thoughts, which have become 
independent, objectified thoughts — ghosts — have ruled the world 
and continue to rule it, and that all history up to now was the history 
of theology, nothing could be easier for him than to transform 
history into a history of ghosts. Sancho’s history of ghosts, therefore, 
rests on the traditional belief in ghosts of the speculative 
philosophers. 



b) Whimsy 

“Man, there are spectres in your head!... You have a fixed idea!” 
thunders Saint Max at his slave Szeliga. “Don’t think I am joking,” 
he threatens him. Don’t dare to think that the solemn “Max Stirner” 
is capable of joking. 

The man of God is again in need of his faithful Szeliga in order to 
pass from the object to the subject, from the apparition to the 
whimsy. 

Whimsy is the hierarchy in the single individual, the domination 



3 The English term is used in the manuscript . — Ed 

b In German a pun on the words Wesen — essence, substance, being — and 
Unwesen — literally inessence. Unwesen can be rendered in English as disorder, 
nuisance, confusion or, in a different context, monster. — Ed. 
c See this volume, pp. 53-54. — Ed. 

Ludwig Feuerbach, “Vorlaufige Thesen zur Reformation der Philo- 
sophic”. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



161 



of thought “in him over him”. After the world has confronted 
the fantasy-making youth (of page 20) as a world of his “feverish 
fantasies”, as a world of ghosts, “the offsprings of his own head” 
inside his head begin to dominate him. The world of his feverish 
fantasies — this is the step forward he has made— now exists as the 
world of his deranged mind. Saint Max — the man who is confronted 
by “the world of the moderns” in the form of the fantasy-making 
youth — has necessarily to declare that “almost the whole of mankind 
consists of veritable fools, inmates of a mad-house” (p. 57). 

The whimsy which Saint Max discovers in the heads of people is 
nothing but his own whimsy — the whimsy of the “saint” who views 
the world sub specie aeterni a and who takes both the hypocritical 
phrases of people and their illusions for the true motives of their ac- 
tions; that is why our naive, pious man confidently pronounces the 
great proposition: “Almost all mankind clings to something higher” 

(P- 57). 

“Whimsy” is “a fixed idea”, i.e., “an idea which has subordinated 
man to itself” or — as is said later in more popular form — all kinds of 
absurdities which people “ have stuffed into their heads”. With the 
utmost ease, Saint Max arrives at the conclusion that everything that 
has subordinated people to itself — for example, the need to produce 
in order to live, and the relations dependent on this — is such an 
“absurdity” or “ fixed idea”. Since the child’s world is the only “world 
of things”, as we learned in the myth of “a man's life”, 
everything that does not exist “for the child” (at times also for the 
animal) is in any case an “idea” and “easily also” a “fixed idea”. We 
are still a long way from getting rid of the youth and the child. 

The chapter on whimsy aims merely at establishing the existence 
of the category of whimsy in the history of “man”. The actual 
struggle against whimsy is waged throughout the entire “book” and 
particularly in the second part. Hence a few examples of whimsy 
can suffice us here. 

On page 59, Jacques le bonhomme believes that 

“our newspapers are full of politics, because they are in the grip of the delusion that 
man was created in order to become a zoon politikon” h . 

Hence, according to Jacques le bonhomme, people engage in 
politics because our newspapers are full of them! If a church father 
were to glance at the stock exchange reports of our newspapers, he 
could not judge differently from Saint Max and would have to say: 
these newspapers are full of stock exchange reports because they are 

a Under the aspect of eternity (see Benedictus Spinoza, Ethica, Pars quinta). — Ed. 

Political animal — thus Aristotle defines man at the beginning of De republica. 
Book I. — Ed. 




162 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



in the grip of the delusion that man was created in order to engage in 
financial speculation. Thus, it is not the newspapers that possess 
whimsies, but whimsies that possess “Stirner”. 

Stirner explains the condemnation of incest and the institutions of 
monogamy from “the holy”, “they are the holy”. If among the 
Persians incest is not condemned, and if the institution of polygamy 
occurs among the Turks, then in those places incest and polygamy 
are “the holy”. It is not possible to see any difference between these 
two “holies” other than that the nonsense with which the Persiahs 
and Turks have “stuffed their heads” is different from that with 
which the Christian Germanic peoples have stuffed their 
heads. — Such is the church father s manner of “detaching himself” 
from historv “in good time”. — Jacques le bonhomme has so little 
inkling of the real, materialist causes for the condemnation of 
polygamy and incest in certain social conditions that he considers this 
condemnation to be merely the dogma of a creed and in common 
with every philistine imagines that when a man is imprisoned for a 
crime of this kind, it means that “moral purity” is confining him in a 
“house of moral correction” (p. 60) — just as jails in general seem to 
him to be houses for moral correction — in this respect he is at a lower 
level than the educated bourgeois, who has a better understanding of 
the matter — cf. the literature on prisons. “Stirner’s” “jails” are the 
most trite illusions of the Berlin burgher which for him, however, 
hardly deserve to be called a “house of moral correction”. 

After Stirner, with the help of an “episodically included” 
“historical reflection”, has discovered that 

“a had to come to pass that the whole man with all his abilities would prove to be 
religious” (p. 64) “so, too, in point of fact” “it is not surprising” — “for we are now so 
thoroughly religious”— “that” the oath “of the members o f the jury condemns us to death 
and that bv means of the ‘official oath’ the police constable, as a good Christian, has us 
put in the clink”. 

When a gendarme stops him for smoking in the Tiergarten, 52 the 
cigar is knocked out of his mouth not bv the royal Prussian 
gendarme who is paid to do so and shares in the monev from fines, 
but by the “official oath”. In precisely the same way the power of the 
bourgeois in the jury court becomes transformed for Stirner — owing 
to the pseudo-hoiv appearance which the amis du commerce assume 
here — into the power of making a vow% the power of the oath, into 
the “ho/\”. “Verily, I say unto you: I have not found so great faith, 
no, not in Israel.” (Matthew 8: 10.) 

“For some persons a thought becomes a maxim, so that it is not the person who 
possesses the maxim, but rather the latter that possesses him, and with the maxim he 
again acquires a firm standpoint.” But “it is not of him that willeth, nor of him that 
runneth, but of God that sheweth mercy” (Romans 9: 16). 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



163 



Therefore Saint Max has on the same page to receive several 
thorns in the flesh 3 and must give us a number of maxims: firstly, 
the maxim [to recognise] no maxims, with which goes, secondly, the 
maxim not to have any firm standpoint; thirdly, the maxim 
“although we should possess spirit, spirit should not possess us”; and 
fourthly, the maxim that one should also be aware of one’s flesh, “for 
only by being aware of his flesh is man fully aware of himself, and 
only by being fully aware of himself, is he aware or rational”. 

C. The Impurely Impure History of Spirits 
a) Negroes and Mongols 

We now go back to the beginning of the “unique” historical 
scheme and nomenclature. The child becomes the Negro, the 
youth — the Mongol. See “The Economy of the Old Testament”. 

“The historical reflection on our Mongolhood, which I shall include episodically at 
this point, I present without any claim to thoroughness or even to authenticity, but solely 
because it seems to me that it can contribute to clarifying the rest” (p. 87). 

Saint Max tries to “clarify” for himself his phrases about the child 
and the youth by giving them world-embracing names, and he tries 
to “clarify” these world-embracing names by replacing them with his 
phrases about the child and the youth. “The Negroid character 
represents antiquity, dependence on things ” (child); “the Mongoloid 
character — the period of dependence on thoughts, the Christian 
epoch” ( the youth). (Cf. “The Economy of the Old Testament”.) “The 
following words are reserved for the future: I am owner of the world 
of things, and I am owner of the world of thoughts ” (pp. 87, 88). This 
“future” has already happened once, on page 20, in connection with 
the man, and it will occur again later, beginning with page 226. 

First “ historical reflection without claim to thoroughness or even to 
authenticity”: Since Egypt is part of Africa where Negroes live, it 
follows that “included” “in the Negro era” (p. 88) are the 
“campaigns of Sesostris”, which never took place, and the “signifi- 
cance of Egypt” (the significance it had also at the time of the 
Ptolemies, Napoleon’s expedition to Egypt, Mohammed Ali, the 
Eastern question, the pamphlets of Duvergier de Haurannes, etc.), 
“and of North Africa in general” (and therefore of Carthage, 
Hannibal’s campaign against Rome, and “easily also”, the signifi- 
cance of Syracuse and Spain, the Vandals, Tertullian, the Moors, A1 
Hussein Abu Ali Ben Abdallah Ibn Sina, piratical states, the French 



2 Corinthians 12:7. — Ed. 




164 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



in Algeria, Abd-el-Kader, Pere Enfantin 53 and the four new toads of 
the Charivari ) (p. 88). Consequently, Stirner clarifies the campaigns 
of Sesostris, etc., by transferring them to the Negro era, and he 
clarifies the Negro era by “episodically including” it as a historical 
illustration of his unique thoughts “about our childhood years”. 

Second “ historical reflection “To the Mongoloid era belong the 
campaigns of the Huns and Mongols up to the Russians” (and 
Wasserpolacken 54 ); thus here again the campaigns of the Huns and 
Mongols, together with the Russians, are “clarified” by their 
inclusion in the “Mongoloid era”, and the “Mongoloid era” — by 
pointing out that it is the era of the phrase “dependence on 
thoughts”, which we have already encountered in connection with 
the youth. 

Third “ historical reflection ”: 

In the Mongoloid era the “value of my ego cannot possibly be put at a high levei 
because the hard, diamond of the non-ego is too high in price, because it is still too gritty 
and impregnable for it to be absorbed and consumed by my ego. On the contrary, 
people are simply exceptionally busv crawling about on this static world, this 
substance, like parasitic animalcules on a body from whose juices they extract 
nourishment, but nevertheless do not devour the body. It is the bustling activity of 
noxious insects, the industriousness of Mongols. Among the Chinese indeed every thing 
remains as of old, etc.... Therefore ” (because among the Chinese everything remains as 
of old) “in our Mongol era every change has only been reformatory and corrective, 
and not destructive, devouring or annihilating. The substance, the object remains. All 
our industriousness is only the activity of ants and the jumping of fleas ... juggling on 
the tightrope of the objective”, etc. (p. 88. Cf. Hegel, Philosophie der Geschichte, pp. 1 13, 
118, 119 (unsoftened substance), p. 140, etc., where China is understood as “substan- 
tiality”). 

We learn here, therefore, that in the true Caucasian era people 
will be guided by the maxim that the earth, “substance”, the “ob- 
ject”, the “static” has to be devoured, “consumed”, “annihilated”, 
“absorbed”, “destroyed”, and along with the earth the solar system 
that is inseparable from it. World-devouring “Stirner” has already 
introduced us to the “reformatory or corrective activity” of the 
Mongols as the youth’s and Christian’s “plans for the salvation and 
correction of the world” on page 36. Thus we have still not advanced a 
step. It is characteristic of the entire “unique” conception of history 
that the highest stage of this Mongol activity earns the title of 
“scientific” — from which already now the conclusion can be drawn, 
which Saint Max later tells us, that the culmination of the Mongolian 
heaven is the Hegelian kingdom of spirits. 

Fourth “ historical reflection ”, The world on which the Mongols crawl 
about is now transformed by means of a “flea jump” into the 
“positive”, this into the “precept”, and, with the help of a paragraph 
on page 89. the precept becomes “morality”, “Morality appears in its 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



165 



first form as custom” — hence it comes forward as a person, but in a 
trice it becomes transformed into a sphere: 

“To act in accordance with the morals and customs of one’s country means here ” 
(i.e., in the sphere of morality) "to be moral”. “Therefore” (because this occurs in the 
sphere of morality as a custom) “pure, moral behaviour in the most straightforward form is 
practised in ... Chinal ” 

Saint Max is unfortunate in his examples. On page 1 16 in just the 
same way he attributes to the North Americans the “religion of 
honesty”. He regards the two most rascally nations on earth, the 
patriarchal swindlers — the Chinese, and the civilised swindlers — the 
Yankees, as “straightforward”, “moral” and “honest”. If he had 
looked up his crib he could have found the North Americans classed 
as swindlers on page 81 of the Philosophie der Geschichte and the 
Chinese ditto on page 130. 

“One” — that friend of the saintly worthy man — now helps him to 
arrive at innovation, and from this an “and” brings him back to 
custom, and thus the material is prepared for achieving a master 
stroke in the 

Fifth historical reflection: “There is in fact no doubt that by means of 
custom man protects himself against the importunity of things, of 
the world” — for example, from hunger; 

“and” — as quite naturally follows from this — 

“founds a world of his own” — which “Stirner” has need of now — 
“in which alone he feels in his native element and at home”, — “alone” , 
after he has first by “custom” made himself “at home” in the 
existing “world” — 

“i.e., builds himself a heaven” — because China is called the Celestial 
Empire. 

“For indeed heaven has no other significance than that of being the real 
homeland of man” — in this context, however, it signifies the imagined 
unreality of the real homeland — 

“where nothing alien any longer prevails upon him”, i.e., where what is 
his own prevails upon him as something alien, and all the rest of the 
old story. “Or rather”, to use Saint Bruno’s words, or “it is easily 
possible”, to use Saint Max’s words, that this proposition should read 
as follows: 



Stirner’s proposition without claim to 
thoroughness or even to authenticity 

“There is in fact no doubt that by 
means of custom man protects himself 
against the importunity of things, of the 
world, and founds a world of his own., in 
which alone he feels in his native element 
and at home, i.e., builds himself a heaven. 



Clarified proposition 

“There is in fact no doubt” that 
because China is called the Celestial 
Empire, because “Stirner” happens to be 
speaking of China and as he is “accus- 
tomed” by means of ignorance “to 
protect himself against the importunity 
of things, of the world, and to found a 




] 60 Kan Marx and Frederick Engels 



Fo- indeed ‘heaven' has no other sig- world o r his own, in which alone he 

nmcance than that oi being tne reai ieeis in ins native element and at 

nomeland of man where nothing alier home’" — therefore he "builds himself a 

anv longer prevails upon him and rules heaven’ out of the Chinese Celestial 

over him no earth!' influence anv Empire. "For indeed’" the importunitv 

lonsrev estranges him from himself, in of the world, of things “has no other 

short, wnere earthiv dross is thrown significance than that of being the real” 

aside and the struggle against the world hell oi" the unique, ‘ in which’ even - 

nas come to an end, where, therefore, thing prevails upon him ana rules over 

nothing is forbidden him anv more” him” as something “alien”, bur which he 

sP- ^ • is able to transform into a “heaven’ bv 

“estranging himself” from al! “earthiv 
influences’ , historical tacvs and connec- 
tions, and hence no longer thinks them 
strange: “in short”, it is a sphere ‘ where 
the earthiv”, the historical ‘dross is 
thrown aside”, and where Stirner “does 
not find’ in the ‘ end” “of the world 
any more “struggle” — and thereby 
everything has been said. 

Sixth “ historical reflection”. On paee 90, Stirner imagines that 

‘ in Cmna everytning is provided for; no matter what happens, the Chinese always knows 
how he should behave, and he has no need to decide according to circumstances; no 
unforeseen event will overthrow his celestial cairn . 

Nor anv British bombardment either — he knew exactly “how he 
should behave’ 7 , particularly in regard to the unfamiliar steamships 
and shrapnel-bombs, 5 ' 

Saint Max extracted that from Hegel s Philosophie der Geschichte, 
pages 118 and 127. to which, of course he had to add something 
unique, in order to achieve his reflection as given above. 

' Consequently' continues Saint Max, ‘ mankind climbs the first rung of the ladder 
of education bv means of custom, and since t: imagines that bv gaining culture, it has 
gained heaven, the realm oi culture or second nature it actually mounts the first rung 
oi the heaveniv ladder” .p, 90;. 

Consequently”, t.e., because Hegel oegins history with China 
and because “the Chinese does not lose ms equanimity”, “Stirner” 
transforms mankind into a person who ‘ mounts the first rung of the 
ladder of culture’ and indeed does so “bv means of custom”, 
because China has no other meaning for Stirner than that of being 
the embodiment of “custom”. Now if is onn a question for our zealot 
against the holv of transforming the “ladder” into a “heaveniv lad- 
der”, since China is also called the Celestial Empire. “Since mankind 
imagines” (“wherefrom” does Stirner ‘ know everything that” 
mankind imagines, see Wigand, page 189) — and this ought to have 
been proved by Stirner — firstly that it transforms “culture” into the 
“heaven of culture”, and secondly that it transforms the “heaven of 




The German ideoiogv. The Leipzig Council. 111. Saint -> •; 



1 07 



culture” into the ‘ culture of heaver.” — an alleged notion on the 
part oi : mankind which appears on page 91 as a notion of Stirner’s 
and therebv receives its correct expression) — ; so it actually mounts 
the first rung of the heavenh ladder”. Since it imagines that it 
mounts the first rung of the heavenh ladder — so — it mounts ir 
actually ! “ Since ” the vouth” “imagines’ that he becomes pure spirit, 
he does actually become such; See the ‘ vouth” and the “Christian” 
on the transition from the world of things to the world of the spirit, 
where the simple formula for this heavenly ladder of unique” ideas 
already occurs. 

Seventh historical reflection . page 90. “If Mongolism” (it follows 
immediately after the heavenlv ladder, whereby “Stirner”, through 
the alleged notion on the part of mankind, was abie to ascertain the 
existence of a spiritual essence [ Wesen ]}, “if Mongolism has 
established the existence of spiritual beings [Wesen]" (rather — if 
“Stirner” has established his fancv about the spiritual essence of the 
Mongols). “ then the Caucasians have fought for thousands of years 
against these spiritual beings, in order to get to the bottom of them”. 
(The youth, who becomes a man and tries all the time” “to 
penetrate behind thoughts”, the Christian who “tries all the time” 
“to explore the depths of divinity ”.') Since the Chinese have noted 
the existence of God knows what spiritual beings (“Stirner” does nor 
note a single one, apart from his heavenly ladder) — so for thousands 
of years the Caucasians have to wrangle with ‘ these” Chinese 
“spiritual beings”; moreover, two lines below Stirner puts on record 
that they actually “stormed the Mongolian heaven, the tien . and 
continues: “When will they destroy this heaven, when will they 
finally become actual Caucasians and find themselves^" 

Here we have the negative unity, already' seen earlier as man, now 
appearing as the ‘actual Caucasian”, i.e., not Negroid, no: 
Mongolian, but as the Caucasian Caucasian . This latter, therefore., a , 
a concept, as essence, is here separated from the actual Caucasians, is 
counterposed to them as the ‘ideal of the Caucasian”, as a 
vocation” in which thev should “find themselves”, as a “destiny”, a 
“task”, as “the holy”, as “the hob” Caucasian, “the perfect’ 
Caucasian, "who indeed” is the Caucasian “in heaven — God". 

“In the sedulous struggle of the Mongolian race, men had built a 
heaven” — so “Stirner” believes (p. 91), forgetting that actual Mon- 
gols are much more occupied with sheep than with heaven a — 
when the people of the Caucasian stock, so long as they ... have 



a In German a pun based on the words die Hdmmei — the '-sheep, and die 
Himmei — the heavens. — Ed. 




168 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



to do with heaven ... undertook the business of storming heaven.” Had 
built a heaven, when ... so long as they have... [they] undertook. The 
unassuming “historical reflection” is here expressed in a consecutio 
temporuvrf which also does not “lay claim” to classic form “or even” 
to grammatical correctness; the construction of the sentences 
corresponds to the construction of history. “Stirner’s” “claims” “are 
restricted to this” and “thereby achieve their final goal”. 

Eighth historical reflection , which is the reflection of reflections, the 
alpha and omega of the whole of Stirner’s history: Jacques le 
bonhomme, as we have pointed out from the beginning, sees in all the 
movement of nations that has so far taken place merely a sequence of 
heavens (p. 91), which can also be expressed as follows: successive 
generations of the Caucasian race up to the present day did nothing 
but squabble about the concept of morality (p. 92) and “their activity 
has been restricted to this” (p. 91). If they had got out of their heads 
this unfortunate morality, this apparition, they would have achieved 
something; as it was, they achieved nothing, absolutely nothing, and 
have to allow Saint Max to set them a task as if they were schoolboys. 
It is completely in accordance with his view of history that at the 
end (p. 92) he conjures up speculative philosophy so that “in it this 
heavenly kingdom, the kingdom of spirits and spectres, should find 
its proper order” — and that in a later passage speculative philosophy 
should be conceived as the “perfect kingdom of spirits”. 

Why it is that for those who regard history in the Hegelian manner 
the result of all preceding history was finally bound to be the 
kingdom of spirits perfected and brought into order in speculative 
philosophy — the solution of this secret “Stirner” could have very 
simply found by recourse to Hegel himself. To arrive at this result 
“the concept of spirit must be taken as the basis and then it must be 
shown that history is the process of the spirit itself” ( Geschichte der 
Philosophic, III, p. 91). After the “concept of spirit” has been 
imposed on history as its basis, it is very easy, of course, to “show” 
that it is to be discovered everywhere, and then to make this as a 
process “find its proper order”. 

After making everything “find its proper order”, Saint Max can 
now exclaim with enthusiasm: “To desire to win freedom for the 
spirit, that is Mongolism”, etc. (cf. p. 17: “To bring to light pure 
thought, etc. — that is the joy of the youth”, etc.), and can declare 
hypocritically: “ Hence it is obvious that Mongolism ... represents 
non-sensuousness and unnaturalness”, etc. — when he ought to have 
said: it is obvious that the Mongol is only the disguised youth who, 



a Sequence of tenses. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



169 



being the negation of the world of things, can also be called 
“unnaturalness”, “non-sensuousness”, etc. 

We have again reached the point where the “youth” can pass into 
the “man”: “But who will transform the spirit into its nothing? He, 
who by means of the spirit represented nature as the futile, the finite, 
the transitory” (i.e., imagined it as such — and, according to page 16 
et seq., this was done by the youth, later the Christian, then the 
Mongol, then the Mongoloid Caucasian, but properly speaking only 
by idealism), “he alone can also degrade the 'spirit” (namely in his 
imagination) “to the same futility” (therefore the Christian, etc.? No, 
exclaims “Stirner” resorting to a similar trick as on pages 19-20 in 
the case of the man). “I can do it, each of you can do it who operates 
and creates” (in his imagination) “as the unrestricted ego”, “in a 
word, the egoist can do it” (p. 93), i.e., the man, the Caucasian 
Caucasian, who therefore is the perfect Christian, the true Christian, 
the holy one, the embodiment of the holy. 

Before dealing with the further nomenclature, we also “should 
like at this point to include an historical reflection” on the origin 
of Stirner’s “historical reflection about our Mongolism”; our 
reflection differs, however, from Stirner’s in that it definitely “lays 
claim to thoroughness and authenticity”. His whole historical 
reflection, just as that on the “ancients”, is a concoction out of Hegel. 

The Negroid state is conceived as “the child” because Hegel says 
on page 89 of his Philosophie der Geschichte: 

“Africa is the country of the childhood of history.” “In defining the African” 
(Negroid) “spirit we must entirely discard the category of universality ” (p. 90)— i.e., 
although the child or the Negro has ideas, he still does not have the idea. “Among the 
Negroes consciousness has not yet reached a firm objective existence, as for example 
God, law, in which man would have the perception of his essence ” ... “thanks to which, 
knowledge of an absolute being is totally absent. The Negro represents natural man in 
all his lack of restraint” (p. 90). “Although they must be conscious of their dependence 
on the natural” (on things, as “Stirner” says), “this, however, does not lead them to 
the consciousness of something higher” (p. 91). 

Here we meet again all Stirner’s determinations of the child and 
the Negro — dependence on things, independence of ideas and 
especially of “the idea”, “the essence”, “the absolute” (holy) 
“being”, etc. 

He found that in Hegel the Mongols and, in particular, the 
Chinese appear as the beginning of history and since for Hegel, too, 
history is a history of spirits (but not in such a childish way as with 
“Stirner”), it goes without saying that the Mongols brought the spirit 
into history and are the original representatives of everything 
“sacred”. In particular, on page 110, Hegel describes the “ Mongolian 
kingdom” (of the Dalai-Lama) as the “ ecclesiasticar realm, the 




170 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



“kingdom of theocratic rule”, a “spiritual, religious kingdom” — in 
contrast to the worldly empire of the Chinese. “Stirner”, of course, 
has to identify China with the Mongols. In Hegel, on page 140, there 
even occurs the “Mongolian principle ” from which “Stirner” derived 
his “ Mongolism ”. Incidentally, if he really wanted to reduce the 
Mongols to the category of “idealism”, he could have “found 
established” in the Dalai-Lama system and Buddhism quite different 
“spiritual beings” from his fragile “heavenly ladder”. But he did not 
even have time to look properly at Hegel’s Philosophie der Geschichte. 
The peculiarity and uniqueness of Stirner’s attitude to history 
consists in the egoist being transformed into a “clumsy” copier of 
Hegel. 

b) Catholicism and Protestantism 
(Cf. “The Economy of the Old Testament”) 

'W 

What we here call Catholicism, “Stirner” calls the “Middle Ages”, 
but as he confuses (as “in everything”) the pious, religious character 
of the Middle Ages, the religion of the Middle Ages, with the actual, 
profane Middle Ages in flesh and blood, we prefer to give the matter 
its right name at once. 

“The Middle Ages” were a “ lengthy period, in which people were content with the 
illusion of having the truth” (they did not desire or do anything else), “without 
seriously thinking about whether one must be true oneself in order to possess the 
truth”. — “In the Middle Ages people ” (that is, the whole of the Middle Ages) 
“mortified the flesh, in order to become capable of assimilating the holy” (p. 108). 

Hegel defines the attitude to the divine in the Catholic church by 
saying 

“that people’s attitude to the absolute was as to something purely external” 
(Christianity in the form of externality) ( Geschichte der Philosophie, III, p. 148, and 
elsewhere). Of course, the individual has to be purified in order to assimilate the truth, 
but “this also occurs in an external way, through redemptions, fasts, self-flagellations, 
visits to holy places, pilgrimages” (ibid., p. 140). 

“Stirner” makes this transition by saying: 

“In the same way, too, as people strain their eyes in order to see a distant object ... so 
they mortified the flesh, etc.” 

Since in “Stirner’s” “book” the Middle Ages are identified with 
Catholicism, they naturally end with Luther ( p. 108). Luther himself 
is reduced to the following definition, which has already cropped up 
in connection with the youth, in the conversation with Szeliga and 
elsewhere: 

“Man, if he wants to attain truth, must become as true as truth itself. Only he who 
already has truth in faith can participate in it.” 

Concerning Lutheranism, Hegel says: 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



171 



“The truth of the gospel exists oniv in the true attitude to it.... The essential 
attitude of the spirit exists onlv for the spirit.... Hence the attitude of the spirit to the 
content is that although the content is essential, it is equally essential that the hoiy and 
consecrating spirit should stand in relation to this content” ( Gesctnchte der Philosophie, 
III, p. 234; “This then is the Lutheran faith — his” q.e., man's) "faith is required of 
turn ami it alone can truly be taken into account'' (ibid., p. 230;. “Luther ... affirms that 
the divine is divine om\ insofar as it is apprehended in this subjective spirituaiitv o: 
faith” (ibid., p. 138). “The doctrine of the’ (Catholic) “church is truth as existent truth” 
( Philosophie der Religion II, p. 331). 

“Stirne^” continues: 

“Accordingly, with Luther the knowledge arises that truth, because it is thought, 
exists oniv for the thinking man and this means that with regard to his object- 
thought — man must adopt a totaliv different standpoint, a pious” (per uppos.j. 

‘ scientific standpoint, or that of thinking” tp. 1 10). 

Apart from the repetition which “Stirner” again “includes” here, 
only the transition from faith to thinking deserves attention. Hegel 
makes the transition in the following way: 

“But this spirit” (namely, the holy and consecrating spirit) ‘ is. secondly, essentially 
also thinking spirit. Thinking a* such must also nave its development in it”, etc. 
([Geschichte der Philosophie,] p. 234). 

“Stirner” continues: 

“7’his thought” (“that I am stoirit, spirit aione”) “pervades the historv of the 
Reformation down to the present day” *p. 111,. 

From the sixteenth century onwards, no other historv exists for 
“Stirner” than the history of the Reformation — and the iatter only in 
the interpretation in which Hegel presents it. 

Saint Max has again displayed his gigantic faith. He has again 
taken as literal truth all the illusions of German speculative 
philosophy; indeed, he has made them still more speculative, still 
more abstract. For him there exists only the history of religion and 
philosophy — and this exists for him oniv through the medium of 
Hegel, who with the passage of time has become the universal crib, 
the reference source for all the latest German speculators about 
principles and manufacturers of svstems. 

Catholicism =attitude to truth as thing, child, Negro, the “an- 
cient”. 

Protestantism = attitude to truth in the spirit, youth, Mongol, the 
“modern”. 

The whole scheme was superfluous, since all this was already 
present in the section on “spirit”. 

As already mentioned in “The Economy of the Old Testament”, it 



J G.W.F. Hegel, Vorlesungen fiber die Philosophie der Religion. — Ed. 




172 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



is now possible to make the child and the youth appear again in new 
“transformations” within Protestantism, as “Stirner” actually does 
on page 112, where he conceives English, empirical philosophy as 
the child, in contrast to German, speculative philosophy as the youth. 
Here again he copies out Hegel, who here, as elsewhere in the 
“book”, frequently appears as “ one ”. 

“One” — i.e., Hegel — “expelled Bacon from the realm of philosophy.” “And, 
indeed, what is called English philosophy does not seem to have got any farther than 
the discoveries made by so-called clear intellects such as Bacon and Hume” (p. 1 12). 

Hegel expresses this as follows: 

“Bacon is in fact the real leader and representative of what is called philosophy in 
England and beyond which the English have by no means gone as yet” ( Geschichte der 
Philosophie, III, p. 254). 

The people whom “Stirner” calls “clear intellects” Hegel (ibid., 
p. 255) calls “educated men of the world” — Saint Max on one occa- 
sion even transforms them into the “simplicity of childish nature”, 
for the English philosophers have to represent the child. On the same 
childish grounds Bacon is not allowed to have “concerned himself 
with theological problems and cardinal propositions”, regardless of 
what may be said in his writings (particularly De Augmentis 
Scientiarum , a Novum Organum and the Essays' 3 ). On the other hand, 
“German thought ... sees life only in cognition itself” (p. 1 12), for it is 
the youth. Ecce iterum Crispinus! c 

How Stirner transforms Descartes into a German philosopher, the 
reader can see for himself in the “book”, p. 112. 



D. Hierarchy 

In the foregoing presentation Jacques le bonhomme conceives 
history merely as the product of abstract thoughts — or, rather, of his 
notions of abstract thoughts — as governed by these notions, which, in 
the final analysis, are all resolved into the “holy”. This domination of 
the “holy”, of thought, of the Hegelian absolute idea over the 
empirical world he further portrays as a historical relation existing at 
the present time, as the domination of the holy ones, the ideologists, 
over the vulgar world — as a hierarchy. In this hierarchy, what 
previously appeared consecutively exists side by side, so that one of the 
two co-existing forms of development rules over the other. Thus, the 



a Francis Bacon, De Dignitate et Augmentis Scientiarum. — Ed. 

Francis Bacon, The Essays or Councels. Civill and Morall. — Ed. 

And there is Crispinus again — the opening words of Juvenal’s fourth satire. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



173 



youth rules over the child, the Mongol over the Negro, the modern 
over the ancient, the selfless egoist ( citoyen ) over the egoist in the 
usual sense of the word (bourgeois), etc. — see “The Economy of the 
Old Testament”. The “destruction” of the “world of things” by the 
“world of the spirit” appears here as the “domination” of the “world 
of thoughts” over the “world of things”. The outcome, of course, is 
bound to be that the domination which the “world of thoughts” 
exercises from the outset in history is at the end of the latter also 
presented as the real, actually existing domination of the think- 
ers — and, as we shall see, in the final analysis, as the domination of 
the speculative philosophers — over the world of things, so that Saint 
Max has only to fight against thoughts and ideas of the ideologists 
and to overcome them, in order to make himself “possessor of the 
world of things and the world of thoughts”. 

“ Hierarchy is the domination of thought, the domination of the spirit. We are still 
hierarchical to this day, we are under the yoke of those who rely on thoughts, and 
thoughts” — who has failed to notice it long ago? — “are the holy ” (p. 97). (Stirner has 
tried to safeguard himself against the reproach that in his whole book he has only been 
producing “thoughts”, i.e., the “holy”, by in fact nowhere producing any thoughts in 
it. Although in the Wigand periodical he ascribes to himself “virtuosity in thinking”, 
i.e., according to his interpretation, virtuosity in the fabrication of the “holy” — and 
this we shall concede him.) — “Hierarchy is the supreme domination of spirit” (p. 467). 
— “The medieval hierarchy was only a weak hierarchy, for it was forced to allow 
all kinds of profane barbarism to exist unrestricted alongside it” (“how Stirner knows 
so much about what the hierarchy was forced to do”, we shall soon see), “and onlv the 
Reformation steeled the power of the hierarchy” (p. 110). “Stirner” indeed thinks 
that “the domination of spirits was never before so all-embracing and omnipotent” as 
after the Reformation; he thinks that this domination of spirits “instead of divorcing 
the religious principle from art, sta? ■■ and science, on the contrary, raised these who !! \ 
from actuality into the kingdom of the spirit and made them religious”. 

This view of modern history merely dilates upon speculative 
philosophy’s old illusion of the domination of spirit in history. 
Indeed, this passage even shows how pious Jacques le bonhomme in 
all good faith continually takes the world outlook derived from 
Hegel, and which has become traditional for him, as the real world, 
and “manoeuvres” on that basis. What may appear as “his own” and 
“unique” in this passage is the conception of this domination of the 
spirit as a hierarchy — and here, again, we will “include” a brief 
“historical reflection” on the origin of Stirner’s “hierarchy”. 

Hegel speaks of the philosophy of hierarchy in the following 
“transformations” : 

“We have seen in Plato’s Republic the idea that philosophers should govern; now” 
(in the Catholic Middle Ages) “the time has come when it is affirmed that the spiritual 
should dominate-, but the spiritual has acquired the meaning that the clerical, the clergy, 
should dominate. Thus, the spiritual is made a special being, the individual” 




174 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



( Geschichte der Philosophic, III, p. 132). — “Thereby actuality, the mundane, is forsaken by 
God ... a few individual persons are holy, the others unholy” (ibid., p. 136). 
“Godforsakenness” is more closely defined thus: “All these forms” (family, work, 
political life, etc.) “are considered nugatory, unholy” (Philosophie der Religion, II, 
p. 343). — “It is a union with worldliness which is unreconciled, worldliness which is 
crude in itself” (for this Hegel elsewhere also uses the word “barbarism”; cf., for 
example. Geschichte der Philosophie, III, p. 136) “and, being crude in itself, is 
simply subjected to domination.” ( Philosophie der Religion, II, pp. 342, 343). — “This 
domination” (the hierarchy of the Catholic church) “is, therefore, a domination of 
passion, although it should be the domination of the spiritual” ( Geschichte der 
Philosophie, III, p. 134). — “ The true domination of the spirit, however, cannot be 
domination of the spirit in the sense that what opposes it should be something 
subordinate” (ibid., p. 131). — “The true meaning is that the spiritual as such” 
(according to “Stirner” the “holy”) “should be the determining factor, and this has 
been so until our times-, thus, we see in the French Revolution” ( following in the wake of 
Hegel, “Stirner” sees it) “that the abstract idea should dominate : state constitutions and 
laws should be determined by it, it should constitute the bond between people, and 
people should be conscious that that which they hold as valid are abstract ideas, liberty and 
equality, etc.” ( Geschichte der Philosophie, III, p. 132). The true domination of spirit as 
brought about by Protestantism, in contrast to its imperfect form in the Catholic 
hierarchy, is defined further in the sense that “the earthly is made spiritual in 
itself ” ( Geschichte der Philosophie, III, p. 185); “that the divine is realised in the sphere 
of actuality” (the Catholic Godforsaken ness of actuality, therefore, ceases to exist — 
Philosophie der Religion, II, p. 344); that the “contradiction” between holiness 
and worldliness “is resolved in morality” ( Philosophie der Religion, II, p. 343); 
that “moral institutions” (marriage, the family, the state, earning one’s livelihood, 
etc.) are “ divine , holy ” ( Philosophie der Religion, II, p. .344). 

Hegel expresses this true domination of spirit in two forms: 

“State, government, law, property, civic order” (and, as we know from his other 
works, art. science, etc., as well), “all this is the religious... emerging in the form 
of the finite” (Geschichte der Philosophic, III, p. 185). 

And, finally, this domination of the religious, the spiritual, etc., is 
expressed as the domination of philosophy: 

“Consciousness of the spiritual is now” (in the eighteenth centurv) “essentiallv the 
foundation, and thereby domination has passed to philosophy” ( Philosophie der Geschichte, 
p. 440). 

Hegel, therefore, ascribes to the Catholic hierarchy of the Middle 
Ages the intention of wanting “to be the domination of spirit” and 
thereupon regards it as a restricted imperfect form of this 
domination of spirit, the culmination of which he sees in Protestant- 
ism and its alleged further development. However unhistorical this 
may be, nevertheless, Hegel is sufficiently historically-minded not to 
extend the use of the name “hierarchy” beyond the bounds of the 
Middle Ages. But Saint Max knows from this same Hegel that the 
later epoch is the “truth” of the preceding one; hence the epoch of 
the perfect domination of spirit is the truth of that epoch in which 
the domination of spirit was as yet imperfect, so that Protestantism 
is the truth of hierarchy and therefore true hierarchy. Since, 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



175 



however, only true hierarchy deserves to be called hierarchy, 
it is clear that the hierarchy of the Middle Ages had to be 
“weakly”, and it is all the easier for Stirner to prove this since in the 
passages given above and in hundreds of other passages from Hegel 
the imperfection of the domination of spirit in the Middle Ages is 
portrayed. He only needed to copy these out, the whole of his “ own ” 
work consisting in substituting the word “hierarchy” for “domina- 
tion of spirit”. There was no need for him even to formulate the 
simple argument by means of which domination of spirit as such is 
transformed by him into hierarchy, since it has become the fashion 
among German theoreticians to give the name of the cause to the 
effect and, for example, to put back into the category of theology 
everything that has arisen out of theology and has not yet fully 
attained the height of the principles of these theoreticians — e.g., 
Hegelian speculation, Straussian pantheism, etc. — a trick especially 
prevalent in 1842. From the above-quoted passages it also follows 
that Hegel: 1) appraises the French Revolution as a new and more 
perfect phase of this domination of spirit; 2) regards philosophers 
as the rulers of the world of the nineteenth century; 3) maintains 
that now only abstract ideas have validity among people; 4) that he 
already regards marriage, the family, the state, earning one's 
livelihood, civic order, property, etc., as “divine and holy”, as the 
“ religious principle ” and 5) that morality as worldly sanctity or as 
sanctified worldliness is represented as the highest and ultimate 
form of the domination of spirit over the world — all these things are 
repeated word for word in “Stirner”. 

Accordingly there is no need to say or prove anything more 
concerning Stirner’s hierarchy, apart from why Saint Max copied out 
Hegel — a fact, however, for the explanation of which further 
material data are necessarv, and whicji, therefore, is only explicable 
for those who are acquainted with the Berlin atmosphere. It is 
another question how the Hegelian idea of the domination of spirit 
arose, and about this see what has been said above. 3 

Saint Max’s adoption of Hegel’s world domination of the 
philosophers and his transformation of it into a hierarchy are due to 
the extremely uncritical credulity of our saint and to a “holy” or 
unholy ignorance which is content with “seeing through” history 
(i.e., with glancing through Hegel’s historical writings) without trou- 
bling to “know” many “things” about it. In general, he was bound to 
be afraid that as soon as he “learned” he would no longer be able to 
“abolish and dissolve” (p. 96), and, therefore, remain stuck in the 



a See this volume, pp. 59-62. — Ed. 




176 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



“bustling activity of noxious insects” — a sufficient reason not to 
“proceed” to the “abolition and dissolution” of his own ignorance. 

If, like Hegel, one designs such a system for the first time, a system 
embracing the whole of history and the present-day world in all its 
scope, one cannot possibly do so without comprehensive, positive 
knowledge, without great energy and keen insight and without 
dealing at least in some passages with empirical history. On the other 
hand, if one is satisfied with exploiting an already existing pattern, 
transforming it for one’s “own” purposes and demonstrating this 
conception of one’s own by means of isolated examples (e.g., 
Negroes and Mongols, Catholics and Protestants, the French 
Revolution, etc.) — and this is precisely what our warrior against the 
holy does — then absolutely no knowledge of history is necessary. 
The result of all this exploitation inevitably becomes comic; most of 
all comic when a jump is made from the past into the immediate 
present, examples of which we saw already in connection with 
“ whims v”. a 

As for the actual hierarch v of the Middle Ages, we shall merely 
note here that it did not exist for the people, for the great mass of 
human beings. For the great mass only feudalism existed, and 
hierarchy onlv existed insofar as it was itself either feudal or 
anti-feudal (within the framework of feudalism). Feudalism itself had 
entirely empirical relations as its basis. Hierarchy and its struggle 
against feudalism (the struggle of the ideologists of a class against the 
class itself) are only the ideological expression of feudalism and of 
the struggles developing within feudalism itself — which include also 
the struggles of the feudally organised nations among themselves. 
Hierarchy is the ideal form of feudalism; feudalism is the political 
form of the medieval relations of production and intercourse. 
Consequently, the struggle of feudalism against hierarchy can only 
be explained by elucidating these practical material relations. This 
elucidation of itself puts an end to the previous conception of history 
which took the illusions of the Middle Ages on trust, in particular 
those illusions which the Emperor and the Pope brought to bear in 
their struggle against each other. 

Since Saint Max merely reduces the Hegelian abstractions about 
the Middle Ages and hierarchy to “pompous words and paltry 
thoughts”, there is no need to examine in more detail the actual, 
historical hierarchy. 

From the above it is now clear that the trick can also be reversed 
and Catholicism regarded not just as a preliminary stage, but 



a See this volume, pp. 160-63. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



177 



also as the negation of the real hierarchy; in which case Catholi- 
cism =negation of spirit, non-spirit, sensuousness, and then 
one gets the great proposition of Jacques le bonhomme — that the 
Jesuits “saved us from the decay and destruction of sensuousness” 
(p. 1 18). What would have happened to “us” if the “destruction’ ^f 
sensuousness had come to pass, we do not learn. The whole material 
movement since the sixteenth century, which did not save “us” from 
the “decay” of sensuousness, but, on the contrary, developed 
“sensuousness” to a much wider extent, does not exist for 
“Stirner” — it is the Jesuits who brought about all that. Compare, 
incidentally, Hegel’s Philosophic der Geschichte, p. 425. 

By carrying over the old domination of the clerics to modern 
times. Saint Max interprets modern times as “ clericalism and then 
by regarding this domination of the clerics carried over to modern 
times as something distinct from the old medieval clerical domina- 
tion, he depicts it as domination of the ideologists, as “scholasticism ” . 
Thus clericalism= hierarchy as the domination of the spirit, 
scholasticism = the domination of the spirit as hierarchy. 

“Stirner” achieves this simple transition to clericalism — which is no 
transition at all — by means of three weighty transformations. 

Firstly, he “has” the “concept of clericalism” in anyone “who lives 
for a great idea, for a good cause” (still the good cause!), “for a 
doctrine, etc.” 

Secondly, in his world of illusion Stirner “comes up against” the 
“age-old illusion of a world that has not yet learned to dispense with 
clericalism”, namely — “to live and create for the sake of an idea, etc.” 

Thirdly, “it is the domination of the idea, i.e., clericalism”, that is: 
“Robespierre, for example” (for example!), “Saint-Just, and so on” 
(and so on!) “were out-and-out priests”, etc. All three transforma- 
tions in which clericalism is “discovered”, “encountered” and 
“called upon” (all this on p. 100), therefore, express nothing more 
than what Saint Max has already repeatedly told us, namely, the 
domination of spirit, of the idea, of the holy, over “life” (ibid.). 

After the “domination of the idea, i.e., clericalism” has thus been 
foisted upon history, Saint Max can, of course, without difficulty find 
this “clericalism” again in the whole of preceding history, and thus 
depict “Robespierre, for example, Saint-Just, and so on” as priests 
and identify them with Innocent III and Gregory VII, and so all 
uniqueness vanishes in the face of the unique. All of them, properly 
speaking, are merely different names, different disguises for one 
person, “clericalism”, which made all history from the beginning of 
Christianity. As to how, with this sort of conception of history, “all 
cats become grey”, since all historical differences are “abolished” 




178 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



and “resolved” in the “notion of clericalism” — as to this. Saint Max 
at once gives us a striking example in his “Robespierre, ror example, 
Saint- just, and so on”. Here we are first given Robespierre as an 
“example” of Saint-Just, and Saint-just — as an ‘ and-so-on” of 
Robespierre. It is then said: 

“These representatives of holy interests are confronted by a world of innumerable 
'personal', earthly interests.” 

Bv whom were they confronted? By the Girondists and Ther- 
midorians, who (see “for example” R. Levasseur s Memoires, “and so 
on”, “i.e.”, Nougaret, Histoire des prisons ; Barere; “ Deux amis de la 
libei t''” 1 { et du commerce} -. Montgailiard, Histoire de Prance; Madame 
Roland, Appel a ta posterite; T. B. Louvet’s Memoires and even the 
disgusting Essais histonques by Beaulieu, etc., etc., as well as all the 
proceedings before the revolutionary tribunal, ‘ and so on”) 
constantly reproached them, the real representatives ot revolution- 
ary power, i.e., of the class which alone was trulv revolutionary, the 
‘ innumerable” masses, for violating “sacred interests”, the constitu- 
tion, ireedom, equality, the rights of man, republicanism, law, samte 
proprietep “tor example” the division of powers, humanity, morality, 
moderation, “and so on”. They were opposed by all the priests, who 
accused them of violating all the main and secondary items of the 
religious and moral catechism (see “for example” Histoire du clerge de 
Prance pendant la revolution, by M. R. c , Paris, libraire catholique, 1828, 
“and so on”). The historical comment ot the bourgeois that during 
the regne de la terreur “Robespierre, for example, Saint-just, and so 
on” cut off the heads of konnetes gens t; see the numerous writings of 
the simpleton Monsieur Peltier . “for example”. La conspiration ae 
Robespierre bv Montjoie ‘ and so on”) is expressed bv Saint Max in the 
following transformation: 

“because the revolutionary nriests and school-masters served Man, they cut the 
tnroats ol mer ’ 

This, of course, saves Saint Max the trouble of wasting even one 
“unique” little word about the actual, empirical grounds for the 
cutting off of heads — grounds which were based on extremely 
worldly interests, though not, of course, of the stockjobbers, but of 
the “innumerable” masses. An earlier “priest”, Spinoza, already in 
the seventeenth centurv had the brazen audacity to act the “strict 



a Two friends of freedom i,and of commerce). — Ed. 

Sacred properly. — Ed. 
c HippoJvte Regnier d’Estourbet. — Ed. 

Respectable people.— -Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



179 



school-master” of Saint Max, by saying: “Ignorance is no argu- 
ment.” 3 Consequently Saint Max loathes the priest Spinoza to such 
an extent that he accepts his anti-cleric, the priest Leibniz, and for all 
such astonishing phenomena as the terror, “for example”, the 
cutting off of heads, “and so on”, produces “sufficient grounds”, 
viz., that “the ecclesiastics stuffed their heads with something of the 
kind” (p. 98). 

Blessed Max, who has found sufficient grounds for everything (“I 
have now found the ground into which my anchor is eternally 
fastened, ” b in the idea, “for example”, in the “clericalism”, “and so 
on” of “Robespierre, for example, Saint-Just, and so on”, George 
Sand, Proudhon, the chaste Berlin seamstress, 0 etc.) — this blessed 
Max “does not blame the class of the bourgeoisie for having asked its 
egoism how far it should give way to the revolutionary idea as such”. 
For Saint Max “the revolutionary idea” which inspired the habits 
bleus 57 and honnetes gens of 1789 is the same “idea” as that of the 
sansculottes of 1793, the same idea concerning which people 
deliberate whether to “give way” to it — but no further “space 
can be given” d to any “idea” about this point. 

We now come to present-day hierarchy, to the domination of the 
idea in ordinary life. The whole of the second part of “the book” is 
filled with struggle against this “hierarchy”. Therefore we shall deal 
with it in detail when we come to this second part. But since Saint 
Max, as in the section on “whimsy”, takes delight in anticipating his 
ideas here and repeats what comes later in the beginning, as he 
repeats the beginning in what comes later, we are compelled already 
at this point to note a few examples of his hierarchy. His method of 
writing a book is the unique “egoism” which we find in the whole 
book. His self-delight stands in inverse proportion to the delight 
experienced by the reader. 

Since the middle class demand love for their kingdom, their 
regime, they want, according to Jacques le bonhomme, to “establish 
the kingdom of love on earth” (p. 98). Since they demand respect for 
their domination and for the conditions in which it is exercised, and 
therefore want to usurp domination over respect, they demand, 
according to this worthy man, the domination of respect as such, their 
attitude towards respect is the same as towards the holy spirit 
dwelling within them (p. 95). Jacques le bonhomme, with his faith 

a Benedictus Spinoza, Ethica, Pars prima. Appendix. — Ed. 

b The words are from a Protestant hymn. — Ed. 

0 Marie Wilhelmine Dahnhardt. — Ed. 

d In German a pun: Raum geben — to give way, to yield to, and to give space to 
something. — Ed. 




180 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



that can move mountains, takes as the actual, earthly basis of the 
bourgeois world the distorted form in which the sanctimonious and 
hypocritical ideology of the bourgeoisie voices their particular 
interests as universal interests. Why this ideological delusion assumes 
precisely this form for our saint, we shall see in connection with 
“political liberalism”. 3 

Saint Max gives us a new example on page 115, speaking of the 
family. He declares that, although it is very easy to become 
emancipated from the domination of one’s own family, nevertheless, 
“refusal of allegiance easily arouses pangs of conscience”, and so 
people retain family affection, the concept of the family, and 
therefore have the “holy conception of the family”, the “holy” 
(p. 116). 

Here again our good man perceives the domination of the holy 
where entirely empirical relations dominate. The attitude of the 
bourgeois to the institutions of his regime is like that of the Jew to the 
law; he evades them whenever it is possible to do so in each 
individual case, but he wants everyone else to observe them. If the 
entire bourgeoisie, in a mass and at one time, were to evade 
bourgeois institutions, it would cease to be bourgeois — a conduct 
which, of course, never occurs to the bourgeois and by no means 
depends on their willing or running. 58 The dissolute bourgeois 
evades marriage and secretly commits adultery; the merchant evades 
the institution of property by depriving others of property by 
speculation, bankruptcy, etc.; the young bourgeois makes himself 
independent of his own family, if he can by in fact abolishing the 
family as far as he is concerned. But marriage, property, the family 
remain untouched in theory, because they are the practical basis on 
which the bourgeoisie has erected its domination, and because in 
their bourgeois form they are the conditions which make the 
bourgeois a bourgeois, just as the constantly evaded law makes the 
religious Jew a religious Jew. This attitude of the bourgeois to the 
conditions of his existence acquires one of its universal forms in 
bourgeois morality. One cannot speak at all of the family “as such’ 
Historically, the bourgeois gives the family the character of the 
bourgeois family, in which boredom and money are the binding link, 
and which also includes the bourgeois dissolution of the family, 
which does not prevent the family itself from always continuing to 
exist. Its dirty existence has its counterpart in the holy concept of it in 
official phraseology and universal hypocrisy. Where the family is 
actually abolished, as with the proletariat, just the opposite of what 



a See this volume, pp. 193-97. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



181 



“stirner” thinks takes place. There the concept of the family does not 
exist at all, but here and there family affection based on extremely 
real relations is certainly to be found. In the eighteenth century the 
concept of the family was abolished by the philosophers, because the 
actual family was already in process of dissolution at the highest 
pinnacles of civilisation. The internal family bond, the separate 
components constituting the concept of the family were dissolved, 
for example, obedience, piety, fidelity in marriage, etc.; but the real 
body of the family, the property relation, the exclusive attitude in 
relation to other families, forced cohabitation — relations determined 
by the existence of children, the structure of modern towns, the 
formation of capital, etc. — all these were preserved, although with 
numerous violations, because the existence of the family is made 
necessary by its connection with the mode of production, which 
exists independently of the will of bourgeois society. That it was 
impossible to do without it was demonstrated in the most striking 
way during the French Revolution, when for a moment the family 
was as good as legally abolished. The family continues to exist even in 
the nineteenth century, only the process of its dissolution has become 
more general, not on account of the concept, but because of the 
higher development of industry and competition; the family still 
exists although its dissolution was long ago proclaimed by French 
and English socialists and this has at last penetrated also to the 
German church fathers, by way of French novels. 

One other example of the domination of the idea in everyday life. 
Since school-masters may be told to find consolation for their scanty 
pay in the holiness of the cause they serve (which could only occur in 
Germany), Jacques le bonhomme actually believes that such talk is 
the reason for their low salaries (p. 100). He believes that “the.holy” 
in the present-day bourgeois world has an actual money value, he 
believes that the meagre funds of the Prussian state (see, inter alia, 
Browning on this subject 3 ) would be so increased by the abolition of 
“the holy” that every village school-master could suddenly be paid a 
ministerial salary. 

This is the hierarchy of nonsense. 

The “keystone of the magnificent cathedral” — as the great 
Michelet b puts it — of hierarchy is “sometimes” the work of “One” 



a G. Browning, The domestic and financial Condition of Great Britain; preceded by a 
Brief Sketch of her Foreign Policy; and of the Statistics and Politics of France, Russia, Austria 
and Prussia . — Ed. 

b Carl Ludwig Michelet, Geschichte der letzten Systeme der Philosophie in Deutschland 
von Kant bis Hegel . — Ed. 




r\.arj Marx and Frederick Engels 



1 8 . 



“Ove sometime 1 ; divides people into two classes, the educated and the uneducated.” 
'One sometimes divides aoes into two classes, the taiied and the tailless.) “The former 
insofar as the' - were worthv of tneir name, occupied themselves witn thoughts, with 
the spirit.” Thev 4 dominated in the post-Chrisuan epoch and tor their thoughts they 
demanded ... respect” The uneducated (the animal, the child, the Negro; are 
‘ powerless” against thoughts and ‘ are dominated bv them. That is the meaning of 
nierarchv ” 

The ‘ educated’’ (the youth, the Mongol, the modern) are, 
therefore, again onh occupied with “spirit”, pure thought, etc.; they 
are metaphysicians by profession, in the final analysis Hegelians. 
“Hence” the “uneducated” are the non-Hegehans. a Hegei was 
indubitabiv ‘ the most educated” Hegelian and therefore in his case 
it must “become apparent what a longing for things particularly tne 
most educated man possesses”. The point is that the ' educated’ anti 
uneducated” are within themselves in conflict with each other 
indeed, in every man the ‘ uneducated’ is in conflict with the 
“educated”. And since the greatest longing for things, i.e., for that 
which belongs to the ‘ uneducated’ , becomes apparent m Hegel, ir 
also becomes apparent here that “the most educated” man is at the 
same time “the most uneducated’ 

"There” {in Hegel; ‘reality should be completer- in accordance with thought and 
no concept be without realise 

This should read: there the ordinary idea of reality should receive 
its complete philosophical expression, while Hegei imagines, on the 
contrary, that “consequently” every philosophical expression creates 
the reality that is in accordance with it. Jacques ie bonhomme takes 
Hegel's illusion about his own philosophy ior the genuine com of 
Hegelian pfniosophv 

The Hegelian philosophy, which in the form of the domination of 
the Hegelians over the non-Hegelians appears as the crown of the 
hierarchy, now conquers the last world empire. 

" Hegel’ , svsiem was >.he supreme despotism and autocracy ot thought, the 
omnipotent e and aimightiness of the spin ” t> 9 7 

Here, therefore, we find ourselves in the realm of spirits of 
Hegelian philosophy, which stretches from Berlin to Halle and 
Tubingen, the realm of spirits whose history was written by Herr 
Bavrhoffer" and lor which the great Michelet collected the 
statistical uafa. 



Here the authors ironically use Berlin dialect words for educated, uneducated 
and most educated (Jebildete, Unjebildete, Allerjebildetste). — Ed. 

Karl Theodor Bavrhoffer, Die Idee und Geschichte der Philosophie. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



183 



The preparation for this realm of spirits was the French 
Revolution, which “ did nothing but transform things into ideas about 
things ” (p. 115; cf. above Hegel on the revolution, p. 

“So people remained citizens” (in “Stirner”, this occurs earlier, 
but “what Stirner says is not what he has in mind, and what he has in 
mind cannot be said”, Wigand, p. 149) and “lived in reflection , they 
had their eye on an object, before which” ( per appos .) “they felt 
reverence and fear”. “Stirner” says in a passage on page 98: “The 
road to hell is paved with good intentions.” But we say: the road to 
the unique is paved with bad concluding clauses b , with appositions, 
which are his “heavenly ladder” borrowed from the Chinese, and his 
“rope of the objective” (p. 88) on which he makes his “flea- 
jumps”. In accordance with this, for “modern philosophy or modern 
times” — since the emergence of the realm of spirits modern times 
are indeed nothing but modern philosophy — it is an easy matter to 
“transform the existing objects into notional objects, i.e., into con- 
cepts”, page 114, a work which Saint Max continues. 

We have already seen our knight of the rueful countenance even 
“before the mountains were brought forth”/ which he later moved 
by his faith, right at the beginning of his book, galloping headlong 
towards the great result of his “magnificent cathedral”. His 
“donkey”, apposition, could not jump swiftly enough for him; now, 
at last, on page 114, he has reached his goal and by means of a 
mighty “or” has transformed modern times into modern philosophy. 

Thereby ancient times (i.e., the ancient and modern, Negroid and 
Mongolian but, properly speaking, only pre-Stirnerian times) 
“reached their final goal”. We can now reveal why Saint Max gave 
the title “Man” to the whole of the first part of his book and made 
out his entire history of miracles, ghosts and knights to be the history 
of “man”. The ideas and thoughts of people were, of course, ideas 
and thoughts about themselves and their relationships, their 
consciousness of themselves and of people in general — for it was the 
consciousness not merely of a single individual but of the individual 
in his interconnection with the whole of society and about the whole 
of the society in which they lived. The conditions, independent of 
them, in which they produced their life, the necessary forms of 
intercourse connected herewith, and the personal and social 
relations thereby given, had to take the form — insofar as they were 



a See this volume, pp. 174-75. — Ed. 

b In German a pun: Vorsatze — intentions, and Nachsatze — concluding clauses, 
conclusions. — Ed. 

c Psalms 90:2. — Ed. 



8—2086 




184 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



expressed in thoughts — of ideal conditions and necessary relations, 
i.e., they had to be expressed in consciousness as determina- 
tions arising from the concept of man as such , from human essence, 
from the nature of man, from man as such. What people were, what 
their relations were, appeared in consciousness as ideas of man as 
such , of his modes of existence or of his immediate conceptual 
determinations. So, after the ideologists had assumed that ideas and 
thoughts had dominated history up to now, that the history of these 
ideas and thoughts constitutes all history up to now, after they had 
imagined that real conditions had conformed to man as such and his 
ideal conditions, i.e., to conceptual determinations, after they had 
made the history of people’s consciousness of themselves the basis of 
their actual history, after all this, nothing was easier than to call the 
history of consciousness, of ideas, of the holy, of established con- 
cepts — the history of “man” and to put it in the place of real history. 
The only distinction between Saint Max and all his predecessors 
is that he knows nothing about these concepts — even in their arbitrary 
isolation from real life, whose products they were — and his trivial 
creative work in his copy of Hegelian ideology is restricted to 
establishing his ignorance even of what he copies. — It is already 
evident from this how he can counterpose the history of the real 
individual in the form of the unique to his fantasy about the history of 
man. 

The unique history takes place at the beginning in the Stoa in 
Athens, later almost wholly in Germany, and finally at the 
Kupfergraben 59 in Berlin, where the despot of “modern philosophy 
or modern times” set up his imperial residence. That already shows 
how exclusively national and local is the matter dealt with. Instead of 
world history, Saint Max gives a few and, what is more, extremely 
meagre and biased comments on the history of German theology and 
philosophy. If on occasion we appear to go outside Germany, it is 
only in order to cause the deeds and thoughts of other peoples, e.g., 
the French Revolution, to “reach their final goal” in Germany, 
namely, at the Kupfergraben. Only national-German facts are given, 
they are dealt with and interpreted in a national-German manner, 
and the result remains a national-German one. But even that is not 
enough. The views and education of our saint are not only German, 
but of a Berlin nature through and through. The role allotted to 
Hegelian philosophy is that which it plays in Berlin, and Stirner 
confuses Berlin with the world and world history. The “youth” is a 
Berliner; the good citizens that we encounter throughout the book 
are Berlin beer-drinking philistines. With such premises for the 
starting-point, it is natural that the result arrived at is merely one 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



185 



confined within the national and local framework. “Stirner” and his 
whole philosophical fraternity, among whom he is the weakest and 
most ignorant member, afford a practical commentary to the valiant 
lines of the valiant Hoffmann von Fallersleben: 

In Germany alone, in Germany alone. 

Would I for ever live. a 



The local Berlin conclusion of our valiant saint — that in Hegelian 
philosophy the world has “all gone” — enables him now without 
much expense to arrive at a universal empire of his “own”. The 
Hegelian philosophy transformed everything into thought, into the 
holy, into apparition, into spirit, into spirits, into spectres. “Stirner” 
will fight against them, he will conquer them in his imagination and 
will erect on their dead bodies his “own”, “unique”, “corporeal” 
empire, the empire of the “whole fellow”. 

“For we wrestle not against flesh and blood, but against principalities, against powers, 
against the rulers o( the darkness of this world, against spiritual wickedness in high places” 
(Ephesians 6:12). 

Now “Stirner” has his “feet shod with the preparation” for waging 
the fight against thoughts. He has no need first to “take the shield of 
faith”, for he has never laid it down. Armed with the “helmet” of 
disaster and the “sword” of spiritlessness (see ibid . b ), he goes into 
battle. “And it was given unto him to make war with the holy” but 
not “to overcome” it. (Revelation of St. John 13:7.) 

5. “ Stirner ” Delighted in His Construction 

We now find ourselves again exactly where we were on page 19 in 
connection with the youth, who became the man, and on page 90 in 
connection with the Mongoloid Caucasian, who was transformed 
into the Caucasian Caucasian and “found himself”. We are, 
therefore, at the third self-finding of the mysterious individual 
whose “arduous life struggle” Saint Max depicts for us. Only the 
whole story is now behind us, and, in view of the extensive material 
we have worked through, we must take a retrospective look at the 
gigantic corpse of the ruined man. 

Though on a later page, where he has long ago forgotten his 
history, Saint Max asserts that “genius has long since been regarded 
as the creator of new world -historic productions” (p. 214), we have 



a From the poem Auf der Wanderung by Hoffmann von Fallersleben. — Ed. 
b Ephesians 6 : 15, 16, 17 (paraphrased). — Ed. 




186 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



already seen that even his bitterest enemies cannot revile his history 
on that score, at any rate, for in it no individuals, let alone geniuses, 
make their appearance, but only ossified, crippled thoughts and 
Hegelian changelings. 

Repetitio est mater studiorum . a Saint Max, who expounded his whole 
history of “philosophy or time” only in order to find an opportunity 
for a few hurried studies of Hegel, finally repeats once again his 
whole unique history. However, he does it with a turn towards 
natural history, offering us important information about “unique” 
natural science, the reason being that for him, whenever the “world” 
has to play an important role, it immediately becomes transformed 
into nature. “Unique” natural science begins at once with the 
admission of its impotence. It does not examine the actual relation of 
man to nature, determined bv industry and natural science, but 
proclaims a fantastic relation of man to nature. 

“How little can man conquer! He has to allow the sun to trace its course, the sea to 
roll its waves, the mountains to tower to the sky” (p. 122). 

Saint Max who, like all saints, loves miracles, but can only perform 
a logical miracle, is annoyed because he cannot make the sun dance 
the cancan, he grieves because he cannot still the ocean, he is 
indignant because he must allow the mountains to tower to the sky. 
Although on page 124 the world already becomes “prosaic” at the 
end of antiquity, it is still, for our saint, highly unprosaic. For him it 
still is the “sun” and not the earth that traces its course, and to his 
sorrow he cannot a la Joshua command “sun, stand thou still”. b On 
page 123, Stirner discovers that 

at the end of the ancient world, “spirit” “again foamed and frothed over irresistib- 
ly because gases ” (spirits) “developed within it and, after the mechanical impact from 
outside became ineffective, chemical tensions, which stimulate in the interior, began 
to come into wonderful play”. 

This sentence contains the most important data of the “unique” 
philosophy of nature, which on the previous page had already ar- 
rived at the conclusion that for man nature is the “unconquerable”. 
Earthly physics knows nothing about a mechanical impact which 
becomes ineffective — unique physics alone has the merit of this 
discovery. Earthly chemistry knows no “gases” which stimulate 
“chemical tensions” and, what is more, “in the interior”. Gases 
which enter into new combinations, into new chemical relations, do 
not stimulate any “tensions”, but at most lead to a fall of tension, 



* Repetition is the mother of learning. — Ed. 
Joshua 10 : 12. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



187 



insofar as they pass mto a liquid state of aggregation and thereby 
their volume decreases to something less than one-thousandth of 
their former volume. If Saint Max feels “tensions” “in” his own 
“interior” due to “gases”, these are highly “mechanical impacts”, 
and by no means “chemical tensions”. They are produced by a 
chemical transformation, determined by physiological causes, of 
certain mixtures into others, whereby part of the constituents of the 
former mixture becomes gaseous, therefore, occupies a larger 
volume and, in the absence of space for it, causes a “mechanical 
impact” or pressure towards the outside. [That] these nonexistent 
“chemical tensions” “come” into extremely “wonderful play” in 
Saint Max’s “interior”, namely, this time in his head, “we see" from 
the role they play in “unique” natural science. Incidentally, it is to be 
desired that Saint Max would no longer withhold from the profane 
natural scientists what nonsense he has in mind with the crazy 
expression “chemical tensions”, which moreover “stimulate in the 
interior” (as though a “mechanical impact” on the stomach does not 
“stimulate it in the interior” as well). 

Saint Max wrote his “unique” natural science only because on this 
occasion he was unable to touch on the ancients in decent fashion 
without at the same time letting fall a few words about the “world of 
things”, about nature. 

At the end of the ancient world the ancients, we are assured here, 
are all transformed into Stoics, “whom no collapse of the world” 
(how many times is it supposed to have collapsed?) “could put out of 
countenance” (p. 123). Thus, the ancients become Chinese, who also 
“cannot be thrown down from the heavens of their tranquillity by 
any unforeseen event” (or idea 3 ) (p. 90). Indeed, Jacques le 
bonhomme seriously believes that against the last of the ancients “the 
mechanical impact from outside became ineffective”. How far this 
corresponds to the actual situation of the Romans and Greeks at the 
end of the ancient world, to their complete lack of stability and 
confidence, which could hardly oppose any remnant of vis inertiae to 
the “mechanical impact” — on this point compare, inter alia, Lucian. 
The powerful mechanical shocks which the Roman empire received 
as a result of its division among several Caesars and their wars 
against one another, as a result of the colossal concentration of 
property, particularly landed property, in Rome, and the decrease in 
Italy’s population caused by this, and as a result of the [pressure of 
the] Huns and Teutons — these shocks, in the opinion of our saintly 



a In the German original a pun: Fall — event— and FAnfall, which can mean 
idea, brain wave, invasion or collapse. — Kd. 




188 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



historian, “became ineffective”; only the “chemical tensions”, only 
the “gases” which Christianity “stimulated in the interior” over- 
threw the Roman Empire. The great earthquakes [in the West] and 
in the East, and other “mechanical impacts” which buried hundreds 
of thousands of people under the [ruins] of their towns and [which 
by no] means left the consciousness of people unchanged, were 
presumably, according to “Stirner”, also “ineffective” or were 
chemical tensions. And “in fact ” (!) “ancient history ends in this, that 
I have made the world my property” — which is proved by means of 
the biblical saying: “All things are delivered unto me” (i.e., Christ) 
“of my Father.” 3 Here, therefore, I = Christ. In this connection, 
Jacques le bonhomme cannot refrain from believing the Christian 
that he could move mountains, etc., if he “only wanted to”. As a 
Christian he proclaims himself the lord of the world, but he is this 
only as a Christian ; he proclaims himself the “owner of the world”. 
“Thereby egoism won its first full victory, since I elevated myself to 
be the owner of the world” (p. 124). In order to rise to the level of 
the perfect Christian, Sdrner’s ego had only to carry through the 
struggle to become poor in spirit as well (which he succeeded in doing 
even before the mountains arose). “Blessed are the poor in spirit: for 
theirs is the kingdom of heaven.” 5 Saint Max has reached perfection 
as regards poverty of spirit and even boasts of it in his great rejoicing 
before the Lord. 

Saint Max, poor in spirit, believes in the fantastic gas formations of 
the Christians arising from the decomposition of the ancient world. 
The ancient Christian owned nothing in this world and was, 
therefore, satisfied with his imaginary heavenly property and his 
divine right to ownership. Instead of making the world the 
possession of the people, he proclaimed himself and his ragged 
fraternity to be “God’s own possession” (1 Peter 2:9). According 
to “Stirner”, the Christian idea of the world is the world into which 
the ancient world is actually dissolved, although this is at most [a 
world] of fantasy into which the world of ancient ideas has [been 
transformed] and in which the Christian [by faith] can move 
mountains, can feel [all-powerful] and press forward to a position 
where the “mechanical impact is ineffective”. Since for “Stirner” 
people are no longer determined by the [external] world, are no 
longer driven forward by the mechanical impact of the need to 
produce, since, in general, the mechanical impact, and with it the 
sexual act as well, has ceased to operate, it is only by a miracle that 



a . Matthew 11 : 27 .— Ed. 
b Matthew 5 : 3.— Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



189 



they have been able to continue to exist. Of course, for German prigs 
and school-masters with a gaseous content like that of “Stirner”, it is 
far easier to be satisfied with the Christian fantasy about proper- 
ty — which is truly nothing but the property of Christian fan- 
tasy — than to describe the transformation of the real property 
relations and production relations of the ancient world. 

That same primitive Christian who, in the imagination of Jacques 
le bonhomme, was the owner of the ancient world, actually belonged 
for the most part to the world of owners; he was a slave and could be 
sold on the market. But “Stirner”, delighted in his construction, 
irrepressibly continues his rejoicing. 

“The first property, the first splendour has been won!” (p. 124). 

In the same way, Stirner’s egoism continues to gain property and 
splendour and to achieve “complete victories”. The theological 
attitude of the primitive Christian to the ancient world is the perfect 
prototype of all his property and all his splendour. 

The following are the grounds given for this property of the 
Christian: 

“The world has lost its divine character ... it has become prosaic, it is my property, 
which I dispose of as I (viz., the spirit) choose” (p. 124). 

This means: the world has lost its divine character, therefore, it is 
freed from my fantasies for my own consciousness; it has become 
prosaic, consequently its relation to me is prosaic and it disposes of 
me in the prosaic way it favours, by no means to please me. Apart 
from the fact that “Stirner” here actually thinks that in ancient times 
the prosaic world did not exist and the divine principle held sway in 
the world, he even falsifies the Christian concept, which continually 
bemoans its impotence in relation to the world, and itself depicts its 
victory over the world in its fantasy as merely an ideal one, by 
transferring it to the day of judgment. Only when a great secular 
power took possession of Christianity and exploited it, whereupon, 
of course, it ceased to be unworldly, could Christianity imagine itself 
to be the owner of the world. Saint Max ascribes to the Christian the 
same false relation to the ancient world as he ascribes to the youth 
with regard to the “world of the child”; he puts the egoist in the 
same relation to the world of the Christian as he puts the man to the 
world of the youth. 

The Christian has now nothing more to do than to become poor in 
spirit as quickly as possible and perceive the world of spirit in all its 
vanity — just as he did with the world of things — in order to be able to 
“dispose as he chooses” of the world of spirit also, whereby he 
becomes a perfect Christian, an egoist. The attitude of the Christian 




190 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



to the ancient world serves, therefore, as the standard for the 
attitude of the egoist to the modern world. The preparation for this 
spiritual poverty was the content of “almost two thousand years” of 
life — a life whose main epochs, of course, took place only in 
Germany. 

“After various transformations the holy spirit in the course of time became the absolute 
idea, which again in manifold refractions split up into the various ideas of love of 
mankind, civic virtue, rationality, etc.” (pp. 125, 126). 

The German stay-at-home again turns the thing upside-down. 
The ideas of love of mankind, etc. — coins whose impressions had 
already been totally worn away, particularly owing to their great 
circulation in the eighteenth century — were recast by Hegel in the 
sublimate of the absolute idea, but after this remindng they were just 
as little successful in retaining their value abroad as Prussian paper 
money. 

The consistent conclusion — which has already appeared again and 
again — of Stirner’s view of history is as follows: 

“Concepts should play the decisive role everywhere, concepts should regulate life, 
concepts should rule. That is the religious world to which Hegel gave systematic 
expression” (p. 126), 

and which our good-natured philistine so much mistakes for 
the real world that on the following page (p. 127) he can say: 

“Now nothing but spirit rules in the world.” 

Stuck fast in this world of illusion, he can (on p. 128) build first of 
all an “altar” and then “erect a church” “round this altar”, a church 
whose “walls” have legs for making progress and “move ever farther 
forward”. “Soon this church embraces the whole earth.” He, the 
unique, and Szeliga, his servant, stand outside, they “wander round 
these walls, and are driven out to the very edge”. “Howling with 
agonising hunger”, Saint Max calls to his servant: “One step more 
and the world of the holy has conquered.” But Szeliga suddenly 
“ sinks into the outermost abyss”, which lies above him — a literary 
miracle! For, since the earth is a sphere, the abyss can only lie above 
Szeliga as soon as the church embraces the whole earth. So he 
reverses the laws of gravity, ascends backwards into heaven and 
thereby reflects honour on “unique” natural science, which is all the 
easier for him since, according to page 126, “the nature of the thing 
and the concept of relation” are a matter of indifference to 
“Stirner”, “do not guide him in his treatment or conclusion”, and 
the “relationship into which” Szeliga “entered” with gravity “is itself 
unique” by virtue of Szeliga’s “uniqueness”, and by no means 
“depends” on the nature of gravity or on how “others”, for instance, 
natural scientists, “classify it”. “Stirner” moreover objects to 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



191 



Szeliga’s “action being separated from the real” Szeliga and 
“assessed according to human standards”. 

Having thus arranged for decent accommodation in heaven for his 
faithful servant, Saint Max passes on to the subject of his own 
passion. On page 95 he discovers that even the “gallows” has the 
“colour of the holy”; “people loathe coming into contact with it, 
there is something uncanny, i.e., unfamiliar, strange about it”. In 
order to transcend this strangeness of the gallows, he transforms it 
into his own gallows, which he can only do by hanging himself on it. 
The lion of Juda makes also this last sacrifice to egoism. 3 The holy 
Christian allows himself to be nailed to the cross, not to redeem the 
cross, but to redeem people from their impiety; the unholy Christian 
hangs himself on the gallows in order to redeem the gallows from 
holiness or to redeem himself from the strangeness of the gallows. 



“The first splendour, the first property has been won, the first 
complete victory achieved!” The holy warrior has now conquered 
history, he has transformed it into thoughts, pure thoughts, which 
are nothing but thoughts — and at the end of time only a host of 
thoughts confront him. And so Saint Max, having taken his 
“gallows” on his back, just like an ass that carries a cross, and his 
servant Szeliga, who was welcomed in heaven with kicks and has 
returned to his master with his head hanging, set out to fight against 
this host of thoughts or, rather, against the mere halo of these 
thoughts. This time it is Sancho Panza, full of moral sayings, maxims 
and proverbs, who takes on himself the struggle against the holy, and 
Don Quixote plays the role of his pious and faithful servant. The 
honest Sancho fights just as bravely as the caballero Manchego h d id in 
the old days, and like him does not fail several times to mistake a 
herd of Mongolian sheep for a swarm of spectres. The plump 
Maritornes “in the course of time, after various transformations in 
manifold refractions”, is transformed into a chaste Berlin seam- 
stress/ dying of anaemia, a subject on which Saint Sancho composes 
an elegy, one which causes all young graduates and Guards lieu- 
tenants to remember Rabelais’ statement that the world-liberating 
“soldier’s prime weapon is the flap of his trousers”. d 

Sancho Panza achieves his heroic feats by perceiving the entire 
opposing host of thoughts in its nullity and vanity. All his great deed 

3 Gf. Revelation of John 5:5. — Ed. 

h Knight of La Mancha, i.e., Don Quixote. — Ed. 

c Marie Wilhelmine Dahnhardt. — Ed. 

d Cf. the heading of Chapter 8, Book 3 of Rabelais’ Gargantua and Pantagruel. — Ed. 




192 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



is confined to mere perception which in the end leaves everything 
existing as it was, changing only his conception, and that not even of 
things, but of philosophical phrases about things. 

Thus, after the ancients have been presented realistically as child, 
Negro, Negroid Caucasians, animal, Catholics, English philosophy, 
the uneducated, non-Hegelians, and the world of things, and the 
moderns have been presented idealistically as youth, Mongol, 
Mongoloid Caucasians, man, Protestants, German philosophy, the 
educated, Hegelians, and the world of thoughts — after everything 
has happened that was from time immemorial decided in the Coun- 
cil of Guardians, the time has at last arrived. The negative unity of 
the ancient and the modern, which has already figured as the man, 
the Caucasian, the Caucasian Caucasian, the perfect Christian, in 
servant’s clothing, seen “through a glass darkly” (1 Corinthians 
13:12), can now, after the passion and death of Stirner on the gallows 
and Szeliga’s ascent to heaven in full glory, return to the simplest 
nomenclature and appear in the clouds of heaven endowed with 
great power and majesty. 3 “And so it is said”: what was previously 
“One” (see “Economy of the Old Testament”) has become 
“ego” — the negative unity of realism and idealism, of the world of 
things and the world of spirit. Schelling calls this unity of realism and 
idealism “indifference” or, rendered in the Berlin dialect, “Jleich- 
jiltigkeit ; in Hegel it becomes the negative unity in which the two 
moments are transcended. Saint Max who, being a proper German 
speculative philosopher, is still tormented by the “unity of oppo- 
sites”, is not satisfied with this; he wants this unity to be visible to him 
in the form of a “corporeal individual”, in a “whole fellow”, and he 
is encouraged in this by Feuerbach’s views expressed in the Anekdota h 
and in the Philosophie der Zukunft. This “ego” of Stirner’s which is the 
final outcome of the hitherto existing world is, therefore, not a 
“corporeal individual”, but a category constructed on the Hegelian 
method and supported by appositions, the further “flea-jumps” of 
which we shall trace in the New Testament. Here we shall merely add 
that in the final analysis this ego comes into existence because it has 
the same illusions about the world of the Christian as the Christian 
has about the world of things. Just as the Christian takes possession 
of the world of things by “getting into his head” fantastic nonsense 
about them, so the “ego”takes possession of the Christian world, the 
world of thoughts, by means of a series of fantastic ideas about it. 
What the Christian imagines about his own relation to the world, 



a Cf. Matthew 24:30.— Ed. 

b Ludwig Feuerbach, “VorlaufigeThesen zur Reformation der Philosophie” . — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



193 



“Stirner” accepts in good faith, finds excellent, and good-naturedly 
repeats after him. 

“Therefore we conclude that a man is justified by faith without the deeds ” (Epistle to 
the Romans 3 : 28). 

Hegel, for whom the modern world was also resolved into the 
world of abstract ideas, defines the task of the modern philosopher, 
in contrast to that of the ancient, as consisting in the following: 
instead of, like the ancients, freeing himself from “natural 
consciousness” and “purging the individual of the immediate, 
sensuous method and making him into conceived and thinking 
substance” (into spirit), the modern philosopher should “abolish 
firm, definite, fixed ideas”. This, he adds, is accomplished by 
“dialectics” ( Phanomenologie , pp. 26, 27). The difference between 
“Stirner” and Hegel is that the former achieves the same thing 
without the help of dialectics. 

6. The Free Ones 

What role “the free ones” have to play here is stated in the 
economy of the Old Testament. We cannot help it that the ego, 
which we had approached so closely, now recedes from us again into 
the nebulous distance. It is not at all our fault that we did not pass at 
once to the ego from page 20 of “the book”. 

A. Political Liberalism 

The key to the criticism of liberalism advanced by Saint Max and 
his predecessors is the history of the German bourgeoisie. We shall 
call special attention to some aspects of this history since the French 
Revolution. 

The state of affairs in Germany at the end of the last century is 
fully reflected in Kant’s Critik der practischen Vernunft. While the 
French bourgeoisie, by means of the most colossal revolution that 
history has ever known, was achieving domination and conquering 
the Continent of Europe, while the already politically emancipated 
English bourgeoisie was revolutionising industry and subjugating 
India politically, and all the rest of the world commercially, the 
impotent German burghers did not get any further than “good will”. 
Kant was satisfied with “good will” alone, even if it remained entirely 
without result, and he transferred the realisation of this good will, the 
harmony between it and the needs and impulses of individuals, to the 
world beyond. Kant’s good will fully corresponds to the impotence, 
depression and wretchedness of the German burghers, whose petty 




194 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



interests were never capable of developing into the common, 
national interests of a class and who were, therefore, constantly 
exploited by the bourgeois of all other nations. These petty, local 
interests had as their counterpart, on the one hand, the truly local 
and provincial narrow-mindedness of the German burghers and, on 
the other hand, their cosmopolitan swollen-headedness. In general, 
from the time of the Reformation German development has borne a 
completely petty-bourgeois character. The old feudal aristocracy 
was, for the most part, annihilated in the peasant wars; what remain- 
ed of it were either imperial petty princes who gradually achieved a 
certain independence and aped the absolute monarchy on a minute, 
provincial scale, or lesser landowners who partly squandered their 
little bit of property at the tiny courts, and then gained their 
livelihood from petty positions in the small armies and government 
offices — or, finally, Junkers from the backwoods, who lived a life of 
which even the most modest English squire 3 or French gentilhomme de 
province would have been ashamed. Agriculture was carried on by a 
method which was neither parcellation nor large-scale production, 
and which, despite the preservation of feudal dependence and 
corvees, never drove the peasants to seek emancipation, both 
because this method of farming did not allow the emergence of any 
active revolutionary class and because of the absence of the 
revolutionary bourgeoisie corresponding to such a peasant class. 

As regards the middle class, we can only emphasise here a few 
significant factors. It is significant that linen manufacture, i.e., an 
industry based on the spinning wheel and the hand-loom, came to be 
of some importance in Germany at the very time when in England 
those cumbersome tools were already being ousted by machines. 
Most characteristic of all is the position of the German middle class in 
relation to Holland. Holland, the only part of the Hanseatic League 60 
that became commercially important, tore itself free, cut Germany 
off from world trade except for two ports (Hamburg and Bremen) 
and since then dominated the whole of German trade. The German 
middle class was too impotent to set limits to exploitation by the 
Dutch. The bourgeoisie of little Holland, with its well-developed 
class interests, was more powerful than the far more numerous 
German middle class with its indifference and its divided petty 
interests. The fragmentation of interests was matched by the 
fragmentation of political organisation, the division into small 
principalities and free imperial cities. How could political concentra- 
tion arise in a country which lacked all the economic conditions for it? 



a Marx and Engels use the English word.— Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



195 



The impotence of each separate sphere of life (one can speak here 
neither of estates nor of classes, but at most of former estates and 
classes not yet born) did not allow any one of them to gain exclusive 
domination. The inevitable consequence was that during the epoch 
of absolute monarchy, which assumed here its most stunted, 
semi-patriarchal form, the special sphere which, owing to division of 
labour, was responsible for the administration of public interests 
acquired an abnormal independence, which became still greater in 
the bureaucracy of modern times. Thus, the state built itself up into 
an apparently independent force, and this position, which in other 
countries was only transitory — a transition stage— it has maintained 
in Germany until the present day. This position of the state explains 
both the conscientiousness of the civil servant, which is found 
nowhere else, and all the illusions about the state which are current 
in Germany, as well as the apparent independence of German 
theoreticians in relation to the middle class — the seeming contradic- 
tion between the form in which these theoreticians express the 
interests of the middle class and these interests themselves. 

The characteristic form which French liberalism, based on real 
class interests, assumed in Germany we find again in Kant. Neither 
he, nor the German middle class, whose whitewashing spokesman he 
was, noticed that these theoretical ideas of the bourgeoisie had as 
their basis material interests and a will that was conditioned and 
determined by the material relations of production. Kant, there- 
fore, separated this theoretical expression from the interests which it 
expressed; he made the materially motivated determinations of the 
will of the French bourgeois into pure self-determinations of “ free 
will ”, of the will in and for itself, of the human will, and so converted 
it into purely ideological conceptual determinations and moral 
postulates. Hence the German petty bourgeois recoiled in horror 
from the practice of this energetic bourgeois liberalism as soon as this 
practice showed itself, both in the Reign of Terror and in shameless 
bourgeois profit-making. 

Under the rule of Napoleon, the German middle class pushed its 
petty trade and its great illusions still further. As regards the 
petty-trading spirit which predominated in Germany at that time, 
Saint Sancho can, inter alia, compare Jean Paul, to mention only 
works of fiction, since they are the only source open to him. The 
German citizens, who railed against Napoleon for compelling them 
to drink chicory 61 and for disturbing their peace with military 
billeting and recruiting of conscripts, reserved all their moral 
indignation for Napoleon and all their admiration for England; yet 
Napoleon rendered them the greatest services by cleaning out 




196 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



Germany’s Augean stables and establishing civilised means of 
communication, whereas the English only waited for the opportunity 
to exploit them a tort et a traverse In the same petty-bourgeois spirit 
the German princes imagined they were fighting for the principle of 
legitimism and against revolution, whereas they were only the paid 
mercenaries of the English bourgeoisie. In the atmosphere of these 
universal illusions it was quite in the order of things that the estates 
privileged to cherish illusions — ideologists, school-masters, students, 
members of the Tugendbund ’ 2 — should talk big and give a suitable 
highflown expression to the universal mood of fantasy and 
indifference. 

The political forms corresponding to a developed bourgeoisie 
were passed on to the Germans from outside by the July 
revolution 6 — as we mention only a few main points we omit the 
intermediary period. Since German economic relations had by no 
means reached the stage of development to which these political 
forms corresponded, the middle class accepted them merely as 
abstract ideas, principles valid in and for themselves, pious wishes 
and phrases, Kantian self-determinations of the will and of human 
beings as they ought to be. Consequently their attitude to these forms 
was far more moral and disinterested than that of other nations, i.e., 
they exhibited a highly peculiar narrow-mindedness and remained 
unsuccessful in all their endeavours. 

Finally the ever more powerful foreign competition and world 
intercourse — from which it became less and less possible for 
Germany to stand aside — compelled the diverse local interests in 
Germany to adopt some sort of common attitude. Particularly since 
1840, the German middle class began to think about safeguarding 
these common interests; its attitude became national and liberal and 
it demanded protective tariffs and constitutions. Thus it has now got 
almost as far as the French bourgeoisie in 1789. 

If, like the Berlin ideologists, one judges liberalism and the state 
within the framework of local German impressions, or limits oneself 
merely to criticism of German-bourgeois illusions about liberalism, 
instead of seeing the correlation of liberalism with the real interests 
from which it originated and without which it cannot really 
exist — then, of course, one arrives at the most banal conclusions. 
This German liberalism, in the form in which it expressed itself up to 
the most recent period, is, as we have seen, even in its popular form, 
empty enthusiasm, ideological reflections about real liberalism. How 
easy it is, therefore, to transform its content wholly into philosophy, 



At random, recklessly. — Ed. 
1830— Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



197 



into pure conceptual determinations, into “rational cognition”! 
Hence if one is so unfortunate as to know even this bourgeoisified 
liberalism only in the sublimated form given it by Hegel and the 
school-masters who depend on him, then one will arrive at 
conclusions belonging exclusively to the sphere of the holy. Sancho 
will provide us with a pitiful example of this. 

“Recently” in active circles “so much has been said” about the rule 
of the bourgeois, “that it is not surprising that news of it”, if only 
through the medium of L. Blanc (translated by the Berliner Buhl), a 
etc., “has even penetrated to Berlin” and there attracted the 
attention of easy-going school-masters ( Wigand , p. 190). It cannot, 
however, be said that “Stirner” in his method of appropriating 
current ideas has “adopted a particularly fruitful and profitable 
style” ( Wigand , ibid.) — as was already evident from his exploitation 
of Hegel and will now be further exemplified. 

It has not escaped our school-master that in recent times the 
liberals have been identified with the bourgeois. Since Saint Max 
identifies the bourgeois with the good burghers, with the petty 
German burghers, he does not grasp what has been transmitted to 
him as it is in fact and as it is expressed by all competent 
authors — viz., that the liberal phrases are the idealistic expression of 
the real interests of the bourgeoisie — but, on the contrary, as 
meaning that the final goal of the bourgeois is to become a perfect 
liberal, a citizen of the state. For Saint Max the bourgeois is not the 
truth of the ciioyen, but the citoyen the truth of the bourgeois. This 
conception, which is as holy as it is German, goes to such lengths that, 
on page 130, “the middle class” (it should read: the domination of 
the bourgeoisie) is transformed into a “thought, nothing but a 
thought” and “the state” comes forward as the “true man”, who in 
the “Rights of Man” confers the rights of “Man”, the true 
solemnisation on each individual bourgeois. And all this occurs after 
the illusions about the state and the rights of man had already been 
adequately exposed in the Deutsch-Franzosische Jahrbiicher* a fact 

* In the Deutsch-Franzosische Jahrbiicher this was done, in view of the context, only 
in relation to the rights of man proclaimed by the French Revolution. [Cf. Karl Marx, 
“Zur Judenfrage” (see present edition, Vol. 3, pp. 161-65). — Ed.] Incidentally, this 
whole conception of competition as “the rights of man” can already be found among 
representatives of the bourgeoisie a century earlier (John Hampden, Petty, 
Boisguillebert, Child, etc.). On the relation of the theoretical liberals to the bourgeois 
compare what has been said [above] on the relation of the ideologists of a class to the 
class itself. [See p. 176 of this volume. — Ed.] 

a The reference is to Louis Blanc, Histoire de dix ans 1830-1840, which appeared in 
Berlin in 1844-45 in Ludwig Buhl’s translation under the title Geschichte der zehn 
Jahre. — Ed. 




198 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



which Saint Max notices at last in his “Apologetical Commentary” 
anno 1845. Hence he can transform the bourgeois — having sepa- 
rated the bourgeois as a liberal from the empirical bourgeois — into a 
holy liberal, just as he transforms the state into the “holy”, and the 
relation of the bourgeois to the modern state into a holy relation, into 
a cult (p. 131) — and with this, in effect, he concludes his criticism of 
political liberalism. He has transformed it into the “holy”.* 

We wish to give here a few examples of how Saint Max embellishes 
this property of his with historical arabesques. For this purpose he 
uses the French Revolution, concerning which a small contract to 
supply him with a few data has been negotiated by his historv-broker, 
Saint Bruno. 

On the basis of a few words from Bailly, obtained moreover 
through the intermediary of Saint Bruno’s Denkwiirdigkeiten , a the 
statement is made that through the convening of the States General 
“those who hitherto were subjects arrive at the consciousness that 
they are proprietors” (p. 132). On the contrary, mon bravel By the 
convening of the States General, those who hitherto were propri- 
etors show their consciousness of being no longer subjects — a con- 
sciousness which was long ago arrived at, for example in the Physio- 
crats, and — in polemical form against the bourgeoisie — in Linguet 
(' Theorie des lots civiles, 1767), Mercier, Mably, and, in general, in the 
writings against the Physiocrats. This meaning was also immediately 
understood at the beginning of the revolution — for example by 
Brissot, Fauchet, Marat, in the Cercle social 63 and by all the democrat- 
ic opponents of Lafayette. If Saint Max had understood the matter 
as it took place independently of his history-broker, he would not 
have been surprised that “Bailly ’s words certainly sound [as if each 
man were now a proprietor...” and that the bourgeois ... express... 
the rule of the proprietors ... that now the proprietors have become 
the bourgeoisie par excellence.] 64 

[...] “As early as July 8 the statement of the Bishop of Autun b and Barere 
[destroyed] the illusion that [each man], the individual, was of importance in the 
legislature; it [showed] the utter impotence of the constituents. The majority of the 
deputies has become master.” JStirner, op. cit., p. 132 f.j 

* [The following passage is crossed out in the manuscript:] For him thereby 
criticism as a whole “achieves its final goal” and all cats turn grey, thereby he also 
admits his ignorance of the real basis and the real content of the rule of the 
bourgeoisie. 

a A reference to Edgar Bauer’s essay “Bailly und die ersten Tage der 
Franzbsischen Revolution” in Denkwiirdigkeiten zur Geschichte der neueren Zeit seit der 
Revolution, by Bruno and Edgar Bauer. — Ed. 

I.e., Talleyrand, who was Bishop of Autun from 1788 to 1791. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



199 



The “ statement of the Bishop of Autun and Barere” is a motion 
tabled by the former on July 4 (not 8), with which Barere had 
nothing to do except that together with many others he supported it 
on July 8. It was carried on July 9, hence it is not at all clear why Saint 
Max speaks of “July 8”. This motion by no means “destroyed” “the 
illusion that each man, the individual, was of importance”, etc.; but it 
destroyed the binding force of the Cahiers given to the deputies, that 
is, the influence and the “importance”, not of “each man, the 
individual”, but of the feudal 177 bailliages and 431 divisions des 
ordres. By carrying the motion, the Assembly discarded the 
characteristic features of the old, feudal Etats generaux. 65 Moreover, it 
was at that time by no means a question of the correct theory of 
popular representation, but of highly practical, essential problems. 
Broglie’s army held Paris at bay and drew nearer every day; the 
capital was in a state of utmost agitation; hardly a fortnight had 
passed since the jeu de paume and the lit de justice, 66 the court was 
plotting with the bulk of the aristocracy and the clergy against the 
National Assembly; lastly, owing to the still existing feudal provincial 
tariff barriers, and as a result of the feudal agrarian system as a 
whole, most of the provinces were in the grip of famine and there 
was a great scarcity of money. At that moment it was a question of an 
assemblee essentiellement active, as Talleyrand himself put it, while the 
Cahiers of [the] aristocratic and other reactionary groups provided 
the court with an opportunity to declare [the] decision of the Assem- 
bly [void by referring] to the wishes of the constituents. The Assem- 
bly proclaimed its independence by carrying Talleyrand’s motion 
and seized the power it required, which in the political sphere could, 
of course, only be done within the framework of political form and 
by making use of the existing theories of Rousseau, etc. (Cf. Le point 
du jour, par Barere de Vieuzac, 1789, Nos. 15 and 17.) The National 
Assembly had to take this step because it was being urged forward by 
the immense mass of the people that stood behind it. By so doing, 
therefore, it did not at all transform itself into an “utterly egoistical 
chamber, completely cut off from the umbilical cord and ruthless” 
[p. 147]; on the contrary it actually transformed itself thereby into 
the true organ of the vast majority of Frenchmen, who would 
otherwise have crushed it, as they later crushed “utterly egoistical” 
deputies who “completely cut themselves off from the umbilical 
cord”. But Saint Max, with the help of his history -broker, sees here 
merely the solution of a theoretical question; he takes the 
Constituent Assembly, six days before the storming of the Bastille, 
for a council of church fathers debating a point of dogma! The 
question regarding the “importance of each man, the individual”. 




200 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



can, moreover, only arise in a democratically elected representative 
body, and during the revolution it only came up for discussion in the 
Convention, and for as empirical reasons as earlier the question of 
the Cahiers. A problem which the Constituent Assembly decided also 
theoretically was the distinction between the representative body of a 
ruling class and that of the ruling estates; and this political rule of the 
bourgeois class was determined by each individual’s position, since it 
was determined by the relations of production prevailing at the time. 
The representative system is a very specific product of modern 
bourgeois society which is as inseparable from the latter as is the 
isolated individual of modern times. 

Just as here Saint Max takes the 177 bailliages and 431 divisions des 
ordres for “individuals”, so he later sees in the absolute monarch and 
his car tel est notre plaisir a the rule of the “individual” as against the 
constitutional monarch, the “rule of the apparition [”] (p. 141), and 
in the aristocrat and the guild-member he again sees the “individu- 
al” in contrast to the citizen (p. 137). 

“The Revolution was not directed against reality, but against this reality, against 
this definite existence ” (p. 145). 

Hence, not against the really existing system of landownership, of 
taxes, of customs duties which hampered commerce at every turn, 
and the [...] 

[... b “Stirner” thinks] it makes no difference [“to ‘the good 
burghers’ who defends them] and their principles, whether an 
absolute or a constitutional king, a republic, etc. — For the “good 
burghers” who quietly drink their beer in a Berlin beer-cellar this 
undoubtedly “makes no difference”; but for the historical bourgeois 
it is by no means a matter of indifference. The “good burgher” 
“Stirner” here again imagines — as he does throughout this sec- 
tion — that the French, American and English bourgeois are good 
Berlin beer-drinking philistines. If one translates the sentence above 
from the language of political illusion into plain language, it means: 
“it makes no difference” to the bourgeoisie whether it rules 
unrestrictedly or whether its political and economic power is 
counterbalanced by other classes. Saint Max believes that an absolute 
king, or someone else, could defend the bourgeoisie just as 
successfully as it defends itself. And even “its principles”, which 
consist in subordinating state power to “ chacun pour soi, chacun chez 



For this is our will — the concluding words of royal edicts. — Ed. 
b A gap in the manuscript. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Ma: 



201 



soi” a and exploiting it for that purpose — an “absolute monarch” is 
supposed to be able to do that! Let Saint Max name any country with 
developed trade and industry and strong competition where the 
bourgeoisie entrusts its defence to an “absolute monarch”. 

After this transformation of the historical bourgeois into German 
philistines devoid of history, “Stirner”, of course, does not need to 
know any other bourgeois than “comfortable burghers and loyal 
officials’^!!) — two spectres who only dare to show themselves on 
“holy” German soil — and can lump together the whole class as 
“obedient servants” (p. 138). Let him just take a look at these 
obedient servants on the stock exchanges of London, Manchester, 
New York and Paris. Since Saint Max is well under way, he can now 
go the whole hog b and, believing one of the narrow-minded 
theoreticians of the Einundzwanzig Bogen who says that “liberalism is 
rational cognition applied to our existing conditions” 0 , can declare 
that the “liberals are fighters for reason”. It is evident from these [...] 
phrases how little the Germans have recovered [from] their original 
illusions about liberalism. Abraham “against hope believed in hope” 
... and his faith “was imputed to him for righteousness” (Romans 
4: 18 and 22). 

“The state pays well, so that its good citizens can without danger pay poorly; it 
provides itself by means of good payment with servants from whom it forms a 
force — the police — for the protection of good citizens and the good citizens willingly 
pay high taxes to the state in order to pay so much lower amounts to their workers” 
(p. 152). 

This should read: the bourgeois pay their state well and make the 
nation pay for it so that without risk thev should be able to pay 
poorly; by good payment they ensure that the state servants are a 
force available for their protection — the police; they willingly pay, 
and force the nation to pay high taxes so as to be able without dan- 
ger to shift the sums they pay on to the workers as a levy (as a 
deduction from wages). “Stirner” here makes the new economic 
discovery that wages are a levy, a tax, paid by the bourgeois to the 
proletarian; whereas the other, mundane economists regard taxes as 
a tribute which the proletarian pays to the bourgeois. 

Our holy church father now passes from the holy middle class to 
the Stirnerian “unique” proletariat (p. 148). The latter consists of 



a Each for himself and the devil take the hindmost. — Ed. 
h The words “the whole hog” are in English in the manuscript. — Ed. 
c From the article “Preussen seit der Einsetzung Arndt’s bis zur Absetzung 
Bauer's” published anonymously in the Einundzwanzig Bogen aus der Schweiz. — Ed. 




202 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



“rogues, prostitutes, thieves, robbers and murderers, gamblers, 
propertyless people with no occupation and frivolous individuals” 
(ibid.)- They form the “dangerous proletariat” and for a moment are 
reduced by “Stirner” to “individual shouters”, and then, finally, to 
“vagabonds”, who find their perfect expression in the “spiritual 
vagabonds” who do not “keep within the bounds of a moderate way 
of thinking.”... 

“So wide a meaning has the so-called proletariat or” ( per appos.) “pauperism”! 
(p. 149). 

On page 151 [“on the other hand,] the state sucks the life-blood” 
of the proletariat. Hence the entire proletariat consists of ruined 
bourgeois and ruined proletarians, of a collection of ragamuffins, 
who have existed in every epoch and whose existence on a mass scale 
after the decline of the Middle Ages preceded the mass formation of 
the ordinary proletariat, as Saint Max can ascertain by a perusal of 
English and French legislation and literature. Our saint has exactly 
the same notion of the proletariat as the “good comfortable 
burghers” and, particularly, the “loyal officials”. He is consistent also 

in identifying the proletariat with pauperism, whereas pauperism is 
the position only of the ruined proletariat, the lowest level to which 
the proletarian sinks who has become incapable of resisting the 
pressure of the bourgeoisie, and it is only the proletarian whose 
whole energy has been sapped who becomes a pauper. Compare 
Sismondi, 3 Wade, b etc. “Stirner” and his fraternity, for example, can 
in the eyes of the proletarians, in certain circumstances count as 
paupers but never as proletarians. 

Such are Saint Max’s “own” ideas about the bourgeoisie and the 
proletariat. But since with these imaginations about liberalism, good 
burghers and vagabonds he, of course, gets nowhere, he finds 
himself compelled in order to make the transition to communism to 
bring in the actual, ordinary bourgeois and proletarians insofar as he 
knows about them from hearsay. This occurs on pages 151 and 152, 
where the lumpen-proletariat becomes transformed into “workers”, 
into ordinary proletarians, while the bourgeois “in course 
of time” undergoes “occasionally” a series of “various transfor- 
mations” and “manifold refractions”. In one line we read: “ The 
propertied rule ”, i.e., the profane bourgeois; six lines later we read: 
“The citizen is what he is by the grace of the state”, i.e., the 
holy bourgeois; yet another six lines later: “The state is the status 
of the middle class”, i.e., the profane bourgeois; this is then ex- 



3 Simonde de Sismondi, Nouveaux principes d’economie politique. — Ed. 
John Wade, History of the Middle and Working Classes. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 203 



plained by saying that “the state gives the propertied” “their prop- 
erty in feudal possession” and that the “money and property” of 
the “capitalists”, i.e., the holy bourgeois, is such “state property” 
transferred by the state to “feudal possession”. Finally, this 
omnipotent state is again transformed into the “state of the 
propertied”, i.e., of the profane bourgeois, which is in accord 
with a later passage: “Owing to the revolution the bourgeoisie 
became omnipotent ” (p. 156). Even Saint Max would never have 
been able to achieve these “heart-rending” and “horrible” con- 
tradictions — at any rate, he would never have dared to promul- 
gate them — had he not had the assistance of the German word 
“Burger” [citizen], which he can interpret at will as “citoyen” or as 
“ bourgeois ” or as the German “good burgher”. 

Before going further, we must take note of two more great 
politico-economic discoveries which our simpleton “brings into 
being” “in the depths of his heart” and which have in common with 
the “joy of youth” of page 17 the feature of being also “pure 
thoughts”. 

On page 1 50 all the evil of the existing social relations is reduced to 
the fact that “burghers and workers believe in the ‘truth’ of money”. 
Jacques le bonhomme imagines that it is in the power of the 
“burghers” and “workers”, who are scattered among all civilised 
states of the world, suddenly, one fine day, to put on record their 
“disbelief” in the “truth of money”; he even believes that if this 
nonsense were possible, something would be achieved by it. He 
believes that any Berlin writer could abolish the “truth of money” 
with the same ease as he abolishes in his mind the “truth” of God or 
of Hegelian philosophy. That money is a necessary product of 
definite relations of production and intercourse and remains a 
“truth” so long as these relations exist — this, of course, is of no 
concern to a holy man like Saint Max, who raises his eyes towards 
heaven and turns his profane backside to the profane world. 

The second discovery is made on page 152 and amounts to this, 
that “the worker cannot turn his labour to account” because he “falls 
into the hands” of “those who” have received “some kind of state 
property” “in feudal possession”. This is merely a further explana- 
tion of the sentence on page 151 already quoted above where the 
state sucks the life-blood of the worker. And here everyone will 
immediately “put forward” “the simple reflection” — that “Stirner” 
does not do so is not “surprising”— how does it come about 
that the state has not given the “workers” also some sort of “state 
property” in “feudal possession”. If Saint Max had asked himself 
this question he would probably have managed to do without his 




204 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



construction of the “holy” burghers, because he would have been 
bound to see the relation in which the propertied stand to the 
modern state. 

By means of the opposition of the bourgeoisie and proletariat — as 
even “Stirner” knows — one arrives at communism. But how one 
arrives at it, only “Stirner” knows. 

“The workers have the most tremendous power in their hands ... they have only to 
cease work and to regard what they have produced by their labour as their property 
and to enjoy it. This is the meaning of the workers’ disturbances which flare up here 
and there” (p. 153). 

Workers’ disturbances, which even under the Byzantine Emperor 
Zeno led to the promulgation of a law (Zeno, de novis operibus 
constitution , which “flared up” in the fourteenth century in the form 
of the Jacquerie and Wat Tyler’s rebellion, in 1518 on the Evil May 
Day b in London, and in 1549 in the great uprising of the tanner 
Kett, 67 and later gave rise to Act 15 of the second and third year of 
the reign of Edward VI, and a series of similar Acts of Parliament; 
the disturbances which soon afterwards, in 1640 and 1659 (eight 
uprisings in one year), took place in Paris and which already since the 
fourteenth century must have been frequent in France and England, 
judging by the legislation of the time; the constant war which since 
1770 in England and since the revolution in France has been waged 
with might and cunning by the workers against the bourgeoisie — all 
this exists for Saint Max only “here and there”, in Silesia, Poznan, 
Magdeburg and Berlin, “according to German newspaper reports”. 

What is produced by labour, according to Jacques le bonhomme’s 
imagination, would continue to exist and be reproduced, as an object 
to be “regarded” and “enjoyed”, even if the producers “ceased 
work”. 

As he did earlier in the case of money, now again our good 
burgher transforms “the workers”, who are scattered throughout 
the civilised world, into a private club which has only to adopt a 
decision in order to get rid of all difficulties. Saint Max does not 
know, of course, that at least fifty attempts have been made in 
England since 1830, and at the present moment yet another is being 
made, to gather all the English workers into a single association and 
that highly empirical causes have frustrated the success of all these 
projects. He does not know that even a minority of workers who 
combine and go on strike very soon find themselves compelled to act 
in a revolutionary way — a fact he could have learned from the 1842 

a Zeno, Decree on New Works. — Ed. 

The words “Evil May Day” are in English in the manuscript. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



205 



uprising in England and from the earlier Welsh uprising of 1839, in 
which year the revolutionary excitement among the workers first 
found comprehensive expression in the “sacred month”, which was 
proclaimed simultaneously with a general arming of the people. 68 
Here again we see how Saint Max constantly tries to pass off his 
nonsense as “ the meaning” of historical facts (in which he is 
successful at best in relation to his “one”) — historical facts “on which 
he foists his own meaning, which are thus bound to lead to 
nonsense” ( Wigand , p. 194). Incidentally, it would never enter the 
head of any proletarian to turn to Saint Max for advice about the 
“meaning” of the proletarian movements or what should be 
undertaken at the present time against the bourgeoisie. 

After this great campaign, our Saint Sancho returns to his 
Maritornes with the following fanfare: 

“The state rests on the slavery of labour. If labour were to become free, the state 
would be lost” (p. 153). 

The modern state, the rule of the bourgeoisie, is based on freedom of 
labour. The idea that along with freedom of religion, state, thought, 
etc., and hence “occasionally” “also” “perhaps” with freedom of 
labour, not I become free, but only one of my enslavers — this idea was 
borrowed by Saint Max himself, many times, though in a very 
distorted form, from the Deutsch-Franzosische Jahrbucher . a Freedom of 
labour is free competition of the workers among themselves. Saint 
Max is very unfortunate in political economy as in all other spheres. 
Labour is free in all civilised countries; it is not a matter of freeing 
labour but of abolishing it. 



B. Communism 

Saint Max calls communism “social liberalism”, because he is well 
aware how great is the disrepute of the word liberalism among the 
radicals of 1842 and the most advanced Berlin “free-thinkers”. 9 
This transformation gives him at the same time the opportunity and 
courage to put into the mouths of the “social liberals” all sorts of 
things which had never been uttered before “Stirner” and the 
refutation of which is intended to serve also as a refutation of 
communism. 

Communism is overcome by means of a series of partly logical and 
partly historical constructions. 



Cf. present edition, Vol. 3, p. 152. — Ed. 




206 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



First logical construction. 

Because “we have seen ourselves made into servants of egoists”, “we should” not 
ourselves “become egoists ... but should rather see to it that egoists become impossible. 
We want to turn them all into ragamuffins, we want no one to possess anything, in 
order that ‘all’ should be possessors. — So say the social [liberals]. — Who is this person 
whom you call ‘all’? It is ‘society’” (p. 153). 

With the aid of a few quotation marks Sancho here transforms 
“all” into a person, society as a person, as a subject =holy society, the 
holy. Now our saint knows what he is about and can let loose the 
whole torrent of his flaming anger against “the holy”, as the result of 
which, of course, communism is annihilated. 

That Saint Max here again puts his nonsense into the mouth of the 
“social [liberals]”, as being the meaning of their words, is not 
“surprising”. He identifies first of all “owning” as a private 
property-owner with “owning” in general. Instead of examining the 
definite relations between private property and production, instead 
of examining “owning” as a landed proprietor, as a rentier, as 
a merchant, as a factory-owner, as a worker — where “owning” would 
be found to be a quite distinct kind of owning, control over other 
people’s labour — he transforms all these relations into “owning as 
such”. a 

[...] political liberalism, which made the “nation” the supreme 
owner. Hence communism has no longer to “abolish” any “personal 
property” but, at most, has to equalise the distribution of “feudal 
possessions”, to introduce egalite there. 

On society as “supreme owner” and on the “ragamuffin”. Saint 
Max should compare, inter alia, L’Egalitaire for 1840: 

“Social property is a contradiction, but social wealth is a consequence of 
communism. Fourier, in contradistinction to the modest bourgeois moralists, repeats a 
hundred times that it is not a social evil that some have too much but that all have too 
little”, and therefore draws attention also to the “poverty of the rich”, in La fausse 
Industrie , Paris, 1835, p. 410. 

Similarly as far back as 1839 — hence before Weitling’s Garan- 
tien h - — it is stated in the German communist magazine Die Stimme des 
Volks (second issue, p. 14) published in Paris: 

“Private property, the much praised, industrious, comfortable, innocent ‘private 
gain', does obvious harm to the wealth of life .” c 

a Four pages of the manuscript are missing here which contained the end of the 
“first logical construction ” and the beginning of the “ second logical construction ” . — Ed. 

Wilhelm Weitling, Garantien der Harmonie und Freiheit. — Ed. 

c This seems to be a quotation from the article “Politischer und Socialer 
Umschwung” published in Blatter der Zukunft, 1846, No. 5. Die Stimme des Volks was 
probably mentioned by mistake. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



207 



Saint Sancho here takes as communism the ideas of a few liberals 
tending towards communism, and the mode of expression of some 
communists who, for very practical reasons, express themselves in a 
political form. 

After “Stirner” has transferred property to “society”, all the 
members of this society in his eyes at once become paupers and 
ragamuffins, although — even according to his idea of the communist 
order of things — they “own” the “supreme owner”. — His benevo- 
lent proposal to the communists — “to transform the word ‘Lump’ 2 
into an honourable form of address, just as the revolution did with 
the word ‘citizen’ is a striking example of how he confuses 
communism with something which long ago passed away. The 
revolution even “transformed” the word sansculotte “into an 
honourable form of address”, as against “ honnetes gens ”, which he 
translates very inadequately as good citizens. Saint Sancho does this 
in order that there may be fulfilled the words in the book of the 
prophet Merlin about the three thousand and three hundred slaps 
which the man who is to come will have to give himself: 

Es menester que Sancho tu escudero 

Se de tres mil azotes, y trecientos 

En ambas sus valientes posaderas 

A1 aire descubiertas, y de modo 

Que le escuezan, le amarguen y le enfaden. 

( Don Quijote, tomo II, cap. 35. ) b 

Saint Sancho notes that the “elevation of society to supreme 
owner” is a “second robbery of the personal element in the interests of 
humanity”, while communism is only the completed robbery of the 
“robbery of the personal element”. “Since he unquestionably 
regards robbery as detestable”, Saint Sancho “therefore believes for 
example” that he “has branded” communism “already by the” 
above “proposition” (“the book”, p. 102). “Once” “Stirner” has 
“detected” “even robbery” in communism, “how could he fail to feel 
‘profound disgust’ at it and ‘just indignation’”! ( Wigand , p. 156.) We 
now challenge “Stirner” to name a bourgeois who has written about 
communism (or Chartism) and has not put forward the same 

a Ragamuffin. — Ed. 

Needful it is that your squire, Sancho Panza, 

Shall deal himself three thousand and three hundred 
Lashes upon his two most ample buttocks. 

Both to the air exposed, and in such sort 

That they shall smart, and sting and vex him sorely. 



( Don Quixote, Vol. II, Ch. 35.) — Ed. 




208 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



absurdity with great emphasis. Communism will certainly carry out 
“robbery” of what the bourgeois regards as “personal”. 

First corollary. 

Page 349: “Liberalism at once came forward with the statement that it is an 
essential feature of man to be not property, but property-owner. Since it was a question 
here of man, and not of an individual, the question of how much, which was precisely 
what constituted the particular interest of individuals, was left to their discretion. 
Therefore, the egoism of individuals had the widest scope as regards this how much and 
carried on tireless competition.” 

That is to say: liberalism, i.e., liberal private property-owners, at 
the beginning of the French Revolution gave private property a 
liberal appearance by declaring it one of the rights of man. They 
were forced to do so if only because of their position as a revolu- 
tionising party; they were even compelled not only to give the mass 
of the French [rural] population the right to property, [but also] to 
let them seize actual property, and they could do all this because 
thereby their own “how much”, which was what chiefly interested 
them, remained intact and was even made safe. 

We find here further that Saint Max makes competition arise from 
liberalism, a slap that he gives history in revenge for the slaps which 
he had to give himself above. A “more exact explanation” of the 
manifesto with which he makes liberalism “ at once come forward” 
can be found in Hegel, who in 1820 expressed himself as follows: 

“In respect of external things it is rational” (i. e., it becomes me as reason, as a man) 
“that I should possess property ... what and how much I possess is, therefore, legally a 
matter of chance” ( Rechtsphilosophie , a § 49). 

It is characteristic of Hegel that he turns the phrase of the 
bourgeois into the true concept, into the essence of property, and 
“Stirner” faithfully imitates him. On the basis of the above analysis, 
Saint Max now makes the further statement, that communism 

“raised the question as to how much property, and answered it in the sense that man 
should have as much as he needs. Can my egoism be satisfied with that?... No. I must 
rather have as much as I am capable of appropriating” (p. 349). 

First of all it should be remarked here that communism has by no 
means originated from § 49 of Hegel’s Rechtsphilosophie and its “what 
and how much”. Secondly, “communism” does not dream of 
wanting to give anything to “man”, for “communism” is not at all of 
the opinion that “man” “needs” anything apart from a brief critical 
elucidation. Thirdly, Stirner foists on to communism the conception 

a G.W.F. Hegel, Grundlinien der Philosophic des Rechts. The preface to this work is 
dated June 25, 1820. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



209 



of “need” held by the present-day bourgeois; hence he introduces a 
distinction which, on account of its paltriness, can be of importance 
only in present-day society and its ideal copy — Stirner’s union of 
“individual shouters” and free seamstresses. “Sdrner” has again 
achieved great “penetration” into the essence of communism. 
Finally, in his demand to have as much as he is capable of 
appropriating (if this is not the usual bourgeois phrase that everyone 
should have as much as his ability 3 permits him, that everyone 
should have the right of free gain). Saint Sancho assumes 
communism as having already been achieved in order to be able 
freely to develop his “ability” and put it into operation, which by no 
means depends solely on him, any more than his fortune itself, but 
depends also on the relations of production and intercourse in which 
he lives. (Cf. the chapter on the “Union”. b ) Incidentally, even Saint 
Max himself does not behave according to his doctrine, for 
throughout his “book” he “needs” things and uses things which he 
was not “capable of appropriating”. 

Second corollary.' 

“But the social reformers preach a social law to us. The individual thus becomes 
the slave of society” (p. 246). “In the opinion of the communists, everyone should 
enjoy the eternal rights of man” (p. 238). 

Concerning the expressions “law”, “labour”, etc., how they are 
used by proletarian writers and what should be the attitude of 
criticism towards them, we shall speak in connection with “True 
Socialism” (see Volume II). As far as law is concerned, we with many 
others have stressed the opposition of communism to law, both 
political and private, as also in its most general form as the rights of 
man. See the Deutsch-Franzdsische Jahrbiicher, where privilege, the 
special right, is considered as something corresponding to private 
property inseparable from social classes, and law as something 
corresponding to the state of competition, of free private property 
(p. 206 and elsewhere); equally, the rights of man themselves are 
considered as privilege, and private property as monopoly. Further, 
criticism of law is brought into connection with German philosophy 
and presented as the consequence of criticism of religion (p. 72); 
further, it is expressly stated that the legal axioms that are supposed 
to lead to communism are axioms of private property, and the right 
of common ownership is an imaginary premise of the right of private 



3 The German word Vermogen used several times in this passage means not only 
ability, capability but also wealth, fortune, means, property; the authors here play on 
the various meanings of the word. — Ed. 
b See this volume, pp. 393-94. — Ed. 




210 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



property (pp. 98, 99). a Incidentally, even in the works of German 
communists passages appeared very early — e.g., in the writings of 
Hess, Einundzwanzig Bogen aus der Schweiz, 1843, p. 326 b and 
elsewhere — which could be appropriated and distorted “by Stirner” 
in his criticism of law. 

Incidentally, the idea of using the phrase quoted above against 
Babeuf, of regarding him as the theoretical representative of 
communism could only occur to a Berlin school-master. “Stirner”, 
however, has the effrontery to assert on page 247 that 

communism, which assumes “that all people by nature have equal rights, refutes its 
own thesis and asserts that people by nature have no rights at all. For it does not want, 
for example, to admit that parents have rights in relation to their children; it abolishes 
the family. In general, this whole revolutionary or Babouvist principle (compare Die 
Kommunisten in der Schweiz, Kommissionalberichtf p. 3) is based on a religious, i.e., false, 
outlook”. 

A Yankee comes to England, where he is prevented by a Justice of 
the Peace from flogging his slave, and he exclaims indignantly: “Do 
you call this a land of liberty, where a man can’t larrup his nigger?” d 

Saint Sancho here makes himself doubly ridiculous. Firstly, he sees 
an abolition of the “equal rights of man” in the recognition of the 
“equal rights by nature” of children in relation to parents, in the 
granting of the same rights of man to children as well as to parents. 
Secondly, two pages previously Jacques le bonhomme tells us that the 
state does not interfere when a father beats his son, because it 
recognises family rights. Thus, what he presents, on the one hand, as 
a particular right (family right), he includes, on the other hand, 
among the “equal rights of man by nature”. Finally, he admits that 
he knows Babeuf only from the Bluntschli report, while this report 
(p. 3), in turn, admits that its wisdom is derived from the worthy 
L. Stein, e Doctor of Law. Saint Sancho’s thorough knowledge of 
communism is evident from this quotation. Just as Saint Bruno is his 
broker as regards revolution, so Saint Bluntschli is his broker as 



a Cf. “Outlines of a Critique of Political Economy” by Engels and Contribution to 
the Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of Law. Introduction and “On the Jewish Question” 
by Marx (see present edition, Vol. 3, pp. 418, 175, 146. — Ed. 

b This refers to Moses Hess’ article “Philosophic der That”, which was published 
in Einundzwanzig Bogen aus der Schweiz. — Ed. 

c Johann Caspar Bluntschli, Die Kommunisten in der Schweiz nach den bei Weitling 
vorgefundenen Papieren. — Ed. 

d This sentence is in English in the manuscript. — Ed. 

e Lorenz von Stein, Der Socialismus und Communismus des heutigen Frankreichs. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



211 



regards communists. With such a state of affairs we ought not to be 
surprised that a few lines lower down our rustic word of God a 
reduces the fraternite of the revolution to “equality of the children of 
God” (in what Christian dogma is there any talk of egalite?). 

Third corollary. 

Page 414: Because the principle of community culminates in communism, 
therefore, communism = “apotheosis of the state founded on love”. 

From the state founded on love, which is Saint Max’s own 
fabrication, he here derives communism which then, of course, 
remains an exclusively Stirnerian communism. Saint Sancho knows 
only egoism on the one hand or the claim to the loving services, pity 
and alms of people on the other hand. Outside and above this 
dilemma nothing exists for him at all. 

Third logical construction. 

“Since the most oppressive evils are to be observed in society, it is especially” (!) 
“the oppressed” (!) who “think that the blame is to be found in society and set 
themselves the task of discovering the right society” (p. 155). 

On the contrary, it is “Stirner” who “sets himself the task” of 
discovering the “society” which is “right” for him, the holy society, 
the society as the incarnation of the holy. Those who are 
“oppressed” nowadays “in society”, “think” only about how to 
achieve the society which is right for them, and this consists primarily 
in abolishing the present society on the basis of the existing 
productive forces. If, e.g., “oppressive evils are to be observed” in a 
machine, if, for example, it refuses to work, and those who need the 
machine (for example, in order to make money) find the fault in the 
machine and try to alter it, etc. — then, in Saint Sancho’s opinion, they 
are setting themselves the task not of putting the machine right, but 
of discovering the right machine, the holy machine, the machine as 
the incarnation of the holy, the holy as a machine, the machine in the 
heavens. “Stirner” advises them to seek the blame “in themselves ”. Is 
it not their fault that, for example, they need a hoe and a plough? 
Could they not use their bare hands to plant potatoes and to extract 
them from the soil afterwards? The saint, on page 156, preaches to 
them as follows: 

“It is merely an ancient phenomenon that one seeks first of all to lay the blame 
anywhere but on oneself — and therefore on the state, on the selfishness of the rich, for 
which, however, we ourselves are to blame.” 

The “oppressed” who seeks to lay the “blame” for pauperism on 
the “state” is, as we have noted above, no other than Jacques le 



a Cf. August Friedrich Ernst Langbein’s poem, Der Landprediger. — Ed. 




212 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



bonhomme himself. Secondly, the “oppressed” who comforts 
himself by causing the “blame” to be laid on the “selfishness of the 
rich” is again no other than Jacques le bonhomme. He could have 
learned something better about the other oppressed from the Facts 
and Fictions of John Watts, 3 tailor and doctor of philosophy, from 
Hobson’s Poor Man's Companion, etc. And, thirdly, who is the person 
that should bear the “blame”? Is it, perhaps, the proletarian child 
who comes into the world tainted with scrofula, who is reared with 
the help of opium and is sent into the factory when seven years 
old — or is it, perhaps, the individual worker who is here expected to 
“revolt” by himself against the world market — or is it, perhaps, the 
girl who must either starve or become a prostitute? No, not these but 
only he who seeks “all the blame”, i.e., the “blame” for everything 
in the present state of the world, “in himself”, viz., once again no 
other than Jacques le bonhomme himself. “This is merely the 
ancient phenomenon” of Christian heart -searching and doing peni- 
tence in a German-speculative form, with its idealist phraseology, 
according to which I, the actual man, do not have to change 
actuality, which I can only change together with others, but have 
to change myself in myself. “It is the internal struggle of the writer 
with himself” ( Die heilige Familie, p. 122, cf. pp. 73, 121 and 306). b 

According to Saint Sancho, therefore, those oppressed by society 
seek the right society. If he were consistent, he should make those 
who “seek to lay the blame on the state” — and according to him 
they are the very same people — also seek the right state. But he cannot 
do this, because he has heard that the communists want to abolish 
the state. He has now to construct this abolition of the state, and our 
Saint Sancho once more achieves this with the aid of his “ass”, the 
apposition, in a way that “looks very simple”: 

“Since the workers are in a state of distress” [ Notstand ], “the existing state of affairs” 

[ Stand der Dinge ], “i.e., the state” [ Staat ] ( status = state or estate) “must be abolished” 
(ibid.). 



Thus: 

the state of distress 
the existing state of affairs 
state, estate 
status 



the existing state of affairs 
state or estate 
status 
the State 



Conclusion: the state of distress = the State. 



3 John Watts, The Facts and Fictions of Political Economists. — Ed. 
b See present edition, Vol. 4, pp. 83, 53, 82, 192. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



213 



What could “look simpler”? “It is only surprising” that the English 
bourgeois in 1688 and the French in 1789 did not “put forward” the 
same “simple reflections” and equations, since in those times it was 
much more the case that estate = status = the State. It follows from this 
that wherever a “state of distress” exists, “the State”, which is, of 
course, the same in Prussia and North America, must be abolished. 

As is his custom, Saint Sancho now presents us with a few proverbs 
of Solomon. 

Proverb of Solomon No. 1. 

Page 163: “That society is no ego, which could give, etc., but an instrument from 
which we can derive benefit; that we have no social duties, but only interests; that we 
do not owe any sacrifices to society, but if we do sacrifice something we sacrifice it for 
ourselves — all this is disregarded by the social [liberals], because they are in thrall to 
the religious principle and are zealously striving for a — holy society.” 

The following “penetrations” into the essence of communism 
result from this; 

1. Saint Sancho has quite forgotten that it was he himself who 
transformed “society” into an “ego” and that consequently he finds 
himself only in his own “society”. 

2. He believes that the communists are only waiting for “society” 
to “give” them something, whereas at most they want to give 
themselves a society. 

3. He transforms society, even before it exists, into an instrument 
from which he wants to derive benefit, without him and other people 
by their mutual social relations creating a society, and hence this 
“instrument”. 

4. He believes that in communist society there can be a question of 
“duties” and “interests”, of two complementary aspects of an 
antithesis which exists only in bourgeois society (under the guise of 
interest the reflecting bourgeois always inserts a third thing between 
himself and his mode of action — a habit seen in truly classic form in 
Bentham, whose nose had to have some interest before it would 
decide to smell anything. Compare “the book” on the right to one’s 
nose, page 247). 

5. Saint Max believes that the communists want to “make 
sacrifices” for “society”, when they want at most to sacrifice existing 
society; in this case he should describe their consciousness that their 
struggle is the common cause of all people who have outgrown the 
bourgeois system as a sacrifice that they make to themselves. 

6. That the social [liberals] are in thrall to the religious principle 
and 

7. that they are striving for a holy society — these points have 
already been dealt with above. How “zealously” Saint Sancho 




214 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



“strives” for a “holy society”, so as to be able to refute communism 
by means of it, we have already seen. 

Proverb of Solomon No. 2. 

Page 277: “If interest in the social problem were less passionate and blind, then one 
... w ould understand that a society cannot be turned into a new one so long as those of 
whom it consists and who constitute it remain as of old.” 

“Stirner” believes that the communist proletarians who revolu- 
tionise society and put the relations of production and the form of 
intercourse on a new basis — i.e., on themselves as new people, on 
their new mode of life — that these proletarians remain “as of old”. 
The tireless propaganda carried on by these proletarians, their daily 
discussions among themselves, sufficiently prove how little they 
themselves want to remain “as of old”, and how little they want 
people to remain “as of old”. They would only remain “as of old” if, 
with Saint Sancho, they “sought the blame in themselves”; but they 
know too well that only under changed circumstances will they cease 
to be “as of old”, and therefore they are determined to change these 
circumstances at the first opportunity. In revolutionary activity the 
changing of oneself coincides with the changing of circumstances. — 
This great saying is explained by means of an equally great example 
which, of course, is again taken from the world of “the holy”. 

“If, for example, the Jewish people was to give rise to a society which spread a new 
faith throughout the world, then these apostles could not remain Pharisees.” 

The first Christians = a society for spreading faith (founded 

anno 1). 

_ Congregatio de propaganda fide 70 
(founded anno 1640). 

Anno 1 =Anno 1640. 

This society which should arise = These apostles. 

These apostles = Non-Jews. 

The Jewish people = Pharisees. 

Christians = Non-Pharisees. 

= Not the Jewish people. 

What can look simpler? 

Reinforced by these equations. Saint Max calmly utters the great 
historic words a : 

“Human beings, by no means intending to achieve their own development, have 
always wanted to form a society.” . 

Human beings, by no means wanting to form a society, have, 
nevertheless, only achieved the development of society, because they 

a Paraphrase of a line from Goethe’s Iphigenie auf Tauris, Act 1, Scene 3. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



215 



have always wanted to develop only as isolated individuals and 
therefore achieved their own development only in and through 
society. Incidentally it would only occur to a saint of the type of our 
Sancho to separate the development of “human beings” from the 
development of the “society” in which they live, and then let his 
fantasy roam on this fantastic basis. Incidentally, he has forgotten his 
own proposition, inspired by Saint Bruno, in which just previously 
he set people the moral demand of changing themselves and thereby 
changing their society — a proposition, therefore, in which he 
identifies the development of people with the development of their 
society. 

Fourth logical construction. 

On page 156 he makes the communists say, in opposition to the 
citizens: 

“Our essence” (!) ‘‘does not consist in all of us being equal children of the state” (!), 
“but in that we all exist for one another. We are all equal in that we all exist for one 
another, that each works for the other, that each of us is a worker.” He then regards 
“to exist as a worker” as equivalent to “each of us exists only through the other”, so 
that the other, “for example, works to clothe me, and I to satisfy his need of 
entertainment, he for my food and I for his instruction. Hence participation in 
labour is our dignity and our equality. 

“What advantage do we derive from citizenship? Burdens. And what value is put 
on our labour? The lowest possible.... What can you put against us? Again, only 
labour!” “Only for labour do we owe you a recompense”; “only for what you do that is 
useful to us” “have you any claim on us”. “We want to be only worth so much to you as 
we perform for you; but you should be valued by us in just the same way.” “Deeds 
which are of some value to us, i.e., work beneficial to the community, determine 
value.... He who does something useful takes second place to no one, or — all workers 
(beneficial to the community) are equal. Since however the worker is worthy of his 
wage a , then let the wage also be equal” (pp. 157,158). 

With “Stirner”, “communism” begins with searchings for “ es- 
sence ”; being a good “youth” he wants again only to “penetrate 
behind things”. That communism is a highly practical movement, 
pursuing practical aims by practical means, and that only perhaps in 
Germany, in opposing the German philosophers, can it spare a 
moment for the problem of “essence” — this, of course, is of no 
concern to our saint. This Stirnerian “communism”, which yearns so 
much for “essence”, arrives, therefore, only at a philosophical 
category, i.e., “being-for-one-another”, which then by means of a 
few arbitrary equations: 

Being-for-one-another = to exist only through another 

= to exist as a worker 

= universal community of workers 

a Cf. Luke 10:7 .— Ed. 



0—2086 




216 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



is brought somewhat closer to the empirical world. We would, 
moreover, challenge Saint Sancho to indicate, for example, in Owen 
(who, after all, as a representative of English communism can serve 
as an example of “communism” just as well as, for example, the 
non-communist Proudhon,* from whom the greater part of the 
above propositions were abstracted and then rearranged) a passage 
containing anything of these propositions about “essence”, universal 
community of workers, etc. Incidentally we do not even have to go so 
far back. The third issue of Die Stimme des Volks, the German 
communist magazine already quoted above, says: 

“What is today called labour is only a miserably small part of the vast, mighty 
process of production; for religion and morality honour with the name of labour only 
the kind of production that is repulsive and dangerous, and in addition they venture 
to embellish such labour with all kinds of maxims — as it were words of blessing (or 
witchcraft) — ‘labour in the sweat of thy brow’ as a test imposed by God; ‘labour 
sweetens life’ for encouragement, etc. The morality of the world in which we live takes 
very good care not to apply the term work to the pleasing and free aspects of human 
intercourse. These aspects are reviled by morality, although they too constitute 
production. Morality eagerly reviles them as vanity, vain pleasure, sensuality. 
Communism has exposed this hypocritical preaching, this miserable morality.” 3 

As universal community of workers, Saint Max reduces the whole 
of communism to equal wages — a discovery which is then repeated in 
the following three “refractions”: on page 351, “Against competi- 
tion there rises the principle of the society of ragamuffins — distribu- 
tion. Is it possible then that I, who am very resourceful, b should have 
no advantage over one who is resourceless?” Further, on page 363, 
he speaks of a “universal tax on human activity in communist 
society”. And, finally, on page 350, he ascribes to the communists the 
view that “labour” is “the only resource” of man. Thus, Saint Max 
re-introduces into communism private property in its dual form — as 



* Proudhon, who was as early as 1841 strongly criticised by the communist 
workers’ journal La Fraternite for advocating equal wages, community of workers in 
general and also the other economic prejudices which can be found in the works of 
this outstanding writer; Proudhon, from whom the communists have accepted 
nothing but his criticism of property. [The note was left unfinished.] 



a This seems to be a quotation from the article “Politischer und Socialer 
Umschwung” published in Blatter der Zukunft, 1846, No. 5. Die Stimme des Volks was 
probably mentioned by mistake. — Ed. 

b In this section the authors play on the different meanings of the word 
Vermogen and its derivatives vielvermogend, unvermogend, etc. Der Vielvermogende 
can denote a person who is able, capable, wealthy, powerful, resourceful, a man of 
property, etc.; der Unvermogende on the other hand, can mean unable, incapable, 
inept, powerless, impecunious, resourceless, etc. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



217 



distribution and wage-labour. As before in connection with “rob- 
bery”, Saint Max here again displays the most ordinary and 
narrow-minded bourgeois views as “his own” “penetrations” into 
the essence of communism. He shows himself fully worthy of the 
honour of having been taught by Bluntschli. As a real 
petty bourgeois, he is then afraid that he, “who is very resource- 
ful”, “should have no advantage over one who is resourceless” — 
although he should fear nothing so much as being left to his own 
“resources”. 

Incidentally, he “who is very resourceful” imagines that citizen- 
ship is a matter of indifference to the proletarians, after he has first 
assumed that they have it. This is just as he imagined above that for 
the bourgeoisie the form of government is a matter of indifference. 
The workers attach so much importance to citizenship, i.e., to active 
citizenship, that where they have it, for instance in America, they 
“make good use” of it, and where they do not have it, they strive to 
obtain it. Compare the proceedings of the North American workers 
at innumerable meetings, the whole history of English Chartism, and 
of French communism and reformism . 71 

First corollary. 



“The worker, being conscious that the essential thing about him is that he is a 
worker, keeps himself away from egoism and subordinates himself to the supremacy 
of a society of workers, just as the bourgeois adhered with devotion” (!) “to the state 
based on competition” (p. 162). 



The worker is at most conscious that for the bourgeois the essential 
thing about him is that he is a worker, who, therefore, can assert 
himself against the bourgeois as such. Both these discoveries of Saint 
Sancho, the “devotion of the bourgeois” and the “ state based on 
competition”, can be recorded only as fresh proofs of the 
“resourcefulness” of the “very resourceful” man. 

Second corollary. 



“The aim of communism is supposed to be the ‘well-being of all'. This indeed really 
looks as though in this way no one need be in an inferior position. But what sort of 
well-being will this be? Have all one and the same well-being? Do all people feel 
equally well in one and the same circumstances?... If that is so, then it is a matter of 
‘true well-being’. Do we not thereby arrive precisely at the point where the tyranny of 
religion begins?... Society has decreed that a particular sort of well-being is ‘true 
well-being’, and if this well-being were, for example, honestly earned enjoyment, but you 
preferred enjoyable idleness, then society ... would prudently refrain from making 
provision for what is for you well-being. By proclaiming the well-being of all, 
communism destroys the well-being of those who up to now have lived as rentiers”, 
etc. (pp. 411. 412). 




218 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



“If that is so”, the following equations result from it: 

The well-being of all = Communism 
= If that is so 

= One and the same well-being of all 
= Equal well-being of all in one and 
the same circumstances 
= True well-being 

= [Holy well-being, the holy, the rule of 
the holy, hierarchy] 3 
= Tyranny of religion. 

Communism = Tyranny of religion. 

“This indeed really looks as though” “Stirner” has said the same 
thing about communism as he has said previously about everything 
else. 

How deeply our saint has “penetrated” into the essence of 
communism is evident also from the fact that he ascribes to 
communism the desire to bring about “true well-being” in the shape 
of “honestlv earned enjoyment”. Who, except “Stirner” and a few 
Berlin cobblers and tailors, thinks of “honestly earned enjoyment”!* 
And, what is more, to put this into the mouth of communists, for 
whom the basis of this whole opposition between work and 
enjoyment disappears. Let our highly moral saint put his mind at 
rest on this score. “Honest earning” will be left to him and those 
whom, unknown to himself, he represents — his petty handicrafts- 
men who have been ruined by industrial freedom and are morally 
“indignant”. “Enjoyable idleness”, too, belongs wholly to the most 
trivial bourgeois outlook. But the crowning point of the whole 
statement is the artful bourgeois scruple that he raises against the 
communists: that they want to abolish the “well-being” of the ren- 
tier and yet talk about the “well-being of all”. Consequently, he 
believes that in communist society there will still be rentiers, whose 
“well-being” would have to be abolished. He asserts that “well- 
being” as rentier is inherent in the individuals who are at present 
rentiers, that it is inseparable from their individuality, and he 
imagines that for these individuals there can exist no other “well- 
being” than that which is determined by their position as rentiers. 

* [The following passage is crossed out in the manuscript:] Who, except Stirner, is 
able to attribute such moral absurdities to the immoral revolutionary proletarians, 
who, as the whole civilised world knows (Berlin, being merely “educated” [jebildet], of 
course does not belong to the civilised world), have the wicked intention not “honestly 
to earn” their “enjoyment” but to take it by conquest! 



3 This passage is enclosed in square brackets in the manuscript. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



219 



He believes further that a society which has still to wage a struggle 
against rentiers and the like, is already organised in a communist 
way.* The communists, at any rate, will have no scruples about 
overthrowing the rule of the bourgeoisie and abolishing its “well- 
being”, as soon as they are strong enough to do so.** It does not 
matter to them at all whether this “well-being” common to their 
enemies and determined by class relations also appeals as personal 
“well-being” to a sentimentality which is narrow-mindedly presumed 
to exist. 

Third corollary. 

On page 190, in communist society 

“worry arises again in the form of labour”. 

The good citizen “Stirner”, who is already rejoicing that he will 
again find his beloved “worry” in communism, has nevertheless 
miscalculated this time. “Worry” is nothing but the mood of 
oppression and anxiety which in the middle class is the necessary 
companion of labour, of beggarly activity for securing scanty 
earnings. “Worry” flourishes in its purest form among the German 
good burghers, where it is chronic and “always identical with itself”, 
miserable and contemptible, whereas the poverty of the proletarian 
assumes an acute, sharp form, drives him into a life-and-death 
struggle, makes him a revolutionary, and therefore engenders not 
“worry”, but passion. If then communism wants to abolish both the 
“worry” of the burgher and the poverty of the proletarian, it goes 
without saying that it cannot do this without abolishing the cause of 
both, i.e., “labour”. 

We now come to the historical constructions of communism. 

First historical construction. 

“So long as faith was sufficient for the honour and dignity of man, no objection 
could be raised against any, even the most arduous labour.” ... “The oppressed classes 



* [The following passage is crossed out in the manuscript:] And finally he makes 
the moral demand that the communists should quietly allow themselves to be 
exploited to all eternity by rentiers, merchants, factory-owners, etc., because they can- 
not abolish this exploitation without at the same time destroying the “well-being” of 
these gentlemen. Jacques le bonhomme, who poses here as the champion of the gros- 
bourgeois, can save himself the trouble of preaching moralising sermons to the 
communists, who can every day hear much better ones from his “good burghers”. 

** [The following passage is crossed out in the manuscript:] ... and they will have 
no scruples about it precisely because for them the “well-being of all” regarded as 
“corporeal individuals” is more important than the “well-being” of the hitherto 
existing social classes. The “well-being” which the rentier enjoys as rentier is not the 
“well-being” of the individual as such, but of the rentier, not an individual well-being 
but a well-being that is general within the framework of the class. 




220 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



could tolerate their misery only so long as they were Christians” (the most that can be 
said is that they were Christians so long as they tolerated their miserable position), “for 
Christianity” (which stands behind them with a stick) “keeps their grumbling and 
indignation in check” (p. 158). 

“How ‘Stirner’ knows so well” what the oppressed classes could do, 
we learn from the first issue of the Allgemeine Literatur-Zeitung, 
where “criticism in the form of a master-bookbinder” quotes the 
following passage from an unimportant book: 2 

“Modern pauperism has assumed a political character; whereas formerly the 
beggar bore his fate submissively and regarded it as God’s will, the modern ragamuffin 
asks whether he is forced to drag out his life in poverty just because he chanced to be 
born in rags.” 

It was due to this power of Christianity that during the liberation 
of the feudal serfs the most bloody and embittered struggles were 
precisely those against the spiritual feudal lords, and it was carried 
through despite all the grumbling and indignation of Christianity as 
embodied in the priests (cf. Eden, History of the Poor, Book I b ; Guizot, 
Histoire de la civilisation en France ; Monteil, Histoire des Francois des 
divers etats, etc.), while, on the other hand, the minor priests, 
particularly at the beginning of the Middle Ages, incited the feudal 
serfs to “grumbling” and “indignation” against the temporal feudal 
lords (cf., inter alia , even the well-known capitulary of Char- 
lemagne 72 ). Compare also what was written above in connection with 
the “workers’ disturbances which flared up here and there”, about 
the “oppressed classes” and their revolts in the fourteenth century. 0 

The earlier forms of workers’ uprisings were connected with the 
degree of development of labour in each case and the resulting form 
of property; direct or indirect communist uprisings were connected 
with large-scale industry. Instead of going into this extensive history, 
Saint Max accomplishes a holy transition from the patient oppressed 
classes to the impatient oppressed classes: 

“Now, when everyone ought to develop into a man ” (“how,” for example, do the 
Catalonian workers “know” that “everyone ought to develop into a man”?), “the 
confining of man to machine labour amounts to slavery” (p. 158). 

Hence, prior to Spartacus and the uprising of the slaves, it was 
Christianity that prevented the “confining of man to machine 



a The passage is from August Theodor Woeniger’s book Publicistische Abhand- 
lungen, quoted by Carl Ernst Reichardt — “the master-bookbinder” — in his article 
“Schriften uber den Pauperismus” (cf. Karl Marx and Frederick Engels, The Holy 
Family, in the present edition, Vol. 4, pp. 9-11). — Ed. 

b Frederic Morton Eden, The State of the Poor, or, an History of the Labouring Classes 
in England . — Ed. 

c See this volume, p. 204. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 221 



labour” from “amounting to slavery”; and in the days of Spartacus it 
was only the concept of “man” that removed this relation and 
brought about slavery. “Or did” Stirner “perhaps” “even” hear 
something about the connection between modern labour unrest and 
machine production and wanted here to give an intimation of this? 
In that case it was not the introduction of machine labour that 
transformed the workers into rebels, but the introduction of the 
concept of “man” that transformed machine labour into slav- 
ery. — “If that is so” then “it indeed really looks as though” we have 
here a “unique” history of the workers’ movements. 

Second historical construction. 

“The bourgeoisie has preached the gospel of material enjoyment and is now 
surprised that this doctrine finds supporters among us proletarians” (p. 159). 

Just now the workers wanted to realise the concept of “man”, the 
holy; now it is “material enjoyment”, the worldly; above it was a 
question of the “drudgery” of labour, now it is only the labour of 
enjoyment. Saint Sancho strikes himself here on ambas sus valientes 
posaderas a — first of all on material history, and then on Stirner’s, holv 
history. According to material history, it was the aristocracy that first 
put the gospel of worldlv enjoyment in the place of enjoyment of the 
gospel; it was at first for the aristocracy that the sober bourgeoisie 
applied itself to work and it very cunningly left to the aristocracy the 
enjoyment from which it was debarred by its own laws (whereby the 
power of the aristocracy passed in the form of money into the 
pockets of the bourgeoisie). 

According to Stirner’s history, the bourgeoisie was satisfied to seek 
“the holy”, to pursue the cult of the state and to “transform all 
existing objects into imaginary ones”, and it required the Jesuits to 
“save sensuousness from complete decay”. According to this same 
Stirnerian history, the bourgeoisie usurped all power by means of 
revolution, consequently also its gospel, that of material enjoyment, 
although according to the same Stirnerian history we have now 
reached the point where “ideas alone rule the world”. Stirner’s 
hierarchy thus finds itself il entre ambas posaderas” . 

Third historical construction. 

Page 159: “After the bourgeois had given freedom from the commands and 
arbitrariness of individuals, there remained the arbitrariness which arises from the 
conjuncture of conditions and which can be called the fortuitousness of circumstances. 
There remained — luck and those favoured by luck.” 

Saint Sancho then makes the communists “find a law and a new 
order which puts an end to these fluctuations” (the thingumbob), 

a His two most ample buttocks. — Ed. 




222 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



about which order he knows this much, that the communists should 
now proclaim: “Let this order henceforth be holy!” (whereas he 
ought now rather to have proclaimed: Let the disorder of my 
fantasies be the holy order of the communists). “Here is wisdom” 
(Revelation of St. John, 13 : 18). “Let him that hath understanding 
count the number” of absurdities which Stirner — usually so verbose 
and always repeating himself — [here] squeezes into a few [lines]. 

In its most general form the first proposition reads: after the 
bourgeoisie had abolished feudalism, the bourgeoisie remained. Or: 
after the domination of individuals had been abolished in “Stirner’s” 
imagination, precisely the opposite remained to be done. “It indeed 
really looks as though” one could bring the two most distant 
historical epochs into a relationship which is the holy relationship, 
the relationship as the holy, the relationship in heaven. 

Incidentally, this proposition of Saint Sancho’s is not satisfied with 
the above-mentioned mode simple of absurdity, it has to bring it to the 
mode compose and bicompose a of absurdity. For, firstly, Saint Max 
believes the bourgeoisie which liberates itself that, by liberating itself 
from the commands and arbitrariness of individuals, it has liberated 
the mass of society as a whole from the commands and arbitrariness 
of individuals. Secondly, in reality it liberated itself not from the 
“commands and arbitrariness of individuals”, but from the domina- 
tion of the corporation, the guild, the estates, and hence was now for 
the first time, as actual individual bourgeois, in a position to impose 
“commands and arbitrariness” on the workers. Thirdly, it only 
abolished the more or less idealistic appearance of the former 
commands and former arbitrariness of individuals, in order to 
establish instead these commands and this arbitrariness in their 
material crudity. He, the bourgeois, wanted his “commands and 
arbitrariness” to be no longer restricted by the hitherto existing 
"commands and arbitrariness” of political power concentrated in 
the monarch, the nobility and the corporations, but at most re- 
stricted only by the general interests of the whole bourgeois 
class, as expressed in bourgeois legislation. He did nothing more 
than abolish the commands and arbitrariness over the commands 
and arbitrariness of the individual bourgeois (see “Political 
Liberalism”). 

Instead of making a real analysis of the conjuncture of conditions, 
which with the rule of the bourgeoisie became a totally different 
conjuncture of totally different conditions, Saint Sancho leaves it in 



J These terms were used by Charles Fourier (see Ch. Fourier, Theorie de I’unite 
universelle) . — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



223 



the form of the general category “conjuncture, etc.”, and bestows on 
it the still more indefinite name of “fortuitousness of cir- 
cumstances”, as though the “commands and arbitrariness of 
individuals” are not themselves a “conjuncture of conditions”. 
Having thus done away with the real basis of communism, i.e., the 
definite conjuncture of conditions under the bourgeois regime, he 
can now also transform this airy communism into his holy 
communism. “It indeed really looks” as though “Stirner” is a “man 
with only ideal”, imagined, historical “wealth” — the “ perfect ragamuf- 
fin ”. See “the book”, p. 362. 

This great construction or, rather, its major proposition is once 
more and with great emphasis repeated on page 189 in the following 
form: 

“Political liberalism abolished the inequality of master and servant; it made people 
masterless, anarchic” (!); “the master was then separated from the individual, from the 
egoist, to become a spectre, the law or the state.” 

Domination of spectres = (hierarchy) = absence of domination, 
equivalent to the domination of the “omnipotent” bourgeois. As we 
see, this domination of spectres is, on the contrary, the domination of 
the many actual masters; hence with equal justification communism 
could be regarded as liberation from this domination of the many. 
This, however, Saint Sancho could not do, for then not only his 
logical constructions of communism but also the whole construction 
of “the free ones” would be overthrown. But this is how it is 
throughout “the book”. A single conclusion from our saint’s own 
premises, a single historical fact, overthrows the entire series of 
penetrations and results. 

Fourth historical construction. On page 350, Saint Sancho derives 
communism directly from the abolition of serfdom. 

I. Major proposition : 

“Extremely much was gained when people succeeded in being regarded ” (!) “as 
property-owners. Thereby serfdom was abolished and everyone who until then had 
himself been property henceforth became a master .” 

(According to the mode simple of absurdity this means: serfdom was 
abolished as soon as it was abolished.) The mode compose of this ab- 
surdity is that Saint Sancho believes that people became “property- 
owners” by means of holy contemplation, by means of “regard- 
ing” and “being regarded”, whereas the difficulty consisted in 
becoming a “property-owner”, and consideration came later of 
itself. The mode bicompose of the absurdity is that when the abolition 
of serfdom, which at first was still partial, had begun to develop its 
consequences and thereby became universal, people ceased to be 




224 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



able to “succeed” in being “regarded” as worth owning (for the 
property-owners those they owned had become too expensive); 
consequently the vast mass “who until then had themselves been 
property”, i.e., unfree workers, became as a result not “masters”, but 
free workers. 

II. Minor historical proposition, which embraces about eight cen- 
turies, although one “will of course not perceive how momentous” it 
is (cf. Wigand, p. 194). 

“However, henceforth your having [ Dein Haben] and what you have [ Deine Habe ] no 
longer suffices, and is no longer recognised; on the other hand, your working and your 
work increases in value. We now respect your mastery of things as previously” (?) “we 
respected your possession of them. Your labour is your wealth. You are now the 
master or possessor of what you have obtained by work and not by inheritance” (ibid.). 

“Henceforth” — “no longer” — “on the other hand” — “now” — “as 
previously” — “now” — “or” — “not” — such is the content of this 
proposition. 

Although “Stirner” has “now” arrived at this, that you (viz., 
Szeliga) are the master of what you have obtained by work and not by 
inheritance, it “now” occurs to him that just the opposite is the case 
at present — and so he causes communism to be born as a monster 
from these two distorted propositions. 

III. Communist conclusion. 

“Since, however, now everything is inherited and every farthing you possess 
bears not the stamp of work, but of inheritance” (the culminating absurdity), “SO 
everything must be remoulded.” 

On this basis Szeliga is able to imagine that he has arrived at both 
the rise and fall of the medieval communes, and the communism of 
the nineteenth century. And thereby Saint Max, despite everything 
“inherited” and “obtained by work”, does not arrive at any “mastery 
of things”, but at most at “having” nonsense. 

Lovers of constructions can now see in addition on page 421 how 
Saint Max, after constructing communism from serfdom, then 
constructs it again in the form of serfdom under a liege lord — 
society — on the same model as he already, above, transformed the 
means by which we earn something into the “holy”, by “grace” of 
winch something is given to us. Now, in conclusion, we shall deal in 
addition only with a few “penetrations” into the essence of 
communism, which follow from the premises given above. 

First of all, “Stirner” gives a new theory of exploitation which consists 
in this: 

“the worker in a pin factory performs only one piece of work, only plays into the hand 
of another and is used, exploited by that other” (p. 158). 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



225 



Thus, here “Stirner” makes the discovery that the workers in a 
factory exploit one another, since they “play into the hands” of one 
another; whereas the factory-owner, whose hands do not work at all, 
cannot, therefore, exploit the workers. “Stirner” here gives a 
striking example of the lamentable position in which communism 
has put the German theoreticians. Now they have to concern 
themselves also with mundane things like pin factories, etc.,. in 
relation to which they behave like real barbarians, like Ojibbeway 
Indians and New Zealanders. 

Stirnerian communism “on the contrary says” (ibid.): 

“All work should have the aim of satisfying ‘man’. Therefore, he” (“man”) “must 
become master of it, i.e., be able to perform it as a totality.” 

“Man” must become a master! — “Man” remains a maker of 
pin-heads, but he has the consolation of knowing that the pin-head is 
part of the pin and that he is able to make the whole pin. The fatigue 
and disgust caused by the eternally repeated making of pin-heads is 
transformed, by this knowledge, into the “satisfaction of man”. 
O Proudhon! 

A further penetration: 



“Since communists declare that only free activity is the essence” ( iterum Crispinus d ) 
“of man, they, like every workaday mode of thought, need a Sunday, a time of exaltation 
and devotion, in addition to their dull labour 

Apart from the “essence of man” that is dragged in here, the 
unfortunate Sancho is forced to convert “free activity”, which is for 
the communists the creative manifestation of life arising from the 
free development of all abilities of the “whole fellow” (in order to 
make it comprehensible to “Stirner”), into “dull labour”, for our 
Berliner notices that the question here is not one of the “hard work 
of thought”. By this simple transformation the communists can now 
also be transposed into the “workaday mode of thought”. Then, of 
course, together with the work -day of the middle class its Sunday also 
is to be found again in communism. 

Page 161 : “The Sunday aspect of communism consists in the communist seeing in 
you the man, the brother.” 

Thus, the communist appears here as “man” and as “worker”. 
This Saint Sancho calls (loc. cit.) “a dual employment of man by the 
communists — an office of material earning and one of spiritual 
earning”. 



d Crispinus again. — Ed. 




226 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



Here, therefore, he brings back even “earning” and bureaucracy 
into communism which, of course, thereby “attains its final goal” 
and ceases to be communism. Incidentally he has to do this, because 
in his “union”, which he will construct later, each also is given a 
“dual position” — as man and as the “unique”. For the present he 
legitimises this dualism by foisting it on communism, a method we 
shall find again in his theory of feudalism and of utilisation. 

On page 344 “Stirner” believes that the “communists” want to 
“settle the question of property amicably”, and on page 413 he even 
makes them appeal to the self-sacrifice of people [and to] the 
self-denying disposition of the capitalists!* The few non- 
revolutionary communist bourgeois who made their appearance since 
the time of Babeuf were a rare occurrence; the vast majority of the 
communists in all countries are revolutionary. All communists in 
France reproach the followers of Saint-Simon and Fourier with their 
peaceableness and differ from the latter chiefly in their having 
abandoned all hope of an “amicable settlement”, just as in Britain it 
is the same criterion which chiefly distinguishes the Chartists from 
the socialists. Saint Max could discover the communist view of the 
“self-denying disposition of the rich” and the “self-sacrifice of 
people” from a few passages of Cabet, the very communist who 
most of all could give the impression that he appeals for devoument, 
self-sacrifice. These passages are aimed against the republicans and 
especially against the attacks on communism made by Monsieur 
Buchez, who still commands the following of a very small number of 
workers in Paris: 

“The same thing applies to self-sacrifice ( devoument ); it is the doctrine of Monsieur 
Buchez, this time divested of its Catholic form, for Monsieur Buchez undoubtedly 
fears that his Catholicism is repugnant to the mass of the workers, and drives them 
away. ‘In order to fulfil their duty ( devoir ) worthily’ — says Buchez — ‘self-sacrifice 
(devoument) is needed.’ — Let those who can understand the difference between devoir 
and devoument. — ‘We require self-sacrifice from everyone, both for great national 
unity and for the workers’ association ... it is necessary for us to be united, always 
devoted ( devoues ) to one another.’ — It is necessary, it is necessary — that is easy to say, 
and people have been saying it for a long time and they will go on saying it for a very 
long time yet without any more success, if they cannot devise other means! Buchez 
complains of the self-seeking of the rich; but what is the use of such complaints? All 
who are unwilling to sacrifice themselves Buchez declares to be enemies. 

“‘If,’ he says, ‘impelled by egoism, a man refuses to sacrifice himself for others, 
what is to be done?... We have not a moment’s hesitation in answering: society always 

* [The following passage is crossed out in the manuscript:] Here Saint Max again 
ascribes to himself the wisdom of seizing and striking, as though his whole harangue 
about the rebellious proletariat were not an unsuccessful travesty of Weitling and his 
thieving proletariat — Weitling is one of the few communists whom he knows by the 
grace of Biuntschli. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



227 



has the right to take from us what our own duty bids us sacrifice to it.... Self-sacrifice is 
the only means of fulfilling one’s duty. Each one of us must sacrifice himself, always 
and everywhere. He who out of egoism refuses to fulfil his duty of self-sacrifice must 
be compelled to do it.’ — Thus Buchez cries out to all: sacrifice yourselves, sacrifice 
yourselves! Think only of sacrificing yourselves! Does this not mean to misunderstand 
human nature and trample it underfoot? Is not this a false view? We might almost 
say — a childish , silly view” (Cabet, Refutation des doctrines de VAtelier, pp. 19, 20). 

Cabet, further, on page 22, demonstrates to the republican 
Buchez that he inevitably arrives at an “aristocracy of self-sacrifice” 
with various ranks, and then asks ironically: 

“What then becomes of devoument ? What remains of devoument if people sacrifice 
themselves only in order to reach the highest pinnacles of hierarchy}... Such a system 
might originate in the mind of a man who would like to become Pope or Car- 
dinal — but in the minds of workers!!!” — “M. Buchez does not want labour to 
become a pleasant diversion, nor that man should work for his own well-being and 
create new pleasures for himself. He asserts ... ‘that man exists on earth only to fulfil a 
calling, a duty (une fonction, un devoir)’. ‘No,’ he preaches to the communists, ‘man, this 
great force, has not been created for himself (n'a point ete fait pour lui-meme).... That is a 
crude idea. Man is a worker ( ouvrier ) in the world, he must accomplish the work 
(oeuvre) which morality imposes on his activity, that is his duty.... Let us never lose sight 
of the fact that we have to fulfil a high calling (une haute fonction) — a calling that began 
with the first day of man’s existence and will come to an end only at the same time as 
humanity.' — But who revealed all these fine things to [M.] Buchez? (Mais qui a revele 
toutes ces belles choses a M. Buchez lui-meme” — which Stirner would have translated: How 
is it that Buchez knows so well what man should do?) — "Du reste, comprenne qui 
pourra. A — Buchez continues: ‘What! Man had to wait thousands of centuries in order 
to learn from you communists that he was created for himself and has no other aim 
than to live in all possible pleasures.... But one must not fall into such an error. One 
must not forget that we are created in order to labour (faits pour travailler), to labour 
always, and that the only thing we can demand is what is necessary for life (la suffisante 
vie), i.e., the well-being that suffices for us to carry out our calling properly. 
Everything that is beyond this boundary is absurd and dangerous.’ — But just prove it, 
prove it! And do not be satisfied merely with delivering oracles like a prophet! At the 
very outset you speak of thousands of centuries! And then, who asserts that people have 
been waiting for us down all the centuries? But have people perhaps been waiting for 
you with all your theories about devoument, devoir, nationalite frangaise, association 
ouvriere ? ‘In conclusion,’ says Buchez, ‘we ask you not to take offence at what we have 
said.’ — We also are polite Frenchmen and we, too, ask you not to take offence” 
(p. 31). — ’“Believe us,’ says Buchez, ‘there exists a communaute which was created long 
ago and of which you too are members.’ — Believe us, Buchez,” concludes Cabet, 
“become a communist!” 

“Self-sacrifice”, “duty”, “social obligation”, “the right of society”, 
“the calling, the destiny of man”, “to be a worker the calling of 
man”, “moral cause”, “workers’ association”, “creation of what is 
indispensable for life” — are not these the same things for which 
Saint Sancho reproaches the communists, and for the absence of 
which the communists are reproached by M. Buchez, whose solemn 

a “However, let him who can understand it.” — Ed. 




228 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



reproaches are ridiculed by Cabet? Do we not find here even 
Stirner’s “hierarchy”? 

Finally, Saint Sancho deals communism the coup de grace on 
page 169, by uttering the following proposition: 

“By taking away also property" (!) “the socialists do not take into account that its 
continuance is safeguarded by the peculiarities of human beings. Are only money and 
goods property, or is not every opinion also something that is mine, that belongs to 
me? Hence , every opinion must be abolished or made impersonal.” 

Or does Saint Sancho’s opinion, insofar as it does not become the 
opinion of others as well, give him command over anything, even 
over another’s opinion? By bringing into play against communism 
the capital of his opinion, Saint Max again does nothing but advance 
against it the oldest and most trivial bourgeois objections, and he 
thinks he has said something new because for him, the “educated” 
Berliner, these hackneyed ideas are new. Destutt de Tracy among, 
and after, many others said the same thing much better approxi- 
mately thirty years ago, and also later, in the book quoted below. For 
example: 

“Formal proceedings were instituted against property, and arguments were 
brought forward for and against it, as though it depended on us to decide whether 
property should or should not exist in the world; but this is based on a complete 
misunderstanding of our nature” ( Traite de la volonte, Paris, 1826, p. 18). 

And then M. Destutt de Tracy undertakes to prove that propriete, 
individuality and personnalite are identical, that the “ego” [ moi ] also 
includes “mine” [mien], and he finds as a natural basis for private 
property that 

“nature has endowed man with an inevitable and inalienable property, property in the 
form of his own individuality” (p. 17). — The individual “clearly sees that this ego is the 
exclusive owner of the body which it animates, the organs which it sets in motion, all 
their capacities, all their forces, all the effects they produce, all their passions and 
actions; for all this ends and begins with this ego, exists only through it, is set in motion 
through its action; and no other person can make use of these same instruments or be 
affected in the same way by them” (p. 16). “Property exists, if not precisely 
everywhere that a sentient individual exists, at least wherever there is a conative 
individual” (p. 19). 

Having thus made private property and personality identical, 
Destutt de Tracy with a play on the words propriete and propre a , like 
“Stirner” with his play on the words Mein h and Meinung, c Eigentum d 
and Eigenheit, e arrives at the following conclusion: 

a One’s own. — Ed. 

b My, mine. — Ed. 

' Opinion, view. — Ed. 

d Property. — Ed. 

‘ Peculiarity. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



229 



“It is, therefore, quite futile to argue about whether it would not be better for each 
of us to have nothing of our own ( de discuter s’il ne vaudrait pas mieux que rien ne fut 
propre a chacun de nous)... in any case it is equivalent to asking whether it would not be 
desirable for us to be quite different from what we are, and even to examining 
whether it would not be better for us not to exist at all” (p. 22). 

“These are extremely popular”, now already traditional objections 
to communism, and for that very reason “it is not surprising that 
Stirner” repeats them. 

When the narrow-minded bourgeois says to the communists: by 
abolishing property, i.e., my existence as a capitalist, as a landed 
proprietor, as a factory-owner, and your existence as workers, you 
abolish my individuality and your own; by making it impossible for 
me to exploit you, the workers, to rake in my profit, interest or rent, 
you make it impossible for me to exist as an individual. — When, 
therefore, the bourgeois tells the communists: by abolishing my 
existence as a bourgeois, you abolish my existence as an individual ; 
when thus he identifies himself as a bourgeois with himself as an 
individual, one must, at least, recognise his frankness and shameless- 
ness. For the bourgeois it is actually the case, he believes himself to be 
an individual only insofar as he is a bourgeois. 

But when the theoreticians of the bourgeoisie come forward and 
give a general expression to this assertion, when they equate the 
bourgeois’s property with individuality in theory as well and want to 
give a logical justification for this equation, then this nonsense 
begins to become solemn and holy. 

Above “Stirner” refuted the communist abolition of private 
property by first transforming private property into “having” and 
then declaring the verb “to have” an indispensable word, an eternal 
truth, because even in communist society it could happen that Stirner 
will “have” a stomach-ache. In exactly the same way here his 
arguments regarding the impossibility of abolishing private property 
depend on his transforming private property into the concept of 
property, on exploiting the etymological connection between the 
words Eigentum and eigert and declaring the word eigen an eternal 
truth, because even under the communist system it could happen 
that a stomach-ache will be eigen to him. All this theoretical nonsense, 
which seeks refuge in etymology, would be impossible if the actual 
private property that the communists want to abolish had not been 
transformed into the abstract notion of “property”. This transfor- 
mation, on the one hand, saves one the trouble of having to say 



Own, peculiar. — Ed. 




230 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



anything, or even merely to know anything, about actual private 
property and, on the other hand, makes it easy to discover a 
contradiction in communism, since after the abolition of ( actual ) 
property it is, of course, easy to discover all sorts of things in 
communism which can be included in the concept “property”. In 
reality, of course, the situation is just the reverse.* In reality 1 possess 
private property only insofar as I have something vendible, whereas 
what is peculiar to me [meine Eigenheit ] may not be vendible at all. My 
frock-coat is private property for me only so long as I can barter, 
pawn or sell it, so long [as it] is [marketable]. If it loses that feature, if 
it becomes tattered, it can still have a number of features which make 
it valuable for me, it may even become a feature of me and turn me 
into a tatterdemalion. But no economist would think of classing it as 
my private property, since it does not enable me to command any, 
even the smallest, amount of other people’s labour. A lawyer, an 
ideologist of private property, could perhaps still indulge in such 
twaddle. Private property alienates [entfremdet] the individuality not 
only of people but also of things. Land has nothing to do with rent 
of land, the machine has nothing to do with profit. For the landed 
proprietor, land has the significance only of rent of land; he leases 
his plots of land and receives rent; this is a feature which land can 
lose without losing a single one of its inherent features, without, for 
example, losing any part of its fertility; it is a feature the extent and 
even the existence of which depends on social relations which are 
created and destroyed without the assistance of individual landed 
proprietors. It is the same with machines. How little connection there 
is between money, the most general form of property, and personal 
peculiarity, how much they are directly opposed to each other was 
already known to Shakespeare better than to our theorising petty 
bourgeois: 

Thus much of this will make black, white; foul, fair; 

Wrong, right; base, noble; old, young; coward, valiant. 

This yellow slave... 

Will make the hoar leprosy adored... 

This it is 

That makes the wappened widow wed again; 

She, whom the spital-house and ulcerous sores 



* [The following passage is crossed out in the manuscript:] Actual private 
property is something extremely general which has nothing at all to do with 
individuality, which indeed directly nullifies individuality. Insofar as I am regarded as 
a property-owner I am not regarded as an individual — a statement which is 
corroborated every day by the marriages for money. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



231 



Would cast the gorge at, this embalms and spices 
To th’ April day again... 

Thou visible god, 

That solder’st close impossibilities, 

And mukest them kiss! 3 

In a word, rent of land, profit, etc., these actual forms of existence 
of private property, are social relations corresponding to a definite 
stage of production, and they are “individual” only so long as they 
have not become fetters on the existing productive forces. 

According to Destutt de Tracy, the majority of people, the 
proletarians, must have lost all individuality long ago, although 
nowadays it looks as if it was precisely among them that individuality 
is most developed. For the bourgeois it is all the easier to prove on 
the basis of his language the identity of commercial and individual, 
or even universal, human relations, as this language itself is a 
product of the bourgeoisie, and therefore both in actuality and in 
language the relations of buying and selling have been made the 
basis of all others. For example, propriete — property [ Eigentum ] and 
characteristic feature [Eigenschaft]; property — possession [Eigentum] 
and peculiarity [Eigentiimlichkeit]; “eigen” [“one’s own’’] — in the 
commercial and in the individual sense; valeur, value, Wert b ; 
commerce, Verkehr c ; echange, exchange , Austausch d , etc., all of which 
are used both for commercial relations and for characteristic 
features and mutual relations of individuals as such. In the other 
modern languages this is equally the case. If Saint Max seriously 
applies himself to exploit this ambiguity, he may easily succeed in 
making a brilliant series of new economic discoveries, without 
knowing anything about political economy; for, indeed, his new 
economic facts, which we shall take note of later, lie wholly within 
this sphere of synonymy. 

Our kindly, credulous Jacques takes the bourgeois play on the 
words Eigentum [property] and Eigenschaft [characteristic feature] so 
literally, in such holy earnest, that he even endeavours to behave like 
a private property-owner in relation to his own features, as we shall 
see later on. 

Finally, on page 421, “Stirner” instructs communism that 

“ actually it” (viz., communism) “does not attack property, but the alienation of 
property”. 



3 William Shakespeare, Timon of Athens, Act IV, Scene 3. — Ed. 
b Worth, value. — Ed. 

c Intercourse, traffic, commerce, communication. — Ed. 
d Exchange, barter, interchange. — Ed. 




232 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engel: 



In this new revelation of his, Saint Max merely repeats an old 
witticism already used repeatedly by, for example, the Saint- 
Simonists. Cf ., for example, Legons sur V Industrie et les finances, Paris, 
1832 a , where, inter alia, it is stated: 

“Property will not be abolished, but its form will be changed ... it will for the first 
time become true personification ... it will for the first time acquire its real, individual 
character” (pp. 42, 43). 

Since this phrase, introduced by the French and particularly 
enlarged on by Pierre Leroux, was seized on with great pleasure by 
the German speculative socialists and used for further speculation, 
and finally gave occasion for reactionary intrigues and sharp 
practices — we shall not deal with it here where it says nothing, but 
later on, in connection with true socialism.* 5 

Saint Sancho, [following the] example of Woeniger, whom 
Reichardt [used], takes delight in turning the proletarians, [and 
hence] also the communists, into “ragamuffins ” . He defines his 
“ragamuffin” on page 362 as a “man possessing only ideal wealth”. 
If Stirner’s “ragamuffins” ever set up a vagabond kingdom, as the 
Paris beggars did in the fifteenth century, then Saint Sancho will be 
the vagabond king, for he is the “perfect” ragamuffin, a man 
possessing not even ideal wealth and therefore living on the interest 
from the capital of his opinion. 

C. Humane Liberalism 

After Saint Max has interpreted liberalism and communism as 
imperfect modes of existence of philosophical “man”, and thereby 
also of modern German philosophy in general (which he was 
justified in doing, since in Germany not only liberalism but 
communism as well was given a petty-bourgeois and at the same time 
highflown ideological form), after this, it is easy for him to depict the 
latest forms of German philosophy, what he has called “humane 
liberalism”, as perfect liberalism and communism, and, at the same 
time, as criticism of both of them. 

With the aid of this holy construction we now get the following 
three delightful transformations (cf. also “The Economy of the Old 
Testament”): 

1. The individual is not man, therefore he is of no value — absence 
of personal will, ordinance — “whose name will be named”: “master- 
less ” — political liberalism, which we have already dealt with above. 



a The author of these lectures is Isaac Pereire. — Ed. 
b See this volume, p. 468. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



233 



2. The individual has nothing human, therefore no validity 
attaches to mine and thine or property: “propertyless” — commu- 
nism, which we have also already dealt with. 

3. In criticism the individual should give place to man, now found 
for the first time: “godless” =identity of “masterless” and “property- 
less” — humane liberalism (pp. 180-81). — In a more detailed 
exposition of this last negative unity, the unshakable orthodoxy of 
Jacques reaches the following climax (p. 189): 

“The egoism of property loses its last possession if even the words ‘my God’ 
become meaningless, for ” (a grand “for”!) “God only exists if he has at heart the 
salvation of each individual, just as the latter seeks his salvation in God.” 

According to this, the French bourgeois would only “lose” his 
“last” “property” if the word adieu were banished from the 
language. In complete accord with the preceding construction, 
property in God, holy property in heaven, the property of fantasy, 
the fantasy of property, are here declared to be supreme property 
and the last sheet-anchor of property. 

From these three illusions about liberalism, communism and 
German philosophy, he now concocts his new — and, thanks be to the 
“holy”, this time the last — transition to the “ego”. Before following 
him in this, let us once more glance at his last “arduous life struggle” 
with “humane liberalism”. 

After our worthy Sancho in his new role of caballero andante , a and 
in fact as caballero de la tristisima figura, h has traversed the whole of 
history, everywhere battling and “blowing down” spirits and 
spectres, “dragons and ostriches, satyrs and hobgoblins, wild beasts 
of the desert and vultures, bitterns and hedgehogs” (cf. Isaiah, 34: 
11-14), how happy he must now be, after his wanderings through all 
these different lands, to come at last to his island of Barataria, 74 to 
“the land” as such, where “Man” goes about in puris naturalibus c l Let 
us once more recall his great thesis, the dogma imposed on him, on 
which his whole construction of history rests, to the effect that: 

“the truths which arise from the concept of man are revered as revelations of precisely 
this concept and regarded as holy”; “the revelations of this holy concept”, even “with 
the abolition of many a truth manifested by means of this concept, are not deprived of 
their holiness” (p. 51). 

We need hardly repeat what we have already proved to our holy 
author in respect of all his examples, namely, that empirical 



d Knight-errant. — Ed. 

Knight of the most rueful countenance. — Ed. 
1 In the pure natural state. — Ed. 




234 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



relations, created by real people in their real intercourse and not at 
all by the holy concept of man, are afterwards interpreted, 
portrayed, imagined, consolidated and justified by people as a 
revelation of the concept “man”. One may also recall his hierarchy. 
And now on to humane liberalism. 

On page 44, where Saint Max “in brief” “contrasts Feuerbach’s 
[theological] view with our view”, at first nothing but phrases are 
advanced against Feuerbach. As we already saw in regard to the 
manufacture of spirits, where “Sdrner” places his stomach among 
the stars (the third Dioscuros, a patron saint and protector against 
seasickness /5 ), because he and his stomach are “different names for 
totally different things” (p. 42), so, here, too, essence [ Weserf ] 
appears first of all as an existing thing, and “so it is now said” (p. 44): 

“The supreme being is, indeed, the essence of man, but precisely because it is his 
essence, and not man himself, it makes absolutely no difference whether we see this essence 
outside man and perceive it as ‘God’ or find it in man and call it the ‘essence of man’ or 
‘Man’. I am neither God nor Man, neither the supreme being nor my essence — and, 
therefore, in the main, it makes no difference whether I think of this essence as inside 
me or outside me.” 

Hence, the “essence of man” is presupposed here as an existing 
thing, it is the “supreme being”, it is not the “ego”, and, instead of 
saying something about “essence”, Saint Max restricts himself to the 
simple statement that it makes “no difference” “whether I think of it 
as inside me or outside me”, in this locality or in that. That this 
indifference to essence is no mere carelessness of style is already 
evident from the fact that he himself makes the distinction between 
essential and inessential and that with him even “the noble essence of 
egoism” finds a place (p. 71). Incidentally everything the German 
theoreticians have said so far about essence and non-essence is to be 
found already far better said by Hegel in his Logik. 

We found the boundless orthodoxy of “Stirner” with regard to the 
illusions of German philosophy expressed in concentrated form in 
the fact that he constantly foists “Man” on history as the sole dramatis 
persona and believes that “Man” has made history. Now we shall find 
the same thing recurring in connection with Feuerbach, whose 
illusions “Stirner” faithfully accepts in order to build further on 
their foundation. 

Page 77: “In general Feuerbach only transposes subject and predicate, giving 
preference to the latter. But since he says himself: ‘Love is not holy because it is a 
predicate of God (nor have people ever held it to be holy for that reason) but it is a 
predicate of God because it is divine by and for itself,’ he was able to conclude that the 



a Wesen can mean either essence or being. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



235 



struggle had to be begun against the predicates themselves, against love and 
everything holy. How could he hope to turn people away from God, once he had left 
them the divine ? And if, as Feuerbach says, the main thing for people has never been 
God, but only his predicates, he could after all have allowed them to keep this tinsel, 
since the puppet, the real kernel, still remained.” 

Since, therefore, Feuerbach “ himself ’ says this, it is reason enough 
for Jacques le bonhomme to believe him that people have esteemed 
love because it is “divine by and for itself” . If precisely the opposite 
of what Feuerbach says took place — and we “make bold to say this” 
( Wigand , p. 157) — if neither God nor his predicates have ever been 
the main thing for people, if this itself is only a religious illusion of 
German theory — it means that the very same thing has happened to 
our Sancho as happened to him before in Cervantes, when four 
stumps were put under his saddle while he slept and his ass was led 
away from under him. 

Relying on these statements of Feuerbach, Sancho starts a battle 
which was likewise already anticipated by Cervantes in the 
nineteenth chapter, where the ingenioso hidalgo fights against the 
predicates, the mummers, while they are carrying the corpse of the 
world to the grave and who, entangled in their robes and shrouds, 
are unable to move and so make it easy for our hidalgo to overturn 
them with his lance and give them a thorough thrashing. The last 
attempt to exploit further the criticism of religion as an independent 
sphere (a criticism which has been flogged to the point of 
exhaustion), to remain within the premises of German theory and 
yet to appear to be going beyond them, and to cook from this bone, 
gnawed away to the last fibres, a thin Rumford beggar’s broth 76 [for 
“the] book” — this last attempt consisted in attacking material 
relations, not in their actual form, and not even in the form of the 
mundane illusions of those who are practically involved in the 
present-day world, but in the heavenly extract of their mundane 
form as predicates, as emanations from God, as angels. Thus, the 
heavenly kingdom was now repopulated and abundant new material 
created for the old method of exploitation of this heavenly kingdom. 
Thus, the struggle against religious illusions, against God, was again 
substituted for the real struggle. Saint Bruno, who earns his bread by 
theology, in his “arduous life struggle” against substance makes the 
same attempt pro aris et foci? as a theologian to go beyond the limits 
of theology. His “substance” is nothing but the predicates of God 
united under one name; with the exception of personality, which 
he reserves for himself — these predicates of God are again nothing 



For home and hearth. — Ed. 




236 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



but deified names for the ideas of people about their definite, 
empirical relations, ideas which subsequently they hypocritically 
retain because of practical considerations. With the theoretical 
equipment inherited from Hegel it is, of course, not possible even to 
understand the empirical, material attitude of these people. Owing 
to the fact that Feuerbach showed the religious world as an illusion of 
the earthly world — a world which in his writing appears merely as a 
phrase — German theory too was confronted with the question which 
he left unanswered: how did it come about that people “got” these 
illusions “into their heads”? Even for the German theoreticians this 
question paved the way to the materialistic view of the world, a view 
which is not without premises, but which empirically observes the 
actual material premises as such and for that reason is, for the 
first time, actually a critical view of the world. This path was already 
indicated in the Deutsch-Franzdsische Jahrbiicher — in the Einleitung 
zur Kritik der Hegelschen Rechtsphilosophie and Zur Judenfrage , a 
But since at that time this was done in philosophical phraseology, the 
traditionally occurring philosophical expressions such as “human 
essence”, “species”, etc., gave the German theoreticians the desired 
reason for misunderstanding the real trend of thought and believing 
that here again it was a question merely of giving a new turn to their 
worn-out theoretical garment — just as Dr. Arnold Ruge, the Dottore 
Graziano of German philosophy, imagined that he could continue as 
before to wave his clumsy arms about and display his pedantic-farci- 
cal mask. One has to “leave philosophy aside” ( Wigand , p. 187, cf. 
Hess, Die letzten Philosophen, p. 8), one has to leap out of it and devote 
oneself like an ordinary man to the study of actuality, for which there 
exists also an enormous amount of literary material, unknown, of 
course, to the philosophers. When, after that, one again encounters 
people like Krummacher or “Sftrner”, one finds that one has long ago 
left them “behind” and below. Philosophy and the study of the 
actual world have the same relation to one another as onanism and 
sexual love. Saint Sancho, who in spite of his absence of 
thought — which was noted by us patiently and by him emphatical- 
ly — remains within the world of pure thoughts, can, of course, save 
himself from it only by means of a moral postulate, the postulate of 
“ thoughtlessness ” (p. 196 of “the book”). He is a bourgeois who saves 
himself in the face of commerce by the banqueroute cochenne , 77 
whereby, of course, he becomes not a proletarian, but an impecu- 
nious, bankrupt bourgeois. He does not become a man of the world, 
but a bankrupt philosopher without thoughts. 



a See present edition, Vol. 3, pp. 146-87. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



237 



The predicates of God handed down from Feuerbach as real 
forces over people, as hierarchs, are the monstrosity which is 
substituted for the empirical world and which “Stirner” finds in 
existence. So heavily does Stirner’s entire “peculiarity” depend 
merely on “prompting”. If “Stirner” (see also p. 63) reproaches 
Feuerbach for reaching no result because he turns the predicate into 
the subject and vice versa, he himself is far less capable of arriving at 
anything, [for] he faithfully accepts these Feuerbachian predicates, 
transformed into subjects, as real personalities ruling [the world], he 
faithfully accepts these phrases about relations as actual relations, 
attaching the predicate “holy” to them, transforming this predicate into 
a subject, the “holy”, i.e., doing exactly the same as that for which he 
reproaches Feuerbach. And so, after he has thus completely got rid 
of the definite content that was the matter at issue, he begins his 
struggle — i.e., his “antipathy” — against this “holy”, which, of 
course, always remains the same. Feuerbach has still the conscious- 
ness “that for him it is ‘only a matter of destroying an illusion’” — and 
it is this with which Saint Max reproaches him (p. 77 of “the 
book”) — although Feuerbach still attaches much too great impor- 
tance to the struggle against this illusion. In “Stirner” even this 
consciousness has “all gone”, he actually believes in the domination 
of the abstract ideas of ideology in the modern world; he believes 
that in his struggle against “predicates”, against concepts, he is no 
longer attacking an illusion, but the real forces that rule the world. 
Hence his manner of turning everything upside-down, hence the 
immense credulity with which he takes at their face value all the 
sanctimonious illusions, all the hypocritical asseverations of the 
bourgeoisie. How little, incidentally, the “puppet” is the “real 
kernel” of the “tinsel”, and how lame this beautiful analogy is, can 
best be seen from “Stirner’s” own “puppet” — “the book”, which 
contains no “kernel”, whether “real” or not “real”, and where even 
the little that there is in its 491 pages scarcely deserves the name 
“tinsel”. — If, however, we must find some sort of “kernel” in it, 
then that kernel is the German petty bourgeois. 

Incidentally, as regards the source of Saint Max’s hatred of 
“predicates”, he himself gives an extremely naive disclosure in the 
“Apologetic Commentary”. He quotes the following passage from 
Das Wesen des Christenthums (p. 31): “A true atheist is only one for 
whom the predicates of the divine being, e.g., love, wisdom, justice 
are nothing, but not one for whom only the subject of these predicates 
is nothing” — and then he exclaims triumphantly: “ Does this not hold 
good for Stirner ?” — “Here is wisdom.” In the above passage Saint 
Max found a hint as to how one should start in order to go “ farthest 




238 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



of all". He believes Feuerbach that the above passage reveals 
the “essence” of the “ true atheist", and lets Feuerbach set him the 
“task” of becoming a “true atheist”. The “unique” is “the true 
atheist" . 

Even more credulously than in relation to Feuerbach does he 
“handle” matters in relation to Saint Bruno or “criticism”. We shall 
gradually see all the things that he allows “criticism” to impose on 
him, how he puts himself under its police surveillance, how it dictates 
his mode of life, his “calling”. For the time being it suffices to 
mention as an example of his faith in criticism that on page 1 86 he 
treats “Criticism” and the “Mass” as two persons fighting against 
each other and “striving to free themselves from egoism”, and 
on page 187 he “accepts” both “for what they ... give themselves out 
to be". 

With the struggle against humane liberalism, the long struggle of 
the Old Testament, when man was a school-master of the unique, 
comes to an end; the time is fulfilled, and the gospel of grace and joy 
is ushered in for sinful humanity. 



The struggle over “man” is the fulfilment of the word, as written 
in the twenty-first chapter of Cervantes, which deals with “the high 
adventure and rich prize of Mambrino’s helmet”. Our Sancho, who 
in everything imitates his former lord and present servant, “has 
sworn to win Mambrino’s helmet” — Man — for himself. After having 
during his various “campaigns” 3 sought in vain to find the 
longed-for helmet among the ancients and moderns, liberals and 
communists, “he caught sight of a man on a horse carrying 
something on his head which shone like gold”. And he said to Don 
Quixote-Szeliga: “If I am not mistaken, there is someone 

approaching us bearing on his head that helmet of Mambrino, about 
which I swore the oath you know of.” “Take good care of what you 
say, your worship, and even greater care of what you do,” replied 
Don Quixote, who by now has become wiser. “Tell me, can you not 
see that knight coming towards us on a dapple-grey steed with a 
gold helmet on his head?” — “What I see and perceive,” replies Don 
Quixote, “is nothing but a man on a grey ass like yours with 
something glittering on his head.” — “Why, that is Mambrino’s 
helmet,” says Sancho. 



3 In the German original the word Ausziige is used which can mean departures, 
campaigns or extracts, abstracts. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



239 



Meanwhile, at a gentle trot there approaches them Bruno, the holy 
barber, on his small ass, criticism, with his barber’s basin on his head; 
Saint Sancho sets on him lance in hand. Saint Bruno jumps from his 
ass, drops the basin (for which reason we saw him here at the Council 
without the basin) and rushes off across country, “for he is the Critic 
himself”. Saint Sancho with great joy picks up the helmet of 
Mambrino, and to Don Quixote’s remark that it looks exactly like a 
barber’s basin he replies: “This famous, enchanted helmet, which 
has become ‘ghostly’, undoubtedly fell into the hands of a man who 
was unable to appreciate its worth, and so he melted down one half 
of it and hammered out the other half in such a way that, as you 
say, it appears to be a barber’s basin; in any case, whatever it may 
look like to the vulgar eye, for me, since I know its value, that is a 
matter of indifference.” 

“The second splendour, the second property, has now been won!” 

Now that he has gained his helmet, “man", he puts himself in 
opposition to him, behaves towards him as towards his “most 
irreconcilable enemy” and declares outright to him (why, we shall see 
later) that he (Saint Sancho) is not “man”, but an “unhuman being, 
the inhuman”. In the guise of this “inhuman”, he now moves to 
Sierra-Morena, in order to prepare himself by acts of penitence for 
the splendour of the New Testament. There he strips himself “stark 
naked” (p. 1 84) in order to achieve his peculiarity and surpass what his 
predecessor in Cervantes does in chapter twenty-five: 



“And hurriedly stripping off his breeches, he stood in his skin and his shirt. And 
then, without more ado, he took two goat leaps into the air turning head over heels, 
thereby revealing such things as caused his trusty armour-bearer to turn Rosinante 
aside, so as not to see them.” 



The “inhuman” far surpasses its mundane prototype. It “ resolutely 
turns its back on itself and thus also turns away from the disquieting 
critic”, and “leaves him behind”. The “ inhuman ” then enters into an 
argument with criticism that has been “left behind”; it “despises it- 
self”, it “conceives itself in comparison with another”, it “commands 
God”, it “seeks its better self outside itself”, it does penance for not yet 
being unique, it declares itself to be the unique, “the egoistical and the 
unique ” — although it was hardly necessary for it to state this after 
having resolutely turned its back on itself. The “inhuman” has 
accomplished all this by its own efforts (see Pfister, Geschichte der 
Teutschen ) and now, purified and triumphant, it rides on its ass into 
the kingdom of the unique. 

End of the Old Testament 




240 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



THE NEW TESTAMENT: “EGO ” 78 
1. The Economy of the New Testament 



Whereas in the Old Testament the object of our edification was 
“unique” logic in the framework of the past, we are now confronted 
by the present time in the framework of “unique” logic. We have 
already thrown sufficient light on the “unique” in his manifold 
antediluvian “refractions” — as man, Caucasian Caucasian, perfect 
Christian, truth of humane liberalism, negative unity of realism and 
idealism, etc., etc. Along with the historical construction of the 
“ego”, the “ego” itself also collapses. This “ego”, the end of the 
historical construction, is no “corporeal” ego, carnally procreated by 
man and woman, which needs no construction in order to exist; it is 
an “ego” spiritually created by two categories, “idealism” and 
“realism,” a merely conceptual existence. 

The New Testament, which has already been dissolved together 
with its premise, the Old Testament, possesses a domestic 
economy that is literally as wisely designed as that of the Old, namely 
the same “with various transformations”, as can be seen from the 
following table: 

I. Peculiarity= the ancients, child, Negro, etc., in their truth, i.e., 
development from the “world of things” to one’s “own” outlook 
and taking possession of this world. Among the ancients this led 
to riddance of the world, among the moderns — riddance of spirit, 
among the liberals — riddance of the individual, among the com- 
munists — riddance of property, among the • humane [liber- 
als] — riddance of God : hence it led in general to the category of 
riddance (freedom) as the goal. The negated category of riddance 
is peculiarity, which of course has no other content than this rid- 
dance. Peculiarity is the philosophically constructed quality of all 
the qualities of Stirner’s individual. 

II. The owner — as such Stirner has penetrated beyond the un- 
truthfulness of the world of things and the world of spirit; hence 
the moderns, the phase of Christianity within the logical develop- 
ment: youth, Mongol. — Just as the moderns divide into the triply 
determined free ones, so the owner falls into three further deter- 
mi nations: 

1. My power, corresponding to political liberalism, where the 
truth of right is brought to light and right as the power of “man” 
is resolved in power as the right of the “ego”. The struggle 
against the state as such. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



241 



2. My intercourse, corresponding to communism, whereby the 
truth of society is brought to light and society (in its forms of 
prison society, family, state, bourgeois society, etc.) as inter- 
course mediated by “man” is resolved in the intercourse of 
the “ego”. 

3. My self-enjoyment, corresponding to critical, humane liber- 
alism, in which the truth of criticism, the consumption, dissolu- 
tion and truth of absolute self-consciousness, comes to light as 
self-consumption, and criticism as dissolution in the interests 
of man is transformed into dissolution in the interests of the 
“ego”. 

THe peculiarity of the individuals was resolved, as we have 
seen, in the universal category of peculiarity, which was the 
negation of riddance, of freedom in general. A description of 
the special qualities of the individual, therefore, can again only 
consist in the negation of this “freedom” in its three “refrac- 
tions”; each of these negative freedoms is now converted by its 
negation into a positive quality. Obviously, just as in the Old 
Testament riddance of the world of things and the world of 
thoughts was already regarded as the acquisition of both these 
worlds, so here also it is a matter of course that this peculiarity or 
acquisition of things and thoughts is in its turn represented as 
perfect riddance. 

The “ego” with its property, its world, consisting of the 
qualities just “pointed out”, is owner. As self-enjoying and 
self-consuming, it is the “ego” raised to the second power, the 
owner of the owner, it being as much rid of the owner as the 
owner belongs to it; the result is “absolute negativity” in its dual 
determination as indifference, “unconcern” 3 and negative 
relation to itself, the owner. Its property in respect of the world 
and its riddance of the world is now transformed into this 
negative relation to itself, into this self-dissolution and self- 
ownership of the owner. The ego, thus determined, is — 

III. The unique, who again, therefore, has no other content 
than that of owner plus the philosophical determination of the 
“negative relation to himself”. The profound Jacques pretends 
that there is nothing to say about this unique, because it is a corpo- 
real, not constructed individual. But the matter here is rather the 
same as in the case of Hegel’s absolute idea at the end of the Logik 
and of absolute personality at the end of the Encyklopadie, about 
which there is likewise nothing to say because the construction 
contains everything that can be said about such constructed per- 

3 In the manuscript the Berlin dialect form Jleichjiiltigkeit (unconcern) is used. — Ed. 




242 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



sonalities. Hegel knows this and does not mind admitting it, 
whereas Stirner hypocritically maintains that his “unique” is also 
something different from the constructed unique alone, but 
something that cannot be expressed, viz., a corporeal individual. 

This hypocritical appearance vanishes if the thing is reversed, 
if the unique is defined as owner, and it is said of the owner that 
he has the universal category of peculiarity as his universal de- 
termination. This not only says everything that is “ sayable ” about 
the unique, but also what he is in general — minus the fantasy of 
Jacques le bonhomme about him. 

“O the depth of the riches both of the wisdom and knowledge of the unique! How 
incomprehensible are his thoughts, and his ways past finding out!” 3 

“Lo, these are parts of his ways: but how little a portion is heard of him!” 
(Job 26: 14.) 



2. The Phenomenology of the Egoist in Agreement 
with Himself, or the Theory of Justification 

As we have already seen in “The Economy of the Old Testament” 
and afterwards, Saint Sancho’s true egoist in agreement with himself 
must on no account be confused with the trivial, everyday egoist, the 
“egoist in the ordinary sense”. Rather he has as his presupposition both 
this latter (the one in thrall to the world of things, child, Negro, 
ancient, etc.) and the selfless egoist (the one in thrall to the world of 
thoughts, youth, Mongol, modern, etc.). It is, however, part of the 
nature of the secrets of the unique that this antithesis and the 
negative unity which follows from it — the “ egoist in agreement with 
himself ’ — can be examined only now, in the New Testament. 

Since Saint Max wishes to present the “true egoist” as something 
quite new, as the goal of all preceding history, he must, on the one 
hand, prove to the selfless, the advocates of devoument, that they are 
egoists against their will, and he must prove to the egoists in the 
ordinary sense that they are selfless, that they are not true, holy, 
egoists. — Let us begin with the first, with the selfless. 

We have already seen countless times that in the world of Jacques 
le bonhomme everyone is obsessed by the holy. “Nevertheless it 
makes a difference” whether “one is educated or uneducated”. The 
educated, who are occupied with pure thought, confront us here as 
“obsessed” by the holy par excellence. They are the “selfless” in their 
practical guise. 



3 Romans 11:33 (paraphrased). — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



243 



“Who then is selfless? Completely” (!) “most” (!!) "likely” (!!!) “he who stakes 
everything else on one thing, one aim, one purpose, one passion.... He is ruled 
by a passion to which he sacrifices all others. And are these selfless not selfish, 
perhaps? Since they possess only a single ruling passion, they are concerned only with a 
single satisfaction, but the more ardently on that account. All their deeds and actions 
are egoistic, but it is a one-sided, concealed, narrow egoism ; it is — obsession” (p. 99). 



Hence, according to Saint Sancho, they possess only a single ruling 
passion; ought they to be concerned also with the passions which not 
they, but others possess, in order to rise to an all-round, unconcealed, 
unrestricted egoism, in order to correspond to this alien scale of 
“holy” egoism? 

In this passage are incidentally introduced also the “miser” and 
the “ pleasure-seeker ” (probably because Stirner thinks that he seeks 
“ pleasure ” as such, holy pleasure, and not all sorts of real pleasures), 
as also “Robespierre, for example, Saint-Just, and so on” (p.100) as 
examples of “selfless, obsessed egoists”. “From a certain moral point 
of view it is argued” (i.e., our holy “egoist in agreement with 
himself” argues from his own point of view in extreme disagreement 
with himself) “approximately as follows”: 



“But if I sacrifice other passions to one passion, I still do not thereby sacrifice myself 
to this passion, and I do not sacrifice anything thanks to which I am truly I myself” 
(p. 386). 

Saint Max is compelled by these two propositions “in disagreement 
with each other” to make the “paltry” distinction that one may well 
sacrifice six “for example”, or seven, “and so on”, passions to a 
single other passion without ceasing to be “truly I myself”, but by no 
means ten passions, or a still greater number. Of course, neither 
Robespierre nor Saint-Just was “ truly I myself”, just as neither 
was truly “man”, but they were truly Robespierre and Saint-Just, 
those unique, incomparable individuals. 

The trick of proving to the “selfless” that they are egoists is an old 
dodge, sufficiently exploited already by Helvetius and Bentham. 
Saint Sancho’s “own” trick consists in the transformation of “egoists 
in the ordinary sense”, the bourgeois, into non-egoists. Helvetius 
and Bentham, at any rate, prove to the bourgeois that by their 
narrow-mindedness they in practice harm themselves, but Saint Max’s 
“own” trick consists in proving that they do not correspond to the 
“ideal”, the “concept”, the “essence”, the “calling”, etc., of the egoist 
and that their attitude towards themselves is not that of absolute 
negation. Here again he has in mind only his German petty 
bourgeois. Let us point out, incidentally, that whereas on page 99 
our saint makes the “miser” figure as a “selfless egoist”, on page 78, 




244 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



on the other hand, the “avaricious one” is included among “egoists 
in the ordinary sense”, among the “impure, unholy”. 

This second class of the hitherto existing egoists is defined on 
page 99 as follows: 

“These people” (the bourgeois) “are therefore not selfless, not inspired, not ideal, 
not consistent, not enthusiasts; they are egoists in the ordinary sense, selfish people, 
thinking of their own advantage, sober, calculating, etc.” 

Since “the book” is not all of a piece, we have already had 
occasion, in connection with “whimsy” and “political liberalism”, to 
see how Stirner achieves the trick of transforming the bourgeois into 
non-egoists, chiefly owing to his great ignorance of real people and 
conditions. This same ignorance serves him here as a lever. 

“This” (i.e., Stirner’s fantasy about unselfishness) “is repugnant to the stubborn 
brain of worldly man but for thousands of years he at least succumbed so far that he 
had to bend his obstinate neck and worship higher powers” (p. 104). The egoists in the 
ordinary sense “behave half clerically and half in a worldly way, they serve both God 
and Mammon” (p. 105). 

We learn on page 78: “The Mammon of heaven and the God of 
the world both demand precisely the same degree of self-denial" , 
hence it is impossible to understand how self-denial for Mammon 
and self-denial for God can be opposed to each other as “worldly” 
and “clerical”. 

On page 105-106, Jacques le bonhomme asks himself: 

“How does it happen, then, that the egoism of those who assert their personal 
interest nevertheless constantly succumbs to a clerical or school-masterly, i.e., an ideal, 
interest?” 

(Here, one must in passing “point out” that in this passage the 
bourgeois are depicted as representatives of personal interests.) It 
happens because: 

“Their personality seems to them too small, too unimportant — as indeed it is— to 
lay claim to everything and be able to assert itself fully. A sure sign of this is the 
fact that they divide themselves into two persons, an eternal and a temporal; on 
Sundays they take care of the eternal aspect and on weekdays the temporal. They have 
the priest within them, therefore they cannot get rid of him.” 

Sancho experiences some scruples here; he asks anxiously whether 
“the same thing will happen” to peculiarity, the egoism in the 
extraordinary sense. 

We shall see that it is not without grounds that this anxious 
question is asked. Before the cock has crowed twice, Saint Jacob 
(Jacques le bonhomme) will have “ denied ” himself thrice. 3 



Cf. Mark 14 : 30. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



245 



He discovers to his great displeasure that the two sides prominent- 
ly appearing in history, the private interest of individuals and the 
so-called general interest, always accompany each other. As usual, he 
discovers this in a false form, in its holy form, from the aspect of 
ideal interests, of the holy, of illusion. He asks: how is it that the 
ordinary egoists, the representatives of personal interests, are at the 
same time dominated by general interests, by school-masters, by the 
hierarchy? His reply to the question is to the effect that the 
bourgeois, etc., “seem to themselves too small”, and he discovers a 
“sure sign” of this in the fact that they behave in a religious way, i.e., 
that their personality is divided into a temporal and an eternal one, 
that is to say, he explains their religious behaviour by their religious 
behaviour, after first transforming the struggle between general and 
personal interests into a mirror image of the struggle, into a simple 
reflection inside religious fantasy. 

How the matter stands as regards the domination of the ideal, see 
above in the section on hierarchy. 

If Sancho’ s question is translated from its highflown form into 
everyday language, then “it now reads”: 

How is it that personal interests always develop, against the will of 
individuals, into class interests, into common interests which acquire 
independent existence in relation to the individual persons, and in 
their independence assume the form of general interests? How is it 
that as such they come into contradiction with the actual individuals 
and in this contradiction, by which they are defined as general 
interests, they can be conceived by consciousness as ideal and even as 
religious, holy interests? How is it that in this process of private 
interests acquiring independent existence as class interests the 
personal behaviour of the individual is bound to be objectified 
[sich versachlichen], estranged [sich entfremden ], and at the same time 
exists as a power independent of him and without him, created 
by intercourse, and is transformed into social relations, into a series 
of powers which determine and subordinate the individual, and 
which, therefore, appear in the imagination as “holy” powers? 
Had Sancho understood the fact that within the framework of 
definite modes of production, which, of course, are not dependent 
on the will, alien [fremde] practical forces, which are independent 
not only of isolated individuals but even of all of them together, 
always come to stand above people — then he could be fairly 
indifferent as to whether this fact is presented in a religious 
form or distorted in the fancy of the egoist, above whom everything 
is placed in imagination, in such a way that he places nothing above 
himself. Sancho would then have descended from the realm of 




246 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



speculation into the realm of reality, from what people fancy to what 
they actually are, from what they imagine to how they act and are 
bound to act in definite circumstances. What seems to him a product 
of thought, he would have understood to be a product of life. He 
would not then have arrived at the absurdity worthy of him — of 
explaining the division between personal and general interests by 
saying that people imagine this division also in a religious way and 
seem to themselves to be such and such, which is, however, only 
another word for “imagining”. 

Incidentally, even in the banal, petty-bourgeois German form in 
which Sancho perceives the contradiction of personal and general 
interests, he should have realised that individuals have always started 
out from themselves, and could not do otherwise, and that therefore 
the two aspects he noted are aspects of the personal development of 
individuals; both are equally engendered by the empirical conditions 
under which the individuals live, both are only expressions of one and 
the same personal development of people and are therefore only in 
seeming contradiction to each other. As regards the position — deter- 
mined by the special circumstances of development and by division 
of labour — which falls to the lot of the given individual, whether he 
represents to a greater extent one or the other aspect of the 
antithesis, whether he appears more as an egoist or more as 
selfless — that was a quite subordinate question, which could only 
acquire any interest at all if it were raised in definite epochs of 
history in relation to definite individuals. Otherwise this question 
could only lead to morally false, charlatan phrases. But as a 
dogmatist Sancho falls into error here and finds no other way out 
than by declaring that the Sancho Panzas and Don Quixotes are born 
such, and that then the Don Quixotes stuff all kinds of nonsense into 
the heads of the Sanchos; as a dogmatist he seizes on one aspect, 
conceived in a school-masterly manner, declares it to be characteris- 
tic of individuals as such, and expresses his aversion to the other 
aspect. Therefore, too, as a dogmatist, the other aspect appears to 
him partly as a mere state of mind , devoument, partly as a mere 
“ principle ”, and not as a relation necessarily arising from the 
preceding natural mode of life of individuals. One has, therefore, 
only to “get this principle out of one’s head”, although, according to 
Sancho’s ideology, it creates all kinds of empirical things. Thus, for 
example, on page 180 “social life, all sociability, all fraternity and all 
that ... was created by the life principle 3 or social principle”. It is 
better the other way round: life created the principle. 



Stirner has “love principle”. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



247 



Communism is quite incomprehensible to our saint because the 
communists do not oppose egoism to selflessness or selflessness 
to egoism, nor do they express this contradiction theoretically 
either in its sentimental or in its highflown ideological form; they 
rather demonstrate its material source, with which it disappears of 
itself. The communists do not preach morality at all, as Stirner does 
so extensively. They do not put to people the moral demand: love 
one another, do not be egoists, etc.; on the contrary, they are very 
well aware that egoism, just as much as selflessness, is in definite 
circumstances a necessary form of the self-assertion of individuals. 
Hence, the communists by no means want, as Saint Max believes, 
and as his loyal Dottore Graziano (Arnold Rugej repeats after him (for 
which Saint Max calls him “an unusually cunning and politic 
mind”, Wigand, p. 192), to do away with the “private individual” for 
the sake of the “general”, selfless man. That is a figment of the 
imagination concerning which both of them could already have 
found the necessary explanation in the Deutsch-Franzosische 
Jahrbiicher. Communist theoreticians, the only communists who have 
time to devote to the study of history, are distinguished precisely by 
the fact that they alone have discovered that throughout history the 
“general interest” is created by individuals who are defined as “pri- 
vate persons”. They know that this contradiction is only a seeming 
one because one side of it, what is called the “general interest”, is 
constantly being produced by the other side, private interest, and in 
relation to the latter it is by no means an independent force with an 
independent history — so that this contradiction is in practice 
constantly destroyed and reproduced. Hence it is not a question 
of the Hegelian “negative unity” of two sides of a contradiction, 
but of the materially determined destruction of the preceding 
materially determined mode of life of individuals, with the disap- 
pearance of which this contradiction together with its unity also 
disappears. 

Thus we see how the “egoist in agreement with himself” as op- 
posed to the “egoist in the ordinary sense” and the “selfless egoist”, 
is based from the outset on an illusion about both of these and about 
the real relations of real people. The representative of personal 
interests is merely an “egoist in the ordinary sense” because of his 
necessary contradiction to communal interests which, within the 
existing mode of production and intercourse, are given an 
independent existence as general interests and are conceived and 
vindicated in the form of ideal interests. The representative of the 
interests of the community is merely “selfless” because of his 
opposition to personal interests, fixed as private interests, and 



10—2086 




248 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



because the interests of the community are defined as general and 
ideal interests. 

Both the “selfless egoist” and the “egoist in the ordinary sense” 
coincide, in the final analysis, in self-denial. 

Page 78: “Thus, self-denial is common to both the holy and unholy, the pure and 
impure: the impure denies all better feelings, all shame, even natural timidity, and 
follows only the desire which rules him. The pure renounces his natural relation to the 
world.... Impelled by the thirst for money, the avaricious person denies all promptings 
of conscience, all sense of honour, all soft-heartedness and pity; he is blind to all 
consideration, his desire drives him on. The holy person acts similarly: he makes 
himself a laughing-stock in the eyes of the world, he is ‘hard-hearted’ and ‘severely 
just’, for he is carried away by his longing.’’ 

The “avaricious man”, shown here as an impure, unholy egoist, 
hence as an egoist in the ordinary sense, is nothing but a figure on 
whom moral readers for children and novels dilate, but that actually 
occurs only as an exception, and is by no means the representative of 
the avaricious bourgeois. The latter, on the contrary, have no need 
to deny the “promptings of conscience”, “the sense of honour”, 
etc., or to restrict themselves to the one passion of avarice alone. On 
the contrary, their avarice engenders a series of other passions — 
political, etc. — the satisfaction of which the bourgeois on no account 
sacrifice. Without going more deeply into this matter, let us at once 
turn to Stirner’s “self-deniai”. 

For the self which denies itself, Saint Max here substitutes a 
different self which exists only in Saint Max’s imagination. He makes 
the “impure” sacrifice general qualities such as “better feelings”, 
“shame”, “timidity”, “sense of honour”, etc., and does not at all ask 
whether the impure actually possesses these properties. As if the 
“impure” is necessarily bound to possess all these qualities! But even 
if the “impure” did possess all of them, the sacrifice of these qualities 
would still be no self-denial, but only confirm the fact — which has to 
be justified even in morality “in agreement with itself” — that for the 
sake of one passion several others are sacrificed. And, finally, 
according to this theory, everything that Sancho does or does not do 
is “self-denial”. He may or may not act in a particular manner [...].* 

* [There is a gap here. An extant page, which has been crossed out and greatly 
damaged, contains the following:] he is an egoist, his own self-denial. If he pursues an 
interest he denies the indifference to this interest, if he does something he denies 
idleness. Nothing is easier [...] for Sancho than to prove to the " egoist in the ordinary 
sense ” — his stumbling-block — that he always denies himself, because he always denies 
the opposite of what he does, and never denies his real interest. 

In accordance with his theory of self-denial Sancho can exclaim on page 80: “Is 
perhaps unselfishness unreal and non-existent? On the contrary, nothing is more 
common!” 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



249 



Although* on* page 420 Saint Max now says: 

“Over the portals of our [epoch] are written not the words ... ‘know thyself, [but] 
‘turn yourself to account’” [Verwerte Dich] 

(here our school-master again transforms the actual turning to 
account which he finds in existence into a moral precept about 
turning to account), nevertheless [for the] “egoist in the ordinary 
[sense’ instead of for] the former “selfless egoist”, “the [Apollonic” 
maxim 8,1 should read: 

“Only know yourselves], only know what [you] are in reality and give up vour 
foolish endeavour to be something different from what you are!” “For”: “This 
leads to the phenomenon of deceived egoism, in which I satisfy not myself, but] 
only one [of my desires, e.] g., the [thirst for] happiness. [ — All] your deeds and 
[actions are secret], concealed ... [egoism,] unconscious egoism, [but] for that very reason 
not egoism, but slavery, service, self-denial. You are egoists and at the same time not 
egoists, inasmuch as you deny egoism ” (p. 217). 

“No sheep, no dog, endeavours to become a real” egoist (p. 443); 
“no animal” calls to the others: “Only know yourselves, only know 

We are really very happy [about the “unselfishness”] of the consciousness of the 
German petty [bourgeois].... 

He immediately gives a good example of this unselfishness by [adducing] 
Orphanage-F[rancke, ‘ O’Connell, Saint Boniface, Robespierre, Theodor Korner...]. 

O’Connell [...], every [child] in Britain knows this. Only in Germany, and 
particularly in Berlin, is it still possible to believe that O’Connell is “unselfish”. 
O’Connell, who “tirelessly works” to place his illegitimate children and to enlarge his 
fortune, who has not for love exchanged his lucrative legal practice (£10,000 per 
annum) for the even more lucrative job of an agitator (£20,000-30,000 per annum) 
(especially lucrative in Ireland, where he has no competition): O’Connell who, acting 
as middleman,' 1 “hard-heartedly” exploits the Irish peasants making them live with 
their pigs while he. King Dan, holds court in princely style in his paiace in Merrion 
Square and at the same time laments continually over the misery of these peasants, 
“for he is carried away bv his longing”; O’Connell, who always pushes the movement 
just as far as is necessary to secure his national tribute 0 and his position as chief, and 
who every year after collecting the tribute gives up all agitation in order to pamper 
himself on his estate at Derrynane. Because of his legal charlatanism carried on over 
many years and his exceedingly brazen exploitation of every movement in which he 
participated, O’Connell is regarded with contempt even by the English bourgeoisie, 
despite his usefulness. 

It is moreover obvious that Saint Max, the discoverer of true egoism, is strongly 
interested in proving that unselfishness has hitherto ruled the world. Therefore he 
puts forward the great proposition ( Wigand , p. 165) that the world was “not egoistic 
for millennia”. At most he admits that from time to time the “egoist” appeared as 
Stirner's forerunner and “ruined nations”. 

* [Marx made the following note at the beginning of this page:] III. Consciousness. 



a The word is in English in the manuscript. — Ed. 

These two words are in English in the manuscript. — Ed. 




250 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



what you are in reality”. — “It is your nature to be” egoistical, “you 
are” egoistical “natures, i. e.”, egoists. “But precisely because you* are 
that already, you have no need to become so” (ibid.). To what you 
are belongs also your consciousness, and since you are egoists you 
possess also the consciousness corresponding to your egoism, and 
therefore there is no reason at all for paying the slightest heed 
to Sdrner’s moral preaching to look into your heart and do penance. 

Here again Stirner exploits the old philosophical device to which 
we shall return later. The philosopher does not say directly: You are 
not people. [He says:] You have always been people, but you were 
not conscious of what you were, and for that very reason you were 
not in reality True People. Therefore your appearance was not 
appropriate to your essence. You were people and you were not 
people. 

In a roundabout way the philosopher here admits that a definite 
consciousness is appropriate to definite people and definite cir- 
cumstances. But at the same time he imagines that his moral demand 
to people — the demand that they should change their conscious- 
ness — will bring about this altered consciousness, and in people who 
have changed owing to changed empirical conditions and who, of 
course, now also possess a different consciousness, he sees nothing 
but a changed [consciousness]. — It is just the same [with the 
consciousness for which you are secretly] longing; [in regard to this] 
you are [secret, unconscious] egoists — i.e., you are really egoists, 
insofar as you are unconscious, but you are non-egoists, insofar as you 
are conscious. Or: at the root of your present [consciousness lies] a 
definite being, which is not the [being] which I demand; your 
consciousness is the consciousness of the egoist such as he should not 
[be], and therefore it shows that you yourselves are egoists such as 
egoists should not be — or it shows that you should be different from 
what you really are. This entire separation of consciousness from the 
individuals who are its basis and from their actual conditions, this 
notion that the egoist of present-day bourgeois society does not 
possess the consciousness corresponding to his egoism, is merely an 
old philosophical fad that Jacques le bonhomme here credulously 
accepts and copies.* Let us deal with Stirner’s “touching example” of 
the avaricious person. He wants to persuade this avaricious person, 

* [The following passage is crossed out in the manuscript:] This fad becomes most 
ridiculous in history, where the consciousness of a later epoch regarding an earlier 
epoch naturally differs from the consciousness the latter has of itself, e.g., the Greeks 
saw themselves through the eyes of the Greeks and not as we see them now; to blame 
them for not seeing themselves with our eyes — that is, “not being conscious of 
themselves as they really were” — amounts to blaming them for being Greeks. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



251 



who is not an “avaricious person” in general, but the avaricious 
“Tom or Dick”; a quite individually defined, “unique” avaricious 
person, whose avarice is not the category of “avarice” (an abstraction 
of Saint Max’s from his all-embracing, complex, “unique” manifesta- 
tion of life) and “does not depend on the heading under which other 
people” (for example, Saint Max) “classify it” — he wants to persuade 
this avaricious person by moral exhortations that he “is satisfying not 
himself but one of his desires”. But “you are you only for a 
[moment], only as a momentary being are you real. What [is 
separated from you,] from the momentary being” is something 
absolutely higher, [e.g., money. But whether] “for you” money is 
“rather” [a higher pleasure], whether it is for you [something 
“absolutely higher” or] not [...] a perhaps [“deny”] myself [? — He] 
finds that I am possessed [by avarice] day and night, [but] 
this is so only in his reflection. It is he who makes “day and night” 
out of the many moments in which I am always the momentary 
being, always myself, always real, just as he alone embraces in one 
moral judgment the different moments of my manifestation of life 
and asserts that they are the satisfaction of avarice. When Saint Max 
announces that I am satisfying only one of my desires, and not 
myself, he puts me as a complete and whole being in opposition to 
me myself. “And in what does this complete and whole being consist? 
It is certainly not your momentary being, not what you are at the 
present moment” — hence, according to Saint Max himself, it consists 
in the holy “being” ( Wigand , p. 171). When “Stirner” says that I 
must change my consciousness, then I know for my part that my 
momentary consciousness also belongs to my momentary being, and 
Saint Max, by disputing that I have this consciousness, attacks as a 
covert moralist my whole mode of life.* And then — “do you exist 
only when you think about yourself, do you exist only owing to 
self-consciousness?” ( Wigand , pp. 157-158.) How can I be anything 
but an egoist? How can Stirner, for example, be anything but an 
egoist — whether he denies egoism or not? “You are egoists and you 
are not egoists, inasmuch as you deny egoism,” — that is what you 
preach. 

Innocent, “deceived”, “unavowed” school-master! Things are just 
the reverse. We egoists in the ordinary sense, we bourgeois, know 
quite well: Charite bien ordonnee commence par soi-meme, h and we have 



* [Here Marx repeats the remark:] III (Consciousness). 



a The following passage is damaged. — -Ed. 
Charity begins at home. — Ed. 




252 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



long had the motto: love thy neighbour as thyself, a interpreted in the 
sense that each is his own neighbour. But we deny that we are 
heartless egoists, exploiters, ordinary egoists, whose hearts cannot be 
lifted up to the exalted feeling of making the interests of their 
fellow-men their own — which, between ourselves, only means that 
we declare our interests to be the interests of our fellow-men. [You] 
deny the “ordinary” [egoism of the] unique egoist [only because] you 
[“deny]” your [“natural] relations to the [world]”. Hence you do not 
understand why we bring practical egoism to perfection precisely by 
denying the phraseology of egoism — we who are concerned with 
realising real egoistical interests, not the holy interest of egoism. 
Incidentally, it could be foreseen — and here the bourgeois coollv 
turns his back on Saint Max — that you German school-masters, if 
you once took up the defence of egoism, would proclaim 
not real, “mundane and plainly evident” egoism (“the book”, 
p. 455), that is to say, “not what is called” egoism, but egoism in 
the extraordinary, school-masterlv sense, philosophical or vaga- 
bond egoism. 

The egoist in the extraordinary sense, therefore, is “only now 
discovered”. “Let us examine this new discovery more closelv” 

(p. ID- 

From what has been just said it is already clear that the egoists who 
existed till now have only to change their consciousness in order to 
become egoists in the extraordinary sense, hence that the egoist in 
agreement with himself is distinguished from the previous type only 
by consciousness; i.e., only as a learned man, as a philosopher. It 
further follows from the whole historical outlook of Saint Max that, 
because the former egoists were ruled only by the “holy”, the true 
egoist has to fight only against the “holy”. “Unique” history has 
shown us how Saint Max transformed historical conditions into 
ideas, and then the egoist into a sinner against these ideas; how every 
egoistic manifestation was transformed into a sin [against these] 
ideas, [the power of] the privileged into a sin [against the idea] of 
equality, into the sin of despotism. [Concerning the] idea of freedom 
[of competition,] therefore, it could be [said in “the book”] that 
[private property is regarded] by him [(p. 155) as“]the personal” [...] 
great, [...] [selfless] egoists [...] essential and invincible [...] only to be 
fought by transforming them into something holy and then asserting 
that he abolishes the holiness in them, i.e., his holy idea about them, 
[i.e.,] abolishes them only insofar as they exist in him as a holy one. b 



a Galatians 5: 14. — Ed. 

This paragraph is damaged. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



253 



Page 50*: “How you are at each moment you are as your creation, and it is precisely 
in this creation that you do not want to lose yourself, the creator. You yourself are a 
higher being than yourself, i.e., vou are not merely a creation, but likewise a creator; 
and it is this that you fail to recognise as an involuntary egoist, and for that reason the 
higher being is something foreign to you.” 

In a somewhat different variation, this same wisdom is stated on 
page 239 of “the book”: 

“The species is nothing" (later it becomes all sorts of things, see “Self-Enjoyment”), 
“and when the individual rises above the limitations of his individuality, it is precisely 
here that he himself appears as an individual; he exists only by raising himself, he 
exists only by not remaining what he is. otherwise he would be done for, dead." 

In relation to these propositions, to his “creation”, Stirner at once 
begins to behave as “creator”, “by no means losing himself in them”: 

“You are vou only for a moment, onlv as a momentary being are you real.... At each 
moment I am wholly what i am ... what is separated from you. the momentary being”, 
is “something absolutely higher” ... ( Wigand , p. 170); and, on page 171 (ibid.), “your 
being” is defined as "vour momentary being”. 

Whereas in “the book” Saint Max says that besides a momentary 
being he has also another, higher being, in the “Apologetical 
Commentary” “the momentary being” [of his] individual is equated 
with his “complete [and whole] being”, and every [being] as a “mo- 
mentary being” is transformed [into an] “absolutely higher being”. 
In “the book” therefore he is, at every moment, a higher being than 
what he is at that moment, whereas in the Commentary”, 
everything that he is not directly at a given moment is defined as an 
“absolutelv higher being”, a holv being. — And in contrast to all this 
division we read on page 200 of “the book”: 

"I know nothing about a division into an ‘imperfect’ and a ‘perfect’ ego.” 

“The egoist in agreement with himself” needs no longer sacrifice 
himself to something higher, since in his own eyes he is himself this 
higher being, and he transfers this schism between a “higher” and a 
“lower being” into himself. So, in fact (Saint Sancho contra 
Feuerbach, “the book”, p. 243), “the highest being has undergone 
nothing but a metamorphosis”. The true egoism of Saint Max 
consists in an egoistic attitude to real egoism, to himself, as he is “at 
each moment”. This egoistic attitude to egoism is selflessness. From 
this aspect Saint Max as a creation is an egoist in the ordinary sense; 
as creator he is a selfless egoist. We shall also become acquainted with 
the opposite aspect, for both these aspects prove to be genuine 
determinations of reflection since they undergo absolute dialectics in 
which each of them is the opposite of itself. 

* [Marx wrote at the top of this page:] II (Creator and Creation). 




254 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



Before entering more deeply into this mystery in its esoteric form, 
one has to observe some of [its arduous] life battles. 

[On pages 82, 83 Stirner achieves the feat of] bringing the most 
general quality, [the egoist,] [into agreement] with himself as creator, 
[from the standpoint of the world] of spirit: 

[“Christianity aimed] at [delivering us from natural determination (determination 
through nature), from desires as a driving force, it consequently wished that man 
should not allow himself to be] determined [by his desires. This does not mean that] he 
[should have ] no [desires], but that [desires] should not possess [him,] that [they] 
should not become fixed, unconquerable, ineradicable. Could we not apply 
these machinations of Christianity against desires to its own precept, that we 
should be determined by the spirit...? ... Then this would signify the dissolution 
of spirit, the dissolution of all thoughts. As one ought to have said there ... so one 
would have to say now: We should indeed possess spirit, but spirit should not 
possess us.” 

“And they that are Christ’s have crucified the flesh with the 
affections and lusts” (Galatians 5:24) — thus, according to Stirner, 
they deal with their crucified affections and lusts like true owners. 
He accepts Christianity in instalments, but will not let matters rest at 
the crucified flesh alone, wanting to crucify his spirit as well, 
consequently, the “whole fellow”. 

The only reason why Christianity wanted to free us from the 
domination of the flesh and “desires as a driving force” was because 
it regarded our flesh, our desires as something foreign to us; it 
wanted to free us from determination by nature only because it 
regarded our own nature as not belonging to us. For if I myself am 
not nature, if my natural desires, my whole natural character, do not 
belong to myself — and this is the doctrine of Christianity — then all 
determination by nature — whether due to my own natural character 
or to what is known as external nature — seems to me a determination 
by something foreign, a fetter, compulsion used against me, 
heteronomy as opposed to autonomy of the spirit. Stirner accepts this 
Christian dialectic without examining it and then applies it to our 
spirit. Incidentally, Christianity has indeed never succeeded in 
freeing us from the domination of desires, even in that juste milieu 
sense foisted on it by Saint Max; it does not go beyond mere moral 
injunctions, which remain ineffective in real life. Stirner takes moral 
injunctions for real deeds and supplements them with the further 
categorical imperative: “We should indeed possess spirit, but spirit 
should not possess us” — and consequently all his egoism in 
agreement with itself is reduced “on closer examination”, as Hegel 
would say, to a moral philosophy that is as delightful as it is edifying 
and contemplative. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



255 



Whether a desire becomes fixed or not, i.e., whether it obtains 
exclusive [power over us] — which, however, does [not] exclude 
[further progress] — depends on whether material circumstances, 
“bad” mundane conditions permit the normal satisfaction of this 
desire and, on the other hand, the development of a totality of 
desires. This latter depends, in turn, on whether we live in 
circumstances that allow all-round activity and thereby the full 
development of all our potentialities. On the actual conditions, and 
the possibility of development they give each individual, depends 
also whether thoughts become fixed or not — just as, for example, the 
fixed ideas of the German philosophers, these “victims of society”, 
qui nous font pitie , a are inseparable from the German conditions. 
Incidentally, in Stirner the domination of desires is a mere phrase, 
the imprint of the absolute saint. Thus, still keeping to the “touching 
example” of the avaricious person, we read: 

“An avaricious person is not an owner, but a servant, and he can do nothing for his 
own sake without at the same time doing it for the sake of his master” (p. 400). 

No one can do anything without at the same time doing it for the 
sake of one or other of his needs and for the sake of the organ of this 
need — for Stirner this means that this need and its organ are made 
into a master over him, just as earlier he made the means for 
satisfying a need (cf. the sections on political liberalism and 
communism) into a master over him. Stirner cannot eat without at 
the same time eating for the sake of his stomach. If the worldly 
conditions prevent him from satisfying his stomach, then his stomach 
becomes a master over him, the desire to eat becomes a fixed desire, 
and the thought of eating becomes a fixed idea — which at the same 
time gives him an example of the influence of world conditions in 
fixing his desires and ideas. Sancho’s “revolt” against the fixation of 
desires and thoughts is thus reduced to an impotent moral 
injunction about self-control and provides new evidence that he 
merely gives an ideologically high-sounding expression to the most 
trivial sentiments of the petty bourgeois.* 



* [The following passage is crossed out in the manuscript:] Since they attack the 
material basis on which the hitherto inevitable fixedness of desires and ideas 
depended, the communists are the only people through whose historical activity the 
liquefaction of the fixed desires and ideas is in fact brought about and ceases to be an 
impotent moral injunction, as it was up to now with all moralists “down to” Stirner. 
communist organisation has a twofold effect on the desires produced in the 



For whom we feel pity. — Ed. 




256 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



Thus, in this first example he fights, on the one hand, against his 
carnal desires, and on the other against his spiritual thoughts — on 
the one hand against his flesh, on the other against his spirit — when 
they, his creations, want to become independent of him, their 
creator. How our saint conducts this struggle, how he behaves as 
creator towards his creation, we shall now see. 

In the Christian “in the ordinary sense”, in the chretien “ simple ”, to 
use Fourier’s expression, 

“ spirit has undivided power and pays no heed to any persuasion of the ‘flesh’. 
However, only through the ‘flesh’ can I break the tyranny of the spirit; for only when 
man perceives also his flesh does he perceive himself wholly, and only when he 
perceives himself wholly does he become perceptive or rational.... But as soon as the 
flesh speaks and — as cannot be otherwise — in a passionate tone ... then he” (the chretien 
simple ) “believes he hears devil voices, voices against the spirit ... and with good reason 
comes out passionately against them. He would not be a Christian if he were prepared 
to tolerate them” (p. 83). 

Hence, when his spirit wishes to acquire independence in relation 
to him, Saint Max calls his flesh to his aid, and when his flesh 



individual by present-day relations; some of these desires — namely desires which exist 
under all relations, and only change their form and direction under different social 
relations — are merely altered by the communist social system, for they are 
given the opportunity to develop normally: but others — namelv those originating 
solely in a particular society, under particular conditions of [production] and 
intercourse — are totally deprived of their conditions of existence. Which [of the 
desires] will be merely changed and [which eliminated] in a communist [society] can 
[only be determined in a practical] way, by [changing the real], actual [“desires”, and 
not by making comparisons with earlier historical conditions]. 

The two expressions: [“fixed” and “desires”], which we [have just used in order to 
be able] to disprove [this “unique” fact of] Stirner’s, [are of course] quite 
inappropriate. The fact that one desire of an individual in modern society can be 
satisfied at the expense of all others, and that this “ought not to be” and that this is 
more or less the case with all individuals in the world today and that thereby the free 
development of the individual as a whole is made impossible — this fact is expressed by 
Stirner thus: “the desires become fixed” in the egoist in disagreement with himself, 
for Stirner knows nothing of the empirical connection of this fact with the world as it is 
today. A desire is already by its mere existence something “fixed”, and it can occur 
only to Saint Max and his like not to allow his sex instinct, for instance, to become 
“fixed”; it is that already and will cease to be fixed only as the result of castration or 
impotence. Each need, which forms the basis of a “desire”, is likewise something 
“fixed”, and try as he may Saint Max cannot abolish this “fixedness” and for example 
contrive to free himself from the necessity of eating within “fixed” periods of 
time. The communists have no intention of abolishing the fixedness of their desires 
and needs, an intention which Stirner, immersed in his world of fancy, ascribes to 
them and to all other men; they only strive to achieve an organisation of production 
and intercourse which will make possible the normal satisfaction of all needs, i.e., a 
satisfaction which is limited only by the needs themselves. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



257 



becomes rebellious, he remembers that he is also spirit. What the 
Christian does in one direction, Saint Max does in both. He is the 
chretien “compose”, he once again reveals himself as the perfect 
Christian. 

Here, in this example, Saint Max, as spirit, does not appear as the 
creator of his flesh and vice versa; he finds his flesh and his spirit 
both present, and only when one side rebels does he remember that 
he has also the other, and asserts this other side, as his true ego, 
against it. Here, therefore, Saint Max is creator only insofar as he is 
one who is “ also-otherwise-determined ”, insofar as he possesses yet 
another quality besides that which it just suits him to subsume under 
the category of “creation”. His entire creative activity consists here in 
the good resolution to perceive himself, and indeed to perceive 
himself entirely or be rational ,* to perceive himself as a “complete, 
entire being”, as a being different from “his momentary being”, and 
even in direct contradiction to the kind of being he is “momen- 
tarily”. 

[Let us now turn to one of the “arduous] life battles” [of our saint]: 

[Pages 80, 81 : “Mv zeal] need not [be less than the] most fanatical, [but at the same] 
time [I remain] towards [it cold as ice, sceptical], and its [most irreconcilable enemy;] I 
remain [its judge, for I am its] owner.” 

[If one desires to] give [meaning] to what Saint [Sancho] says about 
himself, then it amounts ro this: his creative activity here is limited to 
the fact that in his zeal he preserves the consciousness of his zeal, that 
he reflects on it, that he adopts the attitude of the reflecting ego to 
himself as the real ego. It is to consciousness that he arbitrarily gives 
the name “creator”. He is “creator” only insofar as he possesses 
consciousness. 

“Thereupon, you forget yourself in sweet self-oblivion.... But do you exist only 
when you think of yourself, and do you vanish when you forget yourself? Who does not 
forget himself at every instant, who does not lose sight of himself a thousand times an 
hour?” ( Wigand , pp. 157, 158). 

This, of course, Sancho cannot forgive his “self-oblivion” and 
therefore “remains at the same time its most irreconcilable 
enemy”. 

Saint Max, the creation, burns with immense zeal at the very time 
when Saint Max, the creator, has already risen above his zeal by 
means of reflection; or the real Saint Max burns with zeal, and the 
reflecting Saint Max imagines that he has risen above this zeal. This 

* Here, therefore. Saint Max completely justifies Feuerbach’s “touching example” 
of the hetaera and the beloved. In the first case, a man “perceives” only his flesh or only 
her flesh, in the second he perceives himself entirely or her entirely. See Wigand, pp. 170, 
171. 




258 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



rising in reflection above what he actually is, is now amusingly and 
adventurously described in the phrases of a novel to the effect that 
he allows his zeal to remain in existence, i.e., he does not draw any 
serious consequences from his hostility to it, but his attitude towards 
it is “cold as ice”, “sceptical” and that of its “most irreconcilable 
enemy”. 

Insofar as Saint Max burns with zeal, i.e., insofar as zeal is his true 
quality, his attitude to it is not that of creator; and insofar as his 
attitude is that of creator, he does not really burn with zeal, zeal is 
foreign to him, not a quality of him. So long as he burns with zeal he 
is not the owner of zeal, and as soon as he becomes the owner, he 
ceases to burn with zeal. As an aggregate complex, he is at every 
instant, in the capacity of creator and owner, the sum total of all his 
qualities, with the exception of the one quality which he puts in 
opposition to himself, the embodiment of all the others, as creation 
and property — so that precisely that quality which he stresses as his 
own is always foreign to him. 

No matter how extravagant Saint Max’s true story of his heroic 
exploits within himself, in his own consciousness, may sound, it is 
nevertheless an acknowledged fact that there do exist reflect- 
ing individuals, who imagine that in and through reflection they 
have risen above everything,* because in actual fact they never go 
beyond reflection. 

This trick — of declaring oneself against some definite quality as 
being someone who is also-otherwise-determined, namely, in the 
present example as being the possessor of reflection directed towards the 
opposite — this trick can be applied with the necessary variations to any 
quality you choose. For example, my indifference need be no less 
than that of the most blase person; but at the same time I remain 
towards it extremely ardent, sceptical and its most irreconcilable 
enemy, etc. 

[It should] not be forgotten that [the aggregate] complex of all his 
[qualities, the owner] — in which capacity [Saint] Sancho [by reflect- 
ing opposes one particular] quality — is in this [case nothing but 



* [The following passage is crossed out in the manuscript:] All this is in fact merely 
a highflown description of the bourgeois, who controls each of his emotions so that he 
should not sustain any loss, and on the other hand boasts about numerous qualities, 
e.g., philanthropic zeal, towards which he must remain “cold as ice, sceptical and an 
irreconcilable enemy”, in order not to lose himself as owner in his philanthropic zeal 
but to remain the owner of philanthropy. Whereas the bourgeois sacrifices his 
inclinations and desires always for a definite real interest, Saint Max sacrifices the 
quality towards which he adopts the attitude of the “most irreconcilable enemy” for 
the sake of his reflecting ego, his reflection. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



259 



Sancho’s] simple [reflection about this] one quality, [which he has] 
transformed [into his ego by] putting forward, instead of the whole 
[complex, one] merely reflecting [quality and] putting forward 
in opposition to each of his qualities [and to] the series [merely 
the one] quality of reflection, an ego, and himself as the imag- 
ined ego. 

Now he himself gives expression to this hostile attitude to himself, 
this solemn parody of Bentham’s book-keeping 81 of his own interests 
and qualities. 

Page 188: “An interest, no matter towards what end it may be directed, acquires a 
slave in the shape of myself, if I am unable to rid myself of it; it is no longer my 
property, but I am its property. Let us, therefore, accept the directive of criticism that 
we should feel happy only in dissolution.” 

“We!” — Who are “We?” It never occurs to “us” to “accept” 
the “directive of criticism”. — Thus Saint Max, who for the mo- 
ment is under the police surveillance of “criticism”, here demands 
“the same well-being for all”, “equal well-being for all in one 
and the same [respect]”, “the direct tyrannical domination of 
religion ”. 

His interestedness in the extraordinary sense is here revealed as a 
heavenly disinterestedness. 

Incidentally, there is no need here to deal at length with the fact 
that in existing society it does not at all depend on Saint Sancho 
whether an “interest” “acquires a slave in the shape of himself” and 
whether “he is unable to rid himself of it”. The fixation of interests 
through division of labour and class relations is far more obvious 
than the fixation of “desires” and “thoughts”. 

In order to outbid critical criticism, our saint should at least have 
gone as far as the dissolution of dissolution, for otherwise dissolution 
becomes an interest which he cannot get rid of, which in him 
acquires a slave. Dissolution is no longer his property, but he is the 
property of dissolution. Had he wanted to be consistent in the 
example just given, [he should] [have treated his zeal against his] 
own “zeal” as [an “interest”] and [behaved] towards it [as an “irre- 
concilable] enemy”. [But he should have] also considered his [“ice- 
cold” disinterestedness] in relation to his [“ice-cold” zeal] and beco- 
me [just as wholly “ice-cold”] — and thereby, [obviously, he would 
have spared] his original [“interest”] and hence himself the “tempta- 
tion” to turn [in a circle] on the [heel] of speculation. — Instead, he 
cheerfully continues (ibid.): 

“I shall only take care to safeguard my own property for myself” (i.e., to safeguard 
myself from my property) “and, in order to safeguard it, I take it back into myself at 




260 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



any time, I destroy in it any inclination towards independence and absorb it before it 
becomes fixed and can become a fixed idea or passion.” 

How does Stirner “absorb” the persons who are his property! 

Stirner has just allowed himself to be given a “vocation” by 
“criticism”. He asserts that he at once absorbs this “vocation” again, 
by saying on page 189: 



“I do this, however, not for the sake of my human vocation, but because 1 call on 
myself to do so.” 

If I do not call on myself to do so, I am, as we have just heard, a 
slave, not an owner, not a true egoist, I do not behave to myself as 
creator, as I should do as a true egoist; therefore, insofar as a person 
wants to be a true egoist, he must call himself to this vocation given 
him by “criticism”. Thus, it is a universal vocation, a vocation for all, 
not merely his vocation, but also his vocation. 

On the other hand, the true egoist appears here as an ideal which 
is unattainable by the majority of individuals, for (p. 434) “innately 
limited intellects unquestionably form the most numerous class of 
mankind” — and how could these “limited intellects” be able to 
penetrate the mystery of unlimited absorption of oneself and the 
world. 

Incidentally, all these terrible expressions — to destroy, to absorb 
etc. — are merely a new variation of the above-mentioned “ice-cold, 
most irreconcilable enemy”. 

Now, at last, we are put in a position to obtain an insight into 
Stirner’s objections to communism. They were nothing but a 
preliminary, concealed legitimisation of his egoism in agreement 
with itself, in which these objections are resurrected in the flesh. The 
“ equal well-being of all in one and the same respect ” is resurrected in the 
demand that “we should [only] feel happv in [dissolution”. “Care ]” is 
resurrected [in the form of the unique “care]” to secure [one's ego] 
[as one’s property]; [but “with the passage of time]” [“care”] again 
arises as to “how” [one can arrive] at a [unity — ] viz., unity [of creator 
and creation.] And, finally, humanism re[-appears, which in the 
form of the true] egoist confronts empirical individuals as an 
unattainable ideal. Hence page 117 of “the book” should read as 
follows: Egoism in agreement with itself really endeavours to 
transform every man into a “secret police state”. The spy and sleuth 
“reflection” keeps a strict eye on every impulse of spirit and body, 
and every deed and thought, every manifestation of life is, for him, a 
matter of reflection, i.e., a police matter. It is this dismemberment of 
man into “natural instinct” and “reflection” (the inner plebeian — 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



261 



creation, and the internal police — creator) which constitutes the 
egoist in agreement with himself.* 

Hess ( Die letzten Philosophen, p. 26) reproached our saint: 

“He is constantly under the secret police surveillance of his critical conscience .... 
He has not forgotten the ‘directive of criticism ... to feel happy only in dissolution’.... 
The egoist — his critical conscience is always reminding him — should never become so 
interested in anything as to devote himself entirely to his subject”, and so on. 

Saint Max “empowers himself” to answer as follows: 

When “Hess says of Stirner that he is constantly, etc’ — what does this mean except 
that when he criticises he wants to criticise not at random” (i.e., by the way: in the 
unique fashion), “not talking twaddle, but criticising properly” (i.e., like a human 
being)? 

“What it means”, when Hess speaks of the secret police, etc., is so 
clear from the passage by Hess quoted above that even Saint Max’s 
“unique” understanding of it can only be explained as a deliberate 
misunderstanding. His “virtuositv of thought” is transformed here 
into a virtuosity in lying, for which we do not reproach him since it 
was his only way out, but which is hardly in keeping with the subtle 
little distinctions on the right to lie which he sets out elsewhere in 
“the book”. Incidentally, we have already demonstrated — at greater 
length than he deserves — that “when he criticises”, Sancho by no 
means “criticises properly”, but “criticises at random” and “talks 
twaddle”. 

Thus, the attitude of the true egoist as creator towards himself as 
creation was first of all defined in the sense that in opposition to a 
definition in which he became fixed as a creation — for example, as 
against himself as thinker, as spirit — he asserts himself as a person 
also-otherwise-determined, as flesh. Later, he no longer asserts 
himself as really also-otherwise-determined, but as the mere idea of 
being also-otherwise-determined in general — hence, in the above 
example as someone who also-does-not think, who is thoughtless or 
indifferent to thought, an idea which he abandons again as soon as 
its nonsensicalness becomes evident. See above on turning round on 
the heel of speculation. 3 Hence the creative activity consisted here in 
the reflection that this single determination, in the present case 
thought, could also be indifferent for him, i.e., it consisted in 
reflecting in general; as a result, of course, he creates only reflective 

* [The following passage is crossed out in the manuscript:] Incidentally, if Saint 
Max makes “a Prussian officer of high rank” say: “Every Prussian carries his 
gendarme in his heart”, it ought to read: the king’s gendarme, for only the “egoist in 
agreement with himself” carries hh own gendarme in his heart. 



See this volume, p. 259 . — Ed. 




262 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



definitions, if he creates anything at all (e.g., the idea of antithesis, 
the simple essence of which is concealed by all kinds of fiery 
arabesques). 

As for the content of himself as a creation, we have seen that 
nowhere does he create this content, these definite qualities, e.g., his 
thought, his zeal, etc., but only the reflective definition of this 
content as creation, the idea that these definite qualities are his 
creations. All his qualities are present in him and whence they come 
is all the same to him. He, therefore, needs neither to develop 
them — for example, to learn to dance, in order to have mastery over 
his feet, or to exercise his thought on material which is not given to 
everyone, and is not procurable by everyone, in order to become the 
owner of his thought — nor does he need to worry about the 
conditions in the world, which in reality determine the extent to 
which an individual can develop. 

Stirner actually only rids himself of one quality by means of 
another (i.e., the suppression of his remaining qualities by this 
“other”). In reality, however, [as we] have [already shown,] he does 
this only insofar as this quality has not only achieved free 
development, i.e., has not remained merely potential, but also 
insofar as conditions in the world have permitted him to develop in 
an equal measure a totality of qualities, [that is to say,] thanks to the 
division of [labour,] 3 thus making possible the [predominant pursuit] 
of a [single passion, e.]g., that of [writing] books. [In general], it is an 
[absurdity to assume], as Saint [Max does], that one could satisfy one 
[passion], apart from all others, that one could satisfy it without at 
the same time satisfying oneself, the entire living individual. If this 
passion assumes an abstract, isolated character, if it confronts me as 
an alien power, if, therefore, the satisfaction of the individual 
appears as the one-sided satisfaction of a single passion — this by no 
means depends on consciousness or “good will” and least of all on 
lack of reflection on the concept of this quality, as Saint Max 
imagines. 

It depends not on consciousness, but on being; not on thought, but 
on life; it depends on the individual’s empirical development and 
manifestation of life, which in turn depends on the conditions 
obtaining in the world. If the circumstances in which the individual 
lives allow him only the [one]-sided development of one quality at the 
expense of all the rest, [if] they give him the material and time to 
develop only that one quality, then this individual achieves only a 
one-sided, crippled development. No moral preaching avails here. 



See this volume, pp. 254-5 5~Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



263 



And the manner in which this one, pre-eminently favoured quality 
develops depends again, on the one hand, on the material available 
for its development and, on the other hand, on the degree and 
manner in which the other qualities are suppressed. Precisely 
because thought, for example, is the thought of a particular, definite 
individual, it remains his definite thought, determined by his 
individuality and the conditions in which he lives. The thinking 
individual therefore has no need to resort to prolonged reflection 
about thought as such in order to declare that his thought is his own 
thought, his property; from the outset it is his own, peculiarly 
determined thought and it was precisely his peculiarity which [in 
the case of Saint] Sancho [was found to be] the “opposite” of 
this, a peculiarity which is peculiarity “as such”. In the case of an 
individual, for example, whose life embraces a wide circle of varied 
activities and practical relations to the world, and who, there- 
fore, lives a many-sided life, thought has the same character 
of universality as every other manifestation of his life. Conse- 
quently, it neither becomes fixed in the form of abstract thought 
nor does it need complicated tricks of reflection when the 
individual passes from thought to some other manifestation of 
life. From the outset it is always a factor in the total life of 
the individual, one which disappears and is reproduced as 
required. 

In the case of a parochial Berlin school-master or author, however, 
whose activity is restricted to arduous work on the one hand and the 
pleasure of thought on the other, whose world extends from Moabit 
to Kopenick and ends behind the Hamburger Tor , 82 whose relations 
to this world are reduced to a minimum by his pitiful position in life, 
when such an individual experiences the need to think, it is indeed 
inevitable that his thought becomes just as abstract as he himself and 
his life, and that thought confronts him, who is quite incapable of 
resistance, in the form of a fixed power, whose activity offers the 
individual the possibility of a momentary escape from his “bad 
world”, of a momentary pleasure. In the case of such an individual 
the few remaining desires, which arise not so much from intercourse 
with the world as from the constitution of the human body, express 
themselves only through repercussion , i.e., they assume in their 
narrow development the same one-sided and crude character as does 
his thought, they appear only at long intervals, stimulated by the 
excessive development of the predominant desire (fortified by 
immediate physical causes, e.g. [stomach] spasm) and are manifested 
turbulently and forcibly, with the most brutal suppression of the 




264 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engel: 



ordinary, [natural] desire [ — this leads to further] domination over 
[thought.] As a matter of course, the school-master’s [thinking 
reflects on and speculates about] this empirical [fact in a school- 
masterly fashion. [But the mere announcement] that Stirner in 
general “creates” [his qualities] .does not [explain] even their 
particular form of development. The extent to which these qualities 
develop on the universal or local scale, the extent to which they 
transcend local narrow-mindedness or remain within its confines, 
depends not on Stirner, but on the development of world 
intercourse and on the part which he and the locality where he lives 
play in it. That under favourable circumstances some individuals 
are able to rid themselves of their local narrow-mindedness is 
by no means due to individuals imagining that they have got 
rid of, or intend to get rid of their local narrow-mindedness, but is 
only due to the fact that in their real empirical life individuals, 
actuated by empirical needs, have been able to bring about world 
intercourse.* 

The only thing our saint achieves with the aid of his arduous 
reflection about his qualities and passions is that by his constant 
crotchetiness and scuffling with them he poisons the enjoyment and 
satisfaction of them. 

Saint Max creates, as already said, only himself as a creation, i.e., 
he is satisfied with placing himself in this category of created entity. 
His activity [as] creator consists in regarding himself as a creation, 
and he does not even go on to resolve this division of himself into 
[creator and] creation, which is his own [product]. The division [into 
the “essential” and] the “inessential” becomes [for him a] permanent 
life process, [hence mere appearance,] i.e., his real life exists only [in 
“pure”] reflection, is [not] even actual existence; [for since this latter 
is at every] instant outside [him and his reflection], he tries [in vain 
to] present [reflection as] essential. 



“But [since] this enemy” (viz., the true egoist as a creation) “begets himself in his 
defeat, since consciousness, by becoming fixed on him, does not free itself from him, 
but instead always dwells on him and always sees itself besmirched, and since this 

* [The following passage is crossed out in the manuscript:] This specifically 
revolutionary attitude of the communists to the hitherto existing conditions of the life 
of the individuals has already been described above [see this volume, pp. 246, 255], In 
a later profane passage Saint Max admits that the ego receives an “impulse” (in Fich- 
te’s sense) from the world. That the communists intend to gain control over this 
“impulse” — which indeed becomes an extremely complex and multifariously deter- 
mined “impulse” if one is not content with the mere phrase — is, of course, for 
Saint Max much too daring an idea to discuss. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



265 



content of his endeavour is at the same time the very lowest, we find only an individual 
restricted to himself and his petty activity” (inactivity), “and brooding over himself, as 
unhappy as he is wretched" (Hegel)*. 

What we have said so far about the division of Sancho into creator 
and creation, he himself now finally expresses in a logical form: the 
creator and the creation are transformed into the presupposing and 
the presupposed ego, or (inasmuch as his presupposition [of his ego] 
is a positing) into the positing and the posited ego: 

“I for my part start from a certain presupposition since I presuppose myself; but my 
presupposition does not strive for its perfection” (rather does Saint Max strive for its 
abasement), “on the contrary, it serves me merely as something to enjoy and 
consume” tan enviable enjoyment!). “I am nourished by my presupposition alone and 
exist only bv consuming it. But for that reason” (a grand “for that reason”!) “the 
presupposition in question is no presupposition at all, for since" (a grand “for since”!) 
“I am the unique” (it should read: the true egoist in agreement with himself), “I know 
nothing about the duality of a presupposing and presupposed ego (of an ‘imperfect’ 
and perfect’ ego or man)” — it should read: the perfection of my ego consists in this 
alone, that at every instant I know myself as an imperfect ego, as a creation — "but" (a 
magnificent “but”!) “the fact that I consume myself signifies merely that I am.” (It 
should read: The fact that I am signifies here merely that in me I consume in 
imagination the category of the presupposed.) “I do not presuppose myself, because I 
really only posit or create myself perpetually” (viz., I posit and create myself as the 
presupposed, posited or created) “and I am I only because 1 am not presupposed, but 
posited” (it should read: and I exist onlv because I am antecedent to my positing) 
“and, again, I am posited only at the moment when I posit myself, i.e., I am creator 
and creation in one.” 

Stirner is a “posited man”; since he is always a posited ego, and his 
ego is “ also a man' ( Wigand , p. 183). “For that reason" he is a posited 
man; “ for since” he is never driven by his passions to excesses, 
“therefore" , he is what burghers call a sedate man, “but" the fact that 
he is a sedate man “signifies merely” that he always keeps an account 
of his own transformations and refractions. 

What was so far only “for us” — to use for once, as Stirner does, the 
ianguage of Hegei — viz., that his whole creative activity had no other 
content than general definitions of reflection, is now “posited” by 
Stirner himself. Saint Max’s struggle against “ essence ” here attains its 
“final goal” in that he identifies himself with essence, and indeed 
with pure, speculative essence. The relation of creator and creation is 
transformed into an explication of self -presupposition, i.e., [Stirner 
transforms] into an extremely “clumsy” and confused [idea] what 
Hegel [says] about reflection in “the [Doctrine of Essence]”. [Since] 

a G.W.F. Hegel, Phanomenologie des Geistes. B. Selbstbewusstsein. 3. Das ungliick- 
liche Bewusstsein. — Ed. 

b In the German original this is a pun: gesetzter Mann can mean “sedate man” or 
“posited man”. — Ed. 




266 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



Saint Max takes out one [element of his] reflection, [viz., positing 
reflection, his fantasies become] “negative”, [because he] transforms 
himself, etc., into “self-[presupposition”, in] contradistinction to 
[himself as the positing] and himself as the posited, [and] transforms 
reflection into the mystical antithesis of creator and creation. It 
should be pointed out, by the way, that in this section of his Logik 
Hegel analyses the “machinations” of the “creative nothing”, which 
explains also why Saint Max already on page 8 had to “posit” himself 
as this “creative nothing”. 

We shall now “episodically insert” a few passages from Hegel’s 
explanation of self-presupposition for comparison with Saint Max’s 
explanation. But as Hegel does not write so incoherently and “at 
random” as our Jacques le bonhomme, we shall have to collect these 
passages from various pages of the Logik in order to bring them into 
correspondence with Sancho’s great thesis. 

“Essence presupposes itself and is itself the transcendence of this presupposition. 
Since it is the repulsion of itself from itself or indifference towards itself, negative 
relation to itself, it thereby posits itself against itself ... positing has no presupposition 
... the other is only posited through essence itself... Thus, reflection is only the 
negative of itself. Reflection in so far as it presupposes is simply positing reflection. It 
consists therefore in this, that it is itself and' not itself in a unity" (“creator and 
creation in one”) (Hegel, Logik, II, pp. 5, 16, 17, 18, 22). 

One might have expected from Stirner’s “virtuosity of thought” 
that he would have gone on to further researches into Hegel’s Logik. 
However, he wisely refrained from doing so. For, if he had done so, 
he would have found that he, as mere “posited” ego, as creation, i.e., 
insofar as he possesses existence, is merely a seeming ego, and he is 
“ essence ”, creator, only insofar as he does not exist, but only imagines 
himself. We have already seen, and shall see again further on, that 
all his qualities, his whole activity, and his whole attitude to the 
world, are a mere appearance which he creates for himself, 
nothing but “juggling tricks on the tightrope of the objective”. His 
ego is always a dumb, hidden “ego”, hidden in his ego imagined as 
essence. 

Since the true egoist in his creative activity is, therefore, only a 
paraphrase of speculative reflection or pure essence, it follows, 
“according to the myth”, “by natural reproduction”, as was already 
revealed when examining the “arduous life battles” of the true 
egoist, that his “creations” are limited to the simplest determinations 
of reflection, such as identity, difference, equality, inequality, 
[opposition,] etc. — determinations [of reflection] which he [tries] to 
make clear for himself in [“himself”], concerning whom “the tidings 
have [gone] as far as [Berlin]”. [Concerning] his presuppositionless 





fd'utrt' 

foU 7 ^'CjfoUlyS , 

/^>& 



Max Stirner 

Drawing by Engels 

(The inscription in German reads: “Max Stirner. 

Drawn from memory by Frederick Engels. London, 1892 ”.) 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



269 



[ego] we [shall] have occasion to “hear [a little] word” later on. See, 
inter alia, “The Unique”. 3 

As in Sancho’s construction of history the later historical phenome- 
non is transformed, by Hegel’s method, into the cause, the creator, 
of an earlier phenomenon, so in the case of the egoist in agreement 
with himself the Stirner of today is transformed into the creator of 
the Stirner of yesterday, although, to use his language, the Stirner of 
today is the creation of the Stirner of yesterday. Reflection, indeed, 
reverses all this, and in reflection the Stirner of yesterday is the 
creation of the Stirner of today, as a product of reflection, as an 
idea — just as in reflection the conditions of the external world are 
creations of his reflection. 

Page 216: “Do not seek in ‘self-denial’ the freedom that actually deprives you of 
yourselves, but seek yourselves’’ (i.e., seek yourselves in self-denial), “ become egoists , 
each of you should become an all-powerful ego!” 

After the foregoing, we should not be surprised if later on Saint 
Max’s attitude to this proposition is again that of creator and most 
irreconcilable enemy and he “dissolves” his lofty moral postulate: 
“Become an all-powerful ego” into this, that each, in any case, does 
what he can, and that he can do what he does, and therefore, of 
course, for Saint Max, he is “all-powerful”. 

Incidentally, the nonsense of the egoist in agreement with himself 
is summarised in the proposition quoted above. First comes the 
moral injunction to seek and, moreover, to seek oneself. This is 
defined in the sense that man should become something that he so 
far is not, namely, an egoist, and this egoist is defined as being an 
“all-powerful ego”, in whom the peculiar ability has become resolved 
from actual ability into the ego, into omnipotence, into the fantastic 
idea of ability. To seek oneself means, therefore, to become 
something different from what one is and, indeed, to become 
all-powerful, i.e., nothing, a non-thing, a phantasmagoria. 



We have now progressed so far that one of the profoundest 
mysteries of the unique, and at the same time a problem that has 
long kept the civilised world in a state of anxious suspense, can be 
disclosed and solved. 

Who is Szeliga? Since the appearance of the critical Literatur- 
Zeitung (see Die heilige Familie, etc.) this question has been put by 



3 See this volume, p. 433. — Ed. 




270 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



everyone who has followed the development of German philosophy. 
Who is Szeliga? Everyone asks, everyone listens attentively when he 
hears the barbaric sound of this name — but no one replies. 

Who is Szeliga? Saint Max gives us the key to this “secret of 
secrets” . 

Szeliga is Stirner as a creation, Stirner is Szeliga as creator. Stirner is 
the “I”, Szeliga the “you”, in “the book”. Hence Stirner, the creator, 
behaves towards Szeliga, his creation, as towards his “most 
irreconcilable enemy”. As soon as Szeliga wishes to acquire inde- 
pendence in relation to Stirner — he made a hapless attempt in 
this direction in the Norddeutsche Blatter a — Saint Max “takes him back 
into himself”, an experiment which was carried out against this 
attempt of Szeliga’s on pages 176-79 of the “Apologetic Commen- 
tary” in Wigand. The struggle of the creator against the creation, of 
Stirner against Szeliga, is, however, only a seeming one: [Now] 
Szeliga advances against his creator the phrases of this [creator 
himself] — for example, the assertion “that [the mere,] bare body is 
[absence of] thought” ( Wigand , p. 148). Saint [Max,] as we have seen, 
[was thinking] only of [the bare flesh], the body before its 
[formation], and in [this connection] he gave the body the 
[determination] of being “the other of thought”, non-thought and 
the non-thinking being, hence absence of thought; and indeed in a 
later passage he bluntly declares that only absence of thought (as 
previously only the flesh — thus the two concepts are treated as 
identical) saves him from thoughts (p. 196). 

We find a still more striking proof of this mysterious connection in 
Wigand. We have already seen on page 7 of “the book” that the 
“ego”, i.e., Stirner, is “the unique”. On page 153 of the 
“Commentary” he addresses his “you”: “You” ... “are the content of 
the phrase” , viz., the content of the “unique”, and on the same page it 
is stated: “he overlooks the fact that he himself, Szeliga, is the content of 
the phrase” . “The unique” is a phrase, as Saint Max says in so many 
words. Considered as the “ ego ”, i.e., as creator, he is the owner of the 
phrase — this is Saint Max. Considered as “you” , i.e., as creation, he is 
the content of the phrase — this is Szeliga, as we have just been told. 
Szeliga the creation appears as a selfless egoist, as a degenerate Don 
Quixote; Stirner the creator appears as an egoist in the ordinary 
sense, as Saint Sancho Panza. 

Here, therefore, the other aspect of the antithesis of creator and 
creation makes its appearance, each of the two aspects containing its 
opposite in itself. Here Sancho Panza Stirner, the egoist in the 

Szeliga, “Der Einzige und sein Eigenthum, Von Max Stirner”. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



271 



ordinary sense, is victorious over Don Quixote Szeliga, the selfless 
and illusory egoist, is victorious over him precisely as Don Quixote by 
his faith in the world domination of the holy. Who indeed was 
Stirner’s egoist in the [ordinary] sense if not Sancho [Panza,] and 
who his self-sacrificing egoist [if not] Don Quixote, and what was 
[their mutual] relation in the [form in which it has so far existed if] 
not the relation of [Sancho Panza Stirner] to Don Quixote [Szeliga? 
Now as] Sancho Panza [Stirner belongs to himself as] Sancho only [in 
order to make Szeliga as] Don Quixote [believe that] he surpasses 
him in Don [quixotry,] and [in accordance with this role, as] the 
presupposed universal Don [quixotry,] he takes [no steps] against the 
[Don quixotry of his] former master (Don quixotry, by which he 
swears with all the firm faith of a servant), and at the same time he 
displays the cunning already described by Cervantes. In actual 
content he 4 is, therefore, the defender of the practical petty 
bourgeois, but he combats the consciousness that corresponds to the 
petty bourgeois, a consciousness which in the final analysis reduces 
itself to the idealising ideas of the petty bourgeois about the 
bourgeoisie to whom he cannot attain. 

Thus, Don Quixote now, as Szeliga, performs mental services for 
his former armour-bearer. 

How greatly Sancho in his new “transformation” has retained his 
old habits, he shows on every page. “Swallowing” and “consuming” 
still constitute one of his chief qualities, his “natural timidity” has still 
such mastery over him that the King of Prussia and Prince Heinrich 
LXXII become transformed for him into the “Emperor of China” or 

the “Sultan” and he ventures to speak only about the “G a 

chambers”; he still strews around him proverbs and moral sayings 
from his knapsack, he continues to be afraid of “spectres” and even 
asserts that they alone are to be feared; the only difference is that 
whereas Sancho in his unholiness was bamboozled by the peasants in 
the tavern, now in a state of saintliness he continually bamboozles 
himself. 

But let us return to Szeliga. Who has not long ago discovered the 
hand of Szeliga in all the “phrases” which Saint Sancho put into the 
mouth of his “you”? And it is always possible to discover traces of 
Szeliga not only in the phrases of this “you”, but also in the phrases 
in which Szeliga appears as creator, i.e., as Stirner. But because 
Szeliga is a creation, he could only figure in Die heilige Familie as a 
“mystery ” . The revelation of this mystery was the task of Stirner the 
creator. We surmised, of course, that some great, holy adventure was 



German. — Ed. 




272 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



at the root of this. Nor were we deceived. The unique adventure 
really has never been seen or heard of and surpasses the adventure 
with the fulling mills in Cervantes’ twentieth chapter. 

3. The Revelation of John the Divine, 
or ( ‘The Logic of the New Wisdom ” 

In the beginning was the word, the logos. In it was life, and the life 
was the light of men. And the light shone in darkness and the 
darkness did not comprehend it. That was the true light, it was in the 
world, and the w'orld did not know it. He came into his own, and his 
own received him not. But as many as received him, to them gave he 
power to become owners, who believe in the name of the unique. 
[But who] has ever [seen] the unique [?] a 

[Let] us now [examine] this “light of the [world’’ in “the] logic of 
the new wisdom [”, for Saint] Sancho does not rest content with his 
previous [destructions]. 

[In the case of our] “unique” author, it is a matter [of course that] 
the basis of his [genius lies] in the brilliant [series of personal] 
advantages [which constitute] his special [virtuosity] of thought. 
[Since] all these advantages have already been extensively demon- 
strated, it suffices here to give a brief summary of the most 
important of them: carelessness of thought — confusion — incoher- 
ence — admitted clumsiness — endless repetitions — constant con- 
tradiction with himself — unequalled comparisons — attempts to in- 
timidate the reader — systematic legacy-hunting in the realm of 
thoughts by means of the levers “you”, “it”, “one”, etc., and crude 
abuse of the conjunctions for, therefore, for that reason, because, 
accordingly, but, etc. — ignorance — clumsv assertions — solemn frivol- 
ity — revolutionary phrases and peaceful thoughts — biuster — bom- 
bastic vulgarity and coquetting with cheap indecency — elevation of 
Nante the loafer 83 to the rank of an absolute concept — dependence 
on Hegelian traditions and current Berlin phrases — in short, sheer 
manufacture of a thin beggar’s broth (491 pages of it) in the 
Rumford manner. 

Drifting like bones in this beggar’s broth are a whole series of 
transitions, a few specimens of which we shall now' give for the 
amusement of the German public depressed as it is: 

“Could we not — now, however — one sometimes shares — one can then — to the 
efficacy of ... belongs especially that which one frequently ... hears called — and that is 
to say — to conclude, it can now be clear — in the meantime — thus it can, incidentally, be 

a John 1:1, 4-5, 9-12, 18 (paraphrased). — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



273 



thought here — were it not for — or if, perhaps, it were not — progress from ... to the 
point that ... is not difficult — from a certain point of view it is argued approximately 
thus — for example, and so on ”, etc., and “it is to that” in all possible “transformations”. 

We can at once mention here a [logical] trick about which [it is 
impossible] to decide whether it owes [its] existence to the [lauded] 
efficiency of Sancho [or to] the inefficiency of his [thinking]. This 
[trick consists] in seizing on [one aspect], treating it as if it were the 
sole [and only] aspect so far known of an idea [or] concept which [has 
several well]-defined aspects, foisting this aspect [on the concept as] 
its sole characteristic and then setting [against it every other] aspect 
under a [new name, as] something original. This is how the concepts 
of freedom and peculiarity are dealt with, [as] we shall see later. 3 

Among the categories which owe their origin not so much to the 
personality of Sancho, as to the universal distress in which the 
German theoreticians find themselves at the present time, the first 
place is taken by trashy distinction, the extreme of trashiness. Since 
our saint immerses himself in such “soul-torturing” antitheses as 
singular and universal, private interest and universal interest, 
ordinary egoism and selflessness, etc., in the final analysis one arrives 
at the trashiest mutual concessions and dealings between the two 
aspects, which again rest on the most subtle distinctions — distinctions 
whose existence side by side is expressed by “ also ” and whose 
separation from each other is then maintained by means of a 
miserable “ insofar as”. Such trashy distinctions, for instance, are: 
how people exploit one another, but none does so at the expense of 
another, the extent to which something in me is inherent or suggested; 
the construction of human and of unique work, existing side by side, 
what is indispensable for human life and what is indispensable for 
unique life; what belongs to personality in its pure form and what is 
essentially fortuitous, to decide which Saint Max, from his point of 
view, has no criterion at all; what belongs to the rags and tatters and 
what to the skin of the individual; what by means of denial he gets rid 
of altogether or appropriates, to what extent he sacrifices merely his 
freedom or merely his peculiarity, in which case he also makes a 
sacrifice but only insofar as, properly speaking, he does not make a 
sacrifice; what brings me into relation with others as a link or as a 
personal relation. Some of these distinctions are absolutely trashy, 
others — in the case of Sancho at least — lose all meaning and 
foundation. One can regard as the peak of these trashy distinctions 
that between the creation of the worldby the individual and the impulse 
which the individual receives from the world. If, for example, he had 

3 See this volume, pp. 305-09. — Ed. 




274 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



gone more deeply here into this impulse, into the whole extent and 
multifarious character of its influence on him, he would in the end 
have discovered the contradiction that he is as blindly [dependent] on 
the world as he [egoistically] and ideologically creates [it]. (See: “My 
Self-Enjoyment” a .) He [would not then have put] side by side [his“] 
also” and “insofar as ”, [any more than] “human” work [and] 
“unique” work; he would not have opposed one to the other, 
therefore one would [not have] attacked the other [in the rear,] and 
the “egoist in agreement [with himself”] would not be completely 
[subordinated to himself] — but we [know] that the latter did not need 
to be [presupposed] because from the outset this was the point of 
departure. 

This trashy play with distinctions occurs throughout “the book”; it 
is a main lever also for the other logical tricks and particularly takes 
the form of a moral casuistry that is as self-satisfied as it is 
ridiculously cheap. Thus, it is made clear to us by means of examples 
how far the true egoist has the right to tell lies and how far he has 
not; to what extent the betrayal of confidence is “despicable” and to 
what extent it is not; to what extent the Emperor Sigismund and the 
French King Francis I had the right to break their oath 84 and how far 
their behaviour in this respect was “disgraceful”, and other subtle 
historical illustrations of the same sort. Against these painstaking 
distinctions and petty questions there stands out in strong relief the 
indifference of our Sancho for whom it is all the same and who 
ignores all actual, practical and conceptual differences. In general we 
can already say now that his ability to distinguish is far inferior to his 
ability not to distinguish, to regard all cats as black in the darkness of 
the holy, and to reduce everything to anything — an art which finds 
its adequate expression in the use of the apposition. 

Embrace your “ass”, Sancho, you have found him again here. He 
gallops merrily to meet you, taking no notice of the kicks he has been 
given, and greets you with his ringing voice. Kneel before him, 
embrace his neck and fulfil the calling laid down for you by 
Cervantes in Chapter XXX. 

The apposition is Saint Sancho’s ass, his logical and historical 
locomotive, the driving force of “the book”, reduced to its briefest 
and simplest expression. In order to transform one idea into 
another, or to prove the identity of two quite different things, a few 
intermediate links are sought which partly by their meaning, partly 
by their etymology and partly by their mere sound can be used to 
establish an apparent connection between the two basic ideas. These 
links are then appended to the first idea in the form of an apposition, 

a See this volume, p. 422. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



275 



and in such a way that one gets farther and farther away from the 
starting-point and nearer and nearer to the point one wants to reach. 
If the chain of appositions has got so far that one can draw a 
conclusion without any danger, the final idea is likewise fastened on 
in the form of an apposition by means of a dash, and the trick is 
done. This is a highly recommendable method of insinuating 
thoughts, which is the more effective the more it is made to serve as 
the lever for the main arguments. When this trick has been 
successfully performed several times, one can, following Saint 
Sancho’s procedure, gradually omit some of the intermediate links 
and finally reduce the series of appositions to a few absolutely 
essential hooks. 

The apposition, as we have seen above, can also be reversed and 
thus lead to new, even more complicated tricks and more astounding 
results. We have seen there, too, that the apposition is the logical 
form of the infinite series of mathematics. 3 

Saint Sancho employs the apposition in two ways: on the one hand, 
purely logically, in the canonisation of the world, where it enables 
him to transform any earthly thing into “the holy”, and, on the 
other hand, historically, in disquisitions on the connection of various 
epochs and in summing them up, each historical stage being reduced 
to a single word, and the final result is that the last link of the 
historical series has not got us an inch farther than the first, and in 
the end all the epochs of the series are combined in a single abstract 
category like idealism, dependence on thoughts, etc. If the historical 
series of appositions is to be given the appearance of progress, this is 
achieved by regarding the concluding phrase as the completion of 
the first epoch of the series, and the intermediate links as ascending 
stages of development leading to the final, culminating phrase. 

Alongside the apposition we have synonymy, which Saint Sancho 
exploits in every way. If two words are etymologically linked or are 
merely similar in sound, they are made responsible for each other, or 
if one word has different meanings, then, according to need, it is 
used sometimes in one sense and sometimes in the other, while Saint 
Sancho makes it appear that he is speaking of one and the same thing 
in different “refractions”. Further, a special branch of synonymy 
consists of translation, where a French or Latin expression is 
supplemented by a German one which only half-expresses it, and in 
addition denotes something totally different; as we saw above, for 
example, when the word “ respektieren” was translated “to experience 
reverence and fear”, and so on. One recalls the words Staat, Status, 



a See this volume, p. 156. — Ed. 




276 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



Stand, Notstand, etc. a In the section on communism we have already 
had the opportunity of observing numerous examples of this use of 
ambiguous expressions. Let us briefly examine an example of 
etymological synonymy. 

“The word ‘ Gesellschaf t’ b is derived from the word ‘Sal’. If there are many people 
in a Saal, c then the Saal brings it about that thev are in society. They are in society 
and they constitute at most a salon society, since they talk in conventional salon phrases. 
If real intercourse takes place, it should be regarded as independent of society” (p. 286). 

Since the “word ‘ Gesellschaf f is derived from ‘SaF” (which, 
incidentally, is not true, for the original roots of all words are verbs) 
then “Sat” must be equivalent to “Saal”. But “SaG in old 
High-German means a building; Kisello, Geselle — from which 
Gesellschaft is derived — means a house companion; hence “Saa /” is 
dragged in here quite arbitrarily. But that does not matter; “ Saal” is 
immediately transformed into “salon”, as though there was not a gap 
of about a thousand years and a great many miles between the old 
High-German “SaG and the modern French “salon”. Thus society is 
transformed into a salon society, in which, according to the German 
philistine idea, an intercourse consisting only of phrases takes place 
and all real intercourse is excluded. — Incidentally since Saint Max 
only aimed at transforming society into “the holy”, he could have 
arrived at this by a much shorter route if he had made a somewhat 
more accurate study of etymology and consulted any dictionary of 
word roots. What a find it would have been for him to discover there 
the etymological connection between the words “ Gesellschaft ” and 
“ selig ”; Gesellschaft — selig — heilig — das Heilige d — what could look 
simpler? 

If “Stirner’s” etymological synonymy is correct, then the commu- 
nists are seeking the true earldom, the earldom as the holy. As 
Gesellschaft comes from Sal, a building, so Graf (Gothic garavjo ) 
comes from the Gothic ravo, house. Sal, building =ravo, house; 
consequently Gesellschaf t= Graf schaftf The prefixes and suffixes are 
the same in both words, the root syllables have the same meaning — 
hence the holy society of the communists is the holy earldom, the 
earldom as the holy — what could look simpler? Saint Sancho had an 
inkling of this, when he saw in communism the perfection of the 
feudal system, i.e., the system of earldoms. 

a See this volume, p. 212. — Ed. 
b Society. — Ed. 
c Hall, room. — Ed. 

Society — blessed — holy — the holy. — Ed. 
e Earl. — Ed. 

{ Earldom. — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



277 



Synonymy serves our saint, on the one hand, to transform 
empirical relations into speculative relations, by using in its 
speculative meaning a word that occurs both in practical life and in 
philosophical speculation, uttering a few phrases about this specula- 
tive meaning and then making out that he has thereby also criticised 
the actual relations which this word denotes as well. He does this 
with the word speculation. On page 406, “speculation” “appears” 
showing two sides as one essence that possesses a “dual manifesta- 
tion” — O Szeliga! He rages against philosophical speculation and 
thinks he has thereby also settled accounts with commercial specula- 
tion, about [which] he knows nothing. On the other hand, this 
svnonvmy enables him, a concealed petty bourgeois, to transform 
bourgeois relations (see what was said above in dealing with “com- 
munism” about the connection between language and bourgeois re- 
lations 3 ) into personal, individual relations, which one cannot attack 
without attacking the individuality, “peculiarity” and “uniqueness” 
of the individual. Thus, for example, Sancho exploits the etymo- 
logical connection between Geld! 3 and Geltung, c Vermogen d and 
vermogen , e etc. 

Synonymy, combined with the apposition, provides the main lever 
for his conjuring tricks, which we have already exposed on countless 
occasions. To give an example how easy this art is, let us also perform 
a conjuring trick a, la Sancho. 

WechselJ as change, is the law of phenomena, says Hegel, This is the 
reason, “Stirner” could continue, for the phenomenon of the 
strictness of the law against false bills of exchange; for we see here the 
law raised above phenomena, the law as such, holy law, the law as the 
hoiv, the holy itself, against which sin is committed and which is 
avenged in the punishment. Or in other words: Wechsel “in its dual 
manifestation”, as a bill of exchange ( lettre de change) and as change 
( changement ), leads to Verfall 8 (echeance and decadence ). Decline as a 
result of change is observed in history, inter alia, in the fall of the 
Roman Empire, feudalism, the German Empire and the domination 
of Napoleon. The “transition from” these great historical crises “to” 
the commercial crises of our day “is not difficult”, and this explains 
also why these commercial crises are always determined by the expiry 
of bills of exchange. 

d See this volume, p. 231. — Ed. 
b Money. — Ed. 
c Worth, value, validity. — Ed. 

Wealth, property, ability, capability.-; — Ed. 
e To be able, capable. — Ed. 

Change, bill of exchange. — Ed. 

8 Expiry, falling due (of bill); decline, decay. — Ed. 




278 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



Or he could also, as in the case of “ Vermogen ” and “Geld' , justify 
the “ Wechsel” etymologically arid “from a certain point of view argue 
approximately as follows”. The communists want, among other 
things, to abolish the Wechsel (bill of exchange). But does not the 
main pleasure of the world lie precisely in Wechsel (change)? They 
want, therefore, the dead, the immobile, China — that is to say, the 
perfect Chinese is a communist. “Hence” communist declamations 
against Wechselbrieie a and Wechsler. As though every letter were not 
a Wechselbriei, a letter that notes a change, and every man not a 
Wechselnder, a Wechsler. 

To give the simplicity of his construction and logical tricks the 
appearance of great variety, Saint Sancho needs the episode. From 
time to time he “ episodically ” inserts a passage which belongs to 
another part of the book, or which could quite well have been left out 
altogether, and thus still further breaks the thread of his so-called 
argument, which has already been repeatedly broken without that. 
This is accompanied by the naive statement that “we” “do not stick 
to the rules”, and after numerous repetitions causes in the reader a 
certain insensitiveness to even the greatest incoherence. When one 
reads “the book”, one becomes accustomed to everything and finally 
one readily submits even to the worst. Incidentally, these episodes (as 
was only [to be] expected from Saint Sancho) are themselves only 
imaginary and mere repetitions under [other guises] of phrases 
encountered hundreds of times [already]. 

After Saint Max has [thus displayed] his personal qualities, and 
then revealed himself as [“ appearance" and] as “ essence ” in the distin- 
ction, [in] synonymy and in the episode, [we] come [to the] true 
culmination and completion of logic, the “concept”. 

[The] concept is the “ego” (see Hegel’s Logik, Part 3), logic [as the 
ego]. This is the pure relation [of the] ego to the world, a relation 
[divested] of all the real relations that exist for it; [a formula] for 
all the equations to [which the holy] man reduces mundane 
[concepts]. It was already [revealed] above that by applying this 
formula to all sorts of things Sancho merely makes an unsuccessful 
“attempt” to understand the various pure determinations of 
reflection, such as identity, antithesis, etc. 

Let us begin at once with a definite example, e.g., the relation 
between the “ego” and the people. 



* Here and above the authors play on the different meanings of the words Wechsel 
(change, bill of exchange), Wechselbrief (bill of exchange), Wechsler (money-changer) 
and Wechselnder (a changing person). — Ed. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 279 



I am not the people. 

The people = non-I 
I = the non-people. 

Hence, I am the negation of the people, the people is dissolved in 
me. 

The second equation can be expressed also by an auxiliary 
equation: 

The people’s ego is non-existent, 
or: 

The ego of the people is the negation of my ego. 

The whole trick, therefore, consists in: 1) that the negation which 
at the outset belonged to the copula is attached first to the subject 
and then to the predicate; and 2) that the negation, the “not”, is, 
according to convenience, regarded as an expression of dissimilarity, 
difference, antithesis or direct dissolution. In the present example it 
is regarded as absolute dissolution, as complete negation; we shall 
find that — at Saint Max’s convenience — it is used also in the other 
meanings. Thus the tautological proposition that I am not the people 
is transformed into the tremendous new discovery that I am the 
dissolution of the people. 

For the equations given above, it was not even necessary for Saint 
Sancho to have any idea of the people; it was enough for him to 
know that I and the people are “totally different names for totally 
different things”; it was sufficient that the two words do not have a 
single letter in common. If now there is to be further speculation 
about the people from the standpoint of egoistical logic, it suffices to 
attach any kind of trivial determination to the people and to “I” 
from outside, from day-to-day experience, thus giving rise to new 
equations. At the same time it is made to appear that different 
determinations are being criticised in different ways. We shall now 
proceed to speculate in this manner about freedom, happiness and 
wealth : 

Basic equations: The people — non-I. 

Equation No. 1: Freedom of the people = Not my freedom. 

Freedom of the people = My non-freedom. 

Freedom of the people = My lack of freedom. 

(This can also be reversed, resulting in the grand proposition: My 
lack of freedom = slavery is the freedom of the people.) 

Equation No. 2: Happiness of the people = Not my happiness. 

Happiness of the people = My non-happiness. 

Happiness of the people = My unhappiness. 



1 1 —2086 




280 



Karl Marx and Frederick Engels 



(Reversed equation: My unhappiness, my distress, is the happiness 
of the people.) 

Equation No. 3: Wealth of the people = Not my wealth. 

Wealth of the people = My non-wealth. 

Wealth of the people = My poverty. 

(Reversed equation: My poverty is the wealth of the people.) This 
can be continued ad libitum and extended to other determinations. 

For the formation of such equations all that is required, apart from 
a very general acquaintance with such ideas as Stirner can combine in 
one notion with “people”, is to know the positive expression for the 
result obtained in the negative form, e.g., “poverty” — for “non- 
wealth”, etc. That is to say, as much knowledge of the language as 
one acquires in everyday life is quite sufficient to arrive in this way at 
the most surprising discoveries. 

The entire trick here, therefore, consisted in transforming 
not-my-wealth, not-my-happiness, not-my-freedom into my non- 
wealth, my non-happiness, my non-freedom. The “not”, which in 
the first equation is a general negation that can express all possible 
forms of difference, e.g., it may merely mean that it is our common, 
and not exclusively my, wealth — this “not” is transformed in the 
[second] equation into the negation of my wealth, [my] happiness, 
etc., and ascribes to me [non-happiness], unhappiness, slavery. 
[Since] I am denied some definite form of wealth, [the people’s] 
wealth but by no means [wealth] in general, [Sancho believes 
poverty] must be ascribed to me. [But] this is also [brought about] by 
expressing my non-freedom in a positive way and so transforming it 
into my [“lack of freedom”]. But [my non-freedom] can, of course, 
also mean hundreds [of other] things — e.g., my [“lack of freedom]”, 
my non-freedom from [my] body, etc. 

We started out just now from the second equation: the people = 
non-I. We could also have taken the third equation as our starting- 
point: I = the non-people, and then, in the case of wealth for 
example, according to the same method, it would be proved in the 
end that “my wealth is the poverty of the people”. Here, however, 
Saint Sancho would not proceed in this way, but would dissolve 
altogether the property relations of the people and the people itself, 
and then arrive at the following result: my wealth is the destruction 
not only of the people’s wealth but of the people itself. This shows 
how arbitrarily Saint Sancho acted when he transformed non-wealth 
into poverty. Our saint applies these different methods higgledy- 
piggledy and exploits negation sometimes in one meaning and 
sometimes in another. Even “anyone who has not read Stirner’s 
book” “sees at once” ( Wigand , p. 191) what confusions this is liable to 
produce. 




The German Ideology. The Leipzig Council. III. Saint Max 



281 



In just the same way the “ego” “operates” against the state. 

I am not the state. 

State =non-I. 

I = “Negation” of the state. 

Nothing of the state=I. 

Or in other words: I am the ‘‘creative nothing” in which the state is 
swallowed up. 

This simple melody can be used to ring the changes with any 
subject. 

The great proposition that forms the basis of all these equations is: 
I am not non-I. This non-I is given various names, which, on the one 
hand, can be purely logical, e.g., being-in-itself, other-being, or, on 
the other hand, the names of concrete ideas such as the people, state, 
etc. In this way the appearance of a development can be produced by 
taking these names as the starting-point and gradually reducing 
them — with the aid of equations, or a series of appositions — again to 
the non-ego, which was their basis at the outset. Since the real 
relations thus introduced figure only as different modifications of 
the non-ego, and only nominally different modifications at that — no- 
thing at all need be said about these real relations themselves. This is 
all the more ludicrous since [the real] relations are the relations [of 
the individuals] themselves, and declaring them to be relations [of 
the non]-ego only proves that one knows nothing about them. The 
matter is thereby so greatly simplified that even “the great majority 
consisting of innately limited intellects” can learn the trick in ten 
minutes at most. At the same time, this gives us a criterion of the 
“uniqueness” of Saint Sancho. 

Saint* Sancho further defines the non-ego opposed to the ego as 
being that which is alien to the ego, that which is the alien. The 
relation of the non-ego to the ego is “therefore” that of alienation 
[ Entfremdung ]. We have just given the logical formula by which 
Saint Sancho presents any object or relation whatsoever as that which 
is alien to the ego, as the alienation of the ego; on the other hand, 
Saint Sancho can, as we shall see, also present any object or relation 
as something created by the ego and belonging to it Apart, first of all, 
from the arbitrary way in which he presents, or does not present, any 
relation as a relation of alienation (for everything can be made to fit 
in the above equations), we see already here that his only concern is 
to present all actual relations, [and also] actual individuals, [as 
alienated] (to retain this philosophical [expression] for the time 
being), to [transform] them into the wholly [abstract] phrase of 
alienation. Thus [instead] of the task of describing [actual] individu- 
als in their [actual] alienation and in the empirical relations of this